Measurement in quantum mechanics

Measurement in quantum mechanics

The framework of quantum mechanics requires a careful definition of measurement. The issue of measurement lies at the heart of the problem of the interpretation of quantum mechanics, for which there is currently no consensus.

Contents

Measurement from a practical point of view

Measurement is viewed in different ways in the many interpretations of quantum mechanics; however, despite the considerable philosophical differences, they almost universally agree on the practical question of what results from a routine quantum-physics laboratory measurement. To describe this, a simple framework to use is the Copenhagen interpretation, and it will be implicitly used in this section; the utility of this approach has been verified countless times, and all other interpretations are necessarily constructed so as to give the same quantitative predictions as this in almost every case.

Qualitative overview

The quantum state of a system is a mathematical object that fully describes the quantum system. One typically imagines some experimental apparatus and procedure which "prepares" this quantum state; the mathematical object then reflects the setup of the apparatus. Once the quantum state has been prepared, some aspect of it is measured (for example, its position or energy). If the experiment is repeated, so as to measure the same aspect of the same quantum state prepared in the same way, the result of the measurement will often be different.

The expected result of the measurement is in general described by a probability distribution that specifies the likelihoods that the various possible results will be obtained. (This distribution can be either discrete or continuous, depending on what is being measured.)

The measurement process is often said to be random and indeterministic. (However, there is considerable dispute over this issue; in some interpretations of quantum mechanics, the result merely appears random and indeterministic, in other interpretations the indeterminism is core and irreducible.) This is because an important aspect of measurement is wavefunction collapse, the nature of which varies according to the interpretation adopted.

What is universally agreed, however, is that if the measurement is repeated, without re-preparing the state, one finds the same result as the first measurement. As a result, after measuring some aspect of the quantum state, we normally update the quantum state to reflect the result of the measurement; it is this updating that ensures that if an immediate re-measurement is repeated without re-preparing the state, one finds the same result as the first measurement. The updating of the quantum state model is called wavefunction collapse.

Quantitative details

The mathematical relationship between the quantum state and the probability distribution is, again, widely accepted among physicists, and has been experimentally confirmed countless times. This section summarizes this relationship, which is stated in terms of the mathematical formulation of quantum mechanics.

Measurable quantities ("observables") as operators

It is a postulate of quantum mechanics that all measurements have an associated operator (called an observable operator, or just an observable), with the following properties:

  1. The observable is a Hermitian (self-adjoint) operator mapping a Hilbert space (namely, the state space, which consists of all possible quantum states) into itself.
  2. The observable's eigenvalues are real. The possible outcomes of the measurement are precisely the eigenvalues of the given observable.
  3. For each eigenvalue there are one or more corresponding eigenvectors (which in this context are called eigenstates), which will make up the state of the system after the measurement.
  4. The observable has a set of eigenvectors which span the state space. It follows that each observable generates an orthonormal basis of eigenvectors (called an eigenbasis). Physically, this is the statement that any quantum state can always be represented as a superposition of the eigenstates of an observable.

Important examples of observables are:

Operators can be noncommuting. Two Hermitian operators commute if (and only if) there is at least one basis of vectors, each of which is an eigenvector of both operators (this is sometimes called a simultaneous eigenbasis). Noncommuting observables are said to be incompatible and cannot in general be measured simultaneously. In fact, they are related by an uncertainty principle, as a consequence of the Robertson-Schrödinger relation.

Measurement probabilities and wavefunction collapse

There are a few possible ways to mathematically describe the measurement process (both the probability distribution and the collapsed wavefunction). The most convenient description depends on the spectrum (i.e., set of eigenvalues) of the observable.

Discrete, nondegenerate spectrum

Let  {\hat O} be an observable, and suppose that it has discrete eigenstates |n \rang (in bra-ket notation) for n = 1,2,3,... and corresponding eigenvalues O1,O2,O3,..., no two of which are equal.

Assume the system is prepared in state |\psi \rang. Since the eigenstates of an observable form a basis (the eigenbasis), it follows that |\psi\rang can be written in terms of the eigenstates as

|\psi\rang = c_1 | 1 \rang + c_2 | 2 \rang + c_3 | 3 \rang + \cdots

(where c1,c2,... are complex numbers). Then measuring  {\hat O} can yield any of the results O1,O2,O3,..., with corresponding probabilities given by

 \Pr( O_n ) = \frac{ | c_n |^2 }{\sum_k | c_k |^2} = \frac{ |\lang n | \psi \rang|^2}{\lang \psi | \psi\rang}

Usually |\psi\rang is assumed to be normalized, in which case this expression reduces to

 \Pr( O_n ) = | c_n |^2 = |\lang n | \psi \rang|^2

If the result of the measurement is On, then the system's quantum state after the measurement is

 | \psi' \rang  = | n \rang

so any repeated measurement of {\hat O} will yield the same result On. (This phenomenon is called wavefunction collapse.)

Continuous, nondegenerate spectrum

Let  {\hat O} be an observable, and suppose that it has a continuous spectrum of eigenvalues filling the interval (a,b). Assume further that each eigenvalue x in this range is associated with a unique eigenstate |x\rang.

Assume the system is prepared in state |\psi\rang, which can be written in terms of the eigenbasis as

|\psi\rang = \int_a^b c(x) | x \rang dx

(where c(x) is a complex-valued function). Then measuring  {\hat O} can yield a result anywhere in the interval (a,b), with probability density function | c(x) | 2; i.e., a result between y and z will occur with probability

 \Pr( y<x<z ) = \frac{ \int_y^z | c(x) |^2 dx }{\int_a^b | c(x) |^2 dx}

Again, |\psi\rang is often assumed to be normalized, in which case this expression reduces to

 \Pr( y<x<z ) = \int_y^z | c(x) |^2 dx

If the result of the measurement is x, then the new wave function will be

 |\psi'\rang = |x\rang.

Alternatively, it is often possible and convenient to analyze a continuous-spectrum measurement by taking it to be the limit of a different measurement with a discrete spectrum. For example, an analysis of scattering involves a continuous spectrum of energies, but by adding a "box" potential (which bounds the volume in which the particle can be found), the spectrum becomes discrete. By considering larger and larger boxes, this approach need not involve any approximation, but rather can be regarded as an equally valid formalism in which this problem can be analyzed.

Degenerate spectra

If there are multiple eigenstates with the same eigenvalue (called degeneracies), the analysis is a bit less simple to state, but not essentially different. In the discrete case, for example, instead of finding a complete eigenbasis, it is a bit more convenient to write the Hilbert space as a direct sum of eigenspaces. The probability of measuring a particular eigenvalue is the squared component of the state vector in the corresponding eigenspace, and the new state after measurement is the projection of the original state vector into the appropriate eigenspace.

Density matrix formulation

Instead of performing quantum-mechanics computations in terms of wavefunctions (kets), it is sometimes necessary to describe a quantum-mechanical system in terms of a density matrix. The analysis in this case is formally slightly different, but the physical content is the same, and indeed this case can be derived from the wavefunction formulation above. The result for the discrete, degenerate case, for example, is as follows:

Let  {\hat O} be an observable, and suppose that it has discrete eigenvalues O1,O2,O3,..., associated with eigenspaces V1,V2,... respectively. Let Pn be the projection operator into the space Vn.

Assume the system is prepared in the state described by the density matrix ρ. Then measuring  {\hat O} can yield any of the results O1,O2,O3,..., with corresponding probabilities given by

Pr(On) = Tr(Pnρ)

where Tr denotes trace. If the result of the measurement is n, then the new density matrix will be

 \rho' = \frac{P_n \rho P_n}{\mathrm{Tr}(P_n \rho)}

Alternatively, one can say that the measurement process results in the new density matrix

ρ'' = PnρPn
n

where the difference is that ρ ' ' is the density matrix describing the entire ensemble, whereas ρ ' is the density matrix describing the sub-ensemble whose measurement result was n.

Statistics of measurement

As detailed above, the result of measuring a quantum-mechanical system is described by a probability distribution. Some properties of this distribution are as follows:

Suppose we take a measurement corresponding to observable \hat O, on a state whose quantum state is |\psi\rang.

\lang \psi | \hat O | \psi \rang .
\lang \psi | \hat O^2  | \psi \rang - (\lang \psi | \hat O | \psi \rang)^2
\sqrt{\lang \psi | \hat O^2  | \psi \rang - (\lang \psi | \hat O | \psi \rang)^2}

These are direct consequences of the above formulas for measurement probabilities.

Example

Suppose that we have a particle in a 1-dimensional box, set up initially in the ground state |\psi_1\rang. As can be computed from the time-independent Schrödinger equation, the energy of this state is E_1=\frac{\pi^2\hbar^2}{2mL^2} (where m is the particle's mass and L is the box length), and the spatial wavefunction is \lang x|\psi_1\rang = \sqrt{ \frac{2}{L} }~{\rm sin}\left(\frac{\pi x}{L}\right). If the energy is now measured, the result will always certainly be E1, and this measurement will not affect the wavefunction.

Next suppose that the particle's position is measured. The position x will be measured with probability density

 \Pr(S<x<S+dS) = \frac{2}{L}~{\rm sin}^2\left(\frac{\pi S}{L}\right)dS.

If the measurement result was x=S, then the wavefunction after measurement will be the position eigenstate |x=S\rang. If the particle's position is immediately measured again, the same position will be obtained.

The new wavefunction |x=S\rang can, like any wavefunction, be written as a superposition of eigenstates of any observable. In particular, using energy eigenstates, | \psi_n\rang, we have

|x=S\rang = \sum_n | \psi_n \rangle \left\langle \psi_n | x=S \right\rangle = \sum_n | \psi_n \rangle \sqrt{ \frac{2}{L} }~{\rm sin}\left(\frac{n \pi S}{L}\right)

If we now leave this state alone, it will smoothly evolve in time according to the Schrödinger equation. But suppose instead that an energy measurement is immediately taken. Then the possible energy values En will be measured with relative probabilities:

\Pr(E_n) = |\lang \psi_n | S \rang|^2 = \frac{2}{L}~{\rm sin}^2\left(\frac{n \pi S}{L}\right)

and moreover if the measurement result is En, then the new state will be the energy eigenstate |\psi_n\rang.

So in this example, due to the process of wavefunction collapse, a particle initially in the ground state can end up in any energy level, after just two subsequent non-commuting measurements are made.

Wavefunction collapse

The process in which a quantum state becomes one of the eigenstates of the operator corresponding to the measured observable is called "collapse", or "wavefunction collapse". The final eigenstate appears randomly with a probability equal to the square of its overlap with the original state. The process of collapse has been studied in many experiments, most famously in the double-slit experiment. The wavefunction collapse raises serious questions regarding "the measurement problem",[1] as well as, questions of determinism and locality, as demonstrated in the EPR paradox and later in GHZ entanglement. (See below.)

In the last few decades, major advances have been made toward a theoretical understanding of the collapse process. This new theoretical framework, called quantum decoherence, supersedes previous notions of instantaneous collapse and provides an explanation for the absence of quantum coherence after measurement. While this theory correctly predicts the form and probability distribution of the final eigenstates, it does not explain the randomness inherent in the choice of final state.

von Neumann measurement scheme

The von Neumann measurement scheme, the ancestor of quantum decoherence theory, describes measurements by taking into account the measuring apparatus which is also treated as a quantum object. Let the quantum state be in the superposition  \scriptstyle |\psi\rang = \sum_n c_n |\psi_n\rang , where \scriptstyle  |\psi_n\rang are eigenstates of the operator that needs to be measured. In order to make the measurement, the measured system described by \scriptstyle |\psi\rang needs to interact with the measuring apparatus described by the quantum state  \scriptstyle |\phi\rang , so that the total wave function before the interaction is \scriptstyle |\psi\rang |\phi\rang . During the interaction of object and measuring instrument the unitary evolution is supposed to realize the following transition from the initial to the final total wave function:

 |\psi\rang |\phi\rang \rightarrow \sum_n c_n |\psi_n\rang |\phi_n\rang \quad \text{(measurement of the first kind),}

where \scriptstyle |\phi_n\rang are orthonormal states of the measuring apparatus. The unitary evolution above is referred to as premeasurement. The relation with wave function collapse is established by calculating from the final total wave function the final density operator of the object as \scriptstyle \sum_n |c_n|^2  |\psi_n\rang\lang \psi_n|. This density operator is interpreted by von Neumann as describing an ensemble of objects being after the measurement with probability \scriptstyle |c_n|^2 in the state \scriptstyle |\psi_n\rang.

The transition

 |\psi\rang \rightarrow \sum_n |c_n|^2 |\psi_n\rang \lang \psi_n|

is often referred to as weak von Neumann projection, the wave function collapse or strong von Neumann projection

 |\psi\rang \rightarrow \sum_n |c_n|^2 |\psi_n\rang \lang \psi_n| \rightarrow |\psi_n\rang

being thought to correspond to an additional selection of a subensemble by means of observation.

In case the measured observable has a degenerate spectrum, weak von Neumann projection is generalized to Lüders projection

 |\psi\rang \rightarrow \sum_n |c_n|^2 P_n,\; P_n = \sum_i |\psi_{ni}\rang \lang \psi_{ni}|,

in which the vectors \scriptstyle |\psi_{ni}\rang for fixed n are the degenerate eigenvectors of the measured observable. For an arbitrary state described by a density operator \scriptstyle \rho Lüders projection is given by

 \rho \rightarrow \sum_n P_n \rho P_n.

Measurements of the second kind

In a measurement of the second kind the unitary evolution during the interaction of object and measuring instrument is supposed to be given by

 |\psi\rang |\phi\rang \rightarrow \sum_n c_n |\chi_n\rang |\phi_n\rang,

in which the states \scriptstyle |\chi_n\rang of the object are determined by specific properties of the interaction between object and measuring instrument. They are normalized but not necessarily mutually orthogonal. The relation with wave function collapse is analogous to that obtained for measurements of the first kind, the final state of the object now being \scriptstyle |\chi_n\rang with probability \scriptstyle |c_n|^2. Note that many present-day measurement procedures are measurements of the second kind, some even functioning correctly only as a consequence of being of the second kind (for instance, a photon counter, detecting a photon by absorbing and hence annihilating it, thus ideally leaving the electromagnetic field in the vacuum state rather than in the state corresponding to the number of detected photons; also the Stern-Gerlach experiment would not function at all if it really were a measurement of the first kind[2]). [pdf]

Decoherence in quantum measurement

One can also introduce the interaction with the environment \scriptstyle |e\rang , so that, in a measurement of the first kind, after the interaction the total wave function takes a form

 \sum_n c_n |\psi_n\rang |\phi_n\rang |e_n \rang,

which is related to the phenomenon of decoherence.

The above is completely described by the Schrödinger equation and there are not any interpretational problems with this. Now the problematic wavefunction collapse does not need to be understood as a process \scriptstyle |\psi\rangle \rightarrow |\psi_n\rang on the level of the measured system, but can also be understood as a process \scriptstyle |\phi\rangle \rightarrow |\phi_n\rang on the level of the measuring apparatus, or as a process \scriptstyle |e\rangle \rightarrow |e_n\rang on the level of the environment. Studying these processes provides considerable insight into the measurement problem by avoiding the arbitrary boundary between the quantum and classical worlds, though it does not explain the presence of randomness in the choice of final eigenstate. If the set of states

 \{ |\psi_n\rang\} ,  \{ |\phi_n\rang\} , or  \{ |e_n\rang\}

represents a set of states that do not overlap in space, the appearance of collapse can be generated by either the Bohm interpretation or the Everett interpretation which both deny the reality of wavefunction collapse. Both of these are stated to predict the same probabilities for collapses to various states as the conventional interpretation by their supporters. The Bohm interpretation is held to be correct only by a small minority of physicists, since there are difficulties with the generalization for use with relativistic quantum field theory. However, there is no proof that the Bohm interpretation is inconsistent with quantum field theory, and work to reconcile the two is ongoing. The Everett interpretation easily accommodates relativistic quantum field theory.

Philosophical problems of quantum measurements

What physical interaction constitutes a measurement?

Until the advent of quantum decoherence theory in the late 20th century, a major conceptual problem of quantum mechanics and especially the Copenhagen interpretation was the lack of a distinctive criterion for a given physical interaction to qualify as "a measurement" and cause a wavefunction to collapse. This is best illustrated by the Schrödinger's cat paradox. Certain aspects of this question are now well understood in the framework of quantum decoherence theory, such as an understanding of weak measurements, and quantifying what measurements or interactions are sufficient to destroy quantum coherence. Nevertheless, there remains less than universal agreement among physicists on some aspects of the question of what constitutes a measurement.

Does measurement actually determine the state?

The question of whether (and in what sense) a measurement actually determines the state is one which differs among the different interpretations of quantum mechanics. (It is also closely related to the understanding of wavefunction collapse.) For example, in most versions of the Copenhagen interpretation, the measurement determines the state, and after measurement the state is definitely what was measured. But according to the Many-worlds interpretation, measurement determines the state in a more restricted sense: In other "worlds", other measurement results were obtained, and the other possible states still exist.

Is the measurement process random or deterministic?

As described above, there is universal agreement that quantum mechanics appears random, in the sense that all experimental results yet uncovered can be predicted and understood in the framework of quantum mechanics measurements being fundamentally random. Nevertheless, it is not settled[3] whether this is true, fundamental randomness, or merely "emergent" randomness resulting from underlying hidden variables which deterministically cause measurement results to happen a certain way each time. This continues to be an area of active research.[4]

(If there are hidden variables, they would have to be "nonlocal", see below.)

Does the measurement process violate locality?

In physics, the Principle of locality is the concept that information cannot travel faster than the speed of light (also see special relativity). It is known experimentally (see Bell's theorