- William of Ockham
-
William of Ockham Full name William of Ockham Born c. 1288
Ockham, EnglandDied 1347 or 1348
Munich, Holy Roman EmpireEra Medieval Philosophy Region Western Philosophers School Scholasticism Main interests Metaphysics, Epistemology, Theology, Logic, Ontology, Politics Notable ideas Occam's Razor, Nominalism Influenced byInfluencedWilliam of Ockham ( /ˈɒkəm/; also Occam, Hockham, or several other spellings; c. 1288 – c. 1348) was an English Franciscan friar and scholastic philosopher, who is believed to have been born in Ockham, a small village in Surrey.[1] He is considered to be one of the major figures of medieval thought and was at the centre of the major intellectual and political controversies of the fourteenth century. Although he is commonly known for Occam's razor, the methodological principle that bears his name, William of Ockham also produced significant works on logic, physics, and theology. In the Church of England, his day of commemoration is 10 April.[2]
Contents
Life
William of Ockham joined the Franciscan order at an early age. It is believed that he studied theology at the University of Oxford from 1309 to 1321, but never completed his master's degree (the usual undergraduate degree in those times).[3] Because of this, he acquired the byname Venerabilis Inceptor, or "Worthy Beginner" (an inceptor was a student formally admitted to the ranks of teachers by the university authorities[4] ). He was also known as the Doctor Invincibilis or "Unconquerable Teacher."
His work in this period became the subject of controversy, and many scholars have thought that Ockham was summoned before the Papal court of Avignon in 1324 under charges of heresy. During the Middle Ages of Europe, theologian Peter Lombard’s Sentences (1150) had become a standard work of theology, and many ambitious theological scholars wrote commentaries on it.[5] William of Ockham was among these scholarly commentators. However, Ockham’s commentary was not well received by his colleagues, or by the church authorities. In 1324, his commentary was condemned as unorthodox by a synod of bishops, and he was ordered to Avignon, France, to defend himself before a papal court.[5] For two years, he was confined to a Franciscan house, until he was condemned as a heretic in 1326.
An alternative theory, recently proposed by George Knysh, suggests that he was initially appointed in Avignon as a professor of philosophy in the Franciscan school, and that his disciplinary difficulties did not begin until 1327.[6] It is generally believed that these charges were levied by Oxford chancellor John Lutterell.[7] It was in this year that the Franciscan Minister General, Michael of Cesena, had been summoned to Avignon, to answer charges of heresy. A theological commission had been asked to review his Commentary on the Sentences, and it was during this that Ockham found himself involved in a different debate. Michael of Cesena had asked Ockham to review arguments surrounding Apostolic poverty. (The most uncompromising Franciscans, known as spirituals, believed that Jesus and his apostles owned no personal property, and survived by begging and accepting the gifts of others[8]). This brought them into conflict with Pope John XXII.
Eventually Ockham was able to escape from Avignon and made his way to Munich where King Louis IV of Bavaria would become his patron.[5] After studying the works of John XXII and previous papal statements, Ockham agreed with the Minister General. In return for protection and patronage Ockham wrote treaties that argued for King Louis to have supreme control over church and state in the Holy Roman Empire.[5] For doing this Ockham was solemnly excommunicated by Pope John XXII.
He believed that John XXII was himself guilty of heresy for refusing to accept the Franciscan claim.[3] Fearing imprisonment and possible execution, Ockham, Michael of Cesena and other Franciscan sympathizers fled Avignon on 26 May 1328, and eventually took refuge in the court of the Holy Roman Emperor Louis IV of Bavaria, who was also engaged in dispute with the papacy. Ockham was excommunicated but his philosophy was never officially condemned.[3]
He spent much of the remainder of his life writing about political issues, including the relative authority and rights of the spiritual and temporal powers. After Michael of Cesena's death in 1342, William became the leader of the small band of Franciscan dissidents living in exile with Louis IV. Ockham died (prior to the outbreak of the plague, or Black Death) either on 10 April 1347[9] or (more likely) on 9 April 1348 in the Franciscan convent at Munich in Bavaria.[10] He was officially rehabilitated by Innocent VI in 1359.
Faith and reason
William of Ockham believed “only faith gives us access to theological truths. The ways of God are not open to reason, for God has freely chosen to create a world and establish a way of salvation within it apart from any necessary laws that human logic or rationality can uncover.” [11] Ockham's theism was based solely on private revelation and faith (he supported some sort of Non-overlapping magisteria). He believed that only science was a matter of discovery and saw God as the only ontological necessity.[12]
Philosophical thought
In scholasticism, Ockham advocated a reform both in method and in content, the aim of which was simplification. Ockham incorporated much of the work of some previous theologians, especially John Duns Scotus. From Scotus, Ockham derived his view of divine omnipotence, his view of grace and justification, much of his epistemology and ethical convictions. However, he also reacted to and against Scotus in the areas of predestination, penance, his understanding of universals, his distinction ex parte rei (that is, "as applied to created things"), and his view of parsimony.
Nominalism
A pioneer of nominalism, some consider him the father of modern epistemology, because of his strongly argued position that only individuals exist, rather than supra-individual universals, essences, or forms, and that universals are the products of abstraction from individuals by the human mind and have no extra-mental existence.[13] He denied the real existence of metaphysical universals and advocated the reduction of ontology. Ockham is sometimes considered an advocate of conceptualism rather than nominalism, for whereas nominalists held that universals were merely names, i.e. words rather than existing realities, conceptualists held that they were mental concepts, i.e. the names were names of concepts, which do exist, although only in the mind. Therefore, the universal concept has for its object, not a reality existing in the world outside us, but an internal representation which is a product of the understanding itself and which "supposes" in the mind the things to which the mind attributes it; that is, it holds, for the time being, the place of the things which it represents. It is the term of the reflective act of the mind. Hence the universal is not a mere word, as Roscelin taught, nor a sermo, as Abelard held, namely the word as used in the sentence, but the mental substitute for real things, and the term of the reflective process. For this reason Ockham has been called a "terminist", to distinguish him from a nominalist or a conceptualist.[14]
Ontological parsimony
One important contribution that he made to modern science and modern intellectual culture was through the principle of parsimony in explanation and theory building that came to be known as Occam's Razor. This maxim, as interpreted by Bertrand Russell,[15] states that if one can explain a phenomenon without assuming this or that hypothetical entity, there is no ground for assuming it, i.e. that one should always opt for an explanation in terms of the fewest possible number of causes, factors, or variables. He turned this into a concern for ontological parsimony; the principle says that one should not multiply entities beyond necessity – Entia non sunt multiplicanda sine necessitate – although this well-known formulation of the principle is not to be found in any of Ockham's extant writings.[16] He formulates it as: “For nothing ought to be posited without a reason given, unless it is self-evident (literally, known through itself) or known by experience or proved by the authority of Sacred Scripture.”[citation needed] For Ockham, the only truly necessary entity is God; everything else is contingent. He thus does not accept the principle of sufficient reason, rejects the distinction between essence and existence, and advocates against the Thomistic doctrine of active and passive intellect. His scepticism to which his ontological parsimony request leads appears in his doctrine that human reason can prove neither the immortality of the soul nor the existence, unity, and infinity of God. These truths, he teaches, are known to us by Revelation alone.
Natural philosophy
Ockham wrote a great deal on natural philosophy, including a long commentary on Aristotle's physics. According to the principle of ontological parsimony, he holds that we do not need to allow entities in all ten of Aristotle's categories; we thus do not need the category of quantity, as the mathematical entities are not "real". Mathematics must be applied to other categories, such as the categories of substance or qualities, thus anticipating modern scientific renaissance while violating Aristotelian prohibition of metabasis.
Theory of knowledge
In the theory of knowledge, Ockham rejected the scholastic theory of species, as unnecessary and not supported by experience, in favour of a theory of abstraction. This was an important development in late medieval epistemology. He also distinguished between intuitive and abstract cognition; intuitive cognition depends on the existence or non existence of the object, whereas abstractive cognition "abstracts" the object from the existence predicate. It is not yet decided among interpreters as to the role of these two types of cognitive activities.
Political theory
Ockham is also increasingly being recognized as an important contributor to the development of Western constitutional ideas, especially those of government with limited responsibility. He was one of the first medieval authors to advocate a form of church/state separation, and was important for the early development of the notion of property rights. His political ideas are regarded as "natural" or "secular", holding for a secular absolutism. The views on monarchical accountability espoused in his Dialogus (written between 1332 and 1348)[17] greatly influenced the Conciliar movement and assisted in the emergence of liberal democratic ideologies.
Logic
In logic, Ockham wrote down in words the formulae that would later be called De Morgan's Laws,[18] and he pondered ternary logic, that is, a logical system with three truth values; a concept that would be taken up again in the mathematical logic of the 19th and 20th centuries.
Literary Ockhamism/Nominalism
Ockham and his works have been discussed as a possible influence on several late medieval literary figures and works, especially Geoffrey Chaucer, but also Jean Molinet, the Gawain Poet, François Rabelais, John Skelton, Julian of Norwich, the York and Townely Plays, and Renaissance romances. Only in very few of these cases is it possible to demonstrate direct links to Ockham or his texts. However, correspondences between Ockhamist and Nominalist philosophy/theology and literary texts from medieval to postmodern times have been discussed within the scholarly paradigm of literary nominalism.[19]
Works
The standard edition of his philosophical and theological works is William of Ockham: Opera philosophica et theologica, Gedeon Gál, et al., eds. 17 vols. St. Bonaventure, N. Y.: The Franciscan Institute, 1967–88. For his political works, all but the Dialogus have been edited in William of Ockham, H. S. Offler, et al., eds. 4 vols., 1940–97, Manchester: Manchester University Press [vols. 1–3]; Oxford: Oxford University Press [vol. 4].
Philosophical writings
- Summa logicae (c. 1323), Paris 1448, Bologna 1498, Venice 1508, Oxford 1675.
- Quaestiones in octo libros physicorum (before 1327), Rome 1637.
- Summulae in octo libros physicorum (before 1327), Venice 1506.
- Quodlibeta septem (before 1327), Paris 1487.
- Expositio aurea super artem veterem Aristotelis, 1323.
- Major summa logices, Venice 1521.
- Quaestiones in quattuor libros sententiarum, Lyons, 1495.
- Centilogium theologicum, Lyons 1495.
Theological writings
- Questiones earumque decisiones, Lyons 1483.
- Quodlibeta septem, Paris 1487, Strasbourg 1491.
- Centilogium, Lyons 1494.
- De sacramento altaris and De corpore christi, Strasbourg 1491, Venice 1516.
- Tractatus de sacramento allans.
Political writings
- Opus nonaginta dierum (1332), Leuven 1481, Lyons 1495.
- Dialogus* (begun in 1332) Paris 1476. Lyons 1495.
- Super potestate summi pontificis octo quaestionum decisiones (1344).
- Tractatus de dogmatibus Johannis XXII papae (1333–34).
- Epistola ad fratres minores (1334).
- De jurisdictione imperatoris in causis matrimonialibus, Heidelberg 1598.
- Breviloquium de potestate tyrannica (1346).
- De imperatorum et pontifcum potestate [also known as 'Defensorium'] (1348).
See also
- Gabriel Biel
- Philotheus Boehner
- Concept
- Conceptualism
- History of science in the Middle Ages
- List of Roman Catholic scientist-clerics
- List of scholastic philosophers
- Ernest Addison Moody
- Nominalism
- Occam programming language
- Occam's razor
- Ockham algebra
- Oxford Franciscan school
- Rule according to higher law
- Terminism
- Voluntarism (theology)
- Adam de Wodeham
References
This article incorporates text from a publication now in the public domain: Herbermann, Charles, ed (1913). "William of Ockham". Catholic Encyclopedia. Robert Appleton Company.
- ^ There are claims also that he was born in Ockham, Yorkshire but it is now accepted that his birth place was in Surrey. See Wood, Rega (1997). Ockham on the Virtues. Purdue University Press. pp. 3, 6–7n1. ISBN 9781557530974.
- ^ "Holy Days". Liturgical Calendar. Church of England. http://www.cofe.anglican.org/worship/liturgy/commonworship/texts/calendar/holydays.html. Retrieved 22 October 2006.
- ^ a b c Spade, Paul Vincent. "William of Ockham". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford University. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ockham/. Retrieved 2006-10-22.
- ^ Brundage, James (2008). "Canon Law in the Law schools", in "The history of medieval canon law in the classical period". Catholic University of America Press (Wilfried Hartmann & Kenneth Pennington, eds.). pp. 115. ISBN 078-0-8132-1491-7.
- ^ a b c d Roger Olson. The Story of Christian Theology, p. 350. ISBN-100830815058
- ^ Knysh, George, Biographical rectifications concerning Ockham's Avignon period. Franciscan Studies 46, pp.61–91.
- ^ Hundersmarck, Lawrence (1992). Great Thinkers of the Western World. Harper Collins. pp. 123–128. ISBN 0-06-270026-X.
- ^ McGrade, Arthur (1974). The Political Thought of William of Ockham: Personal and Institutional Principles. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-20284-1.
- ^ Gál, Gedeon, 1982. William of Ockham Died Impenitent in April 1347. Franciscan Studies 42, pp. 90–95
- ^ Knysh, George. Ockham Perspectives, Ukrainian Academy of Arts and Sciences in Canada, Winnipeg, 1994, pp. 28–29.
- ^ Dale T. Irvin & Scott W. Sunquist. History of World Christian Movement Volume I: Earliest Christianity to 1453, p. 434. ISBN-9781570753961
- ^ Standford Encyclopedia of Philosophy on William Ockham
- ^ Baird, Forrest E.; Walter Kaufmann (2008). From Plato to Derrida. Upper Saddle River, New Jersey: Pearson Prentice Hall. ISBN 0-13-158591-6.
- ^ William Turner (1913). "William of Ockham". Catholic Encyclopedia. New York: Robert Appleton Company.
- ^ Russell, Bertrand (2000). History of Western Philosophy. Allen & Unwin. pp. 462–463. ISBN 0-415-22854-9.
- ^ W. M. Thorburn (1918). "The Myth of Occam's Razor". Mind 27 (107): 345–353. doi:10.1093/mind/XXVII.3.345. http://en.wikisource.org/wiki/The_Myth_of_Occam%27s_Razor. Retrieved 2006-10-25.
- ^ Cf. the online British Academy edition at http://www.britac.ac.uk/pubs/dialogus/ockdial.html
- ^ In his Summa Logicae, part II, sections 32 & 33.
- ^ William H. Watts and Richard J. Utz, "Nominalist Influence on Chaucer's Poetry: A Bibliographical Essay," Medievalia & Humanistica 20 n.s. (1993), 147–73; Helen Ruth Andretta, Chaucer's 'Troilus and Criseyde.' A Poet's Response to Ockhamism (New York: Lang, 1997).
Bibliography
- Adams, Marilyn (1987). William Ockham. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. ISBN 0268019401.
- Beckmann, Jan (1992). Ockham-Bibliographie, 1900–1990. Hamburg: F. Meiner Verlag. ISBN 9783787311033.
- Freppert, Lucan (1988). The Basis of Morality According to William Ockham. Franciscan Herald Press. ISBN 9780819909183.
- Knysh, George (1996). Political Ockhamism. Winnipeg: WCU Council of Learned Societies. ISBN 9781896637006.
- Panaccio, Claude (2004). Ockham on Concepts. Aldershot: Ashgate. ISBN 9780754632283.
- McGrade, Arthur Stephen (2002). The Political Thought of William Ockham. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 9780521522243.
- Spade, Paul (1999). The Cambridge Companion to Ockham. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 052158244X.
- Wood, Rega (1997). Ockham on the Virtues. Purdue University Press. ISBN 9781557530974.
External links
- Mediaeval Logic and Philosophy, maintained by Paul Vincent Spade
- William of Ockham biography at University of St Andrews, Scotland
- Dialogus, text translation and studies at British Academy, UK
- The Myth of Occam's Razor by William M. Thorburn (1918)
- BBC Radio 4 'In Our Time' programme on Ockham Download and listen
- William of Ockham entry by Paul Vincent Spade in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
- Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy: William of Ockham
- The Nominalist Ontology of William of Ockham, with an annotated bibliography
- William Turner (1913). "William of Ockham". Catholic Encyclopedia. New York: Robert Appleton Company.
- Richard Utz and Terry Barakat, "Medieval Nominalism and the Literary Questions: Selected Studies." Perspicuitas
Categories:- 1285 births
- 1347 deaths
- 13th-century philosophers
- 14th-century philosophers
- Alumni of Merton College, Oxford
- English philosophers
- Franciscans
- Logicians
- Latin commentators on Aristotle
- English Christian theologians
- People excommunicated by the Roman Catholic Church
- People from Guildford (district)
- Philosophers of language
- Renaissance Latin-language writers
- Roman Catholic philosophers
- Scholastic philosophers
- 14th century in science
- 14th-century Latin writers
- Divine command theory
- Roman Catholic cleric–scientists
Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.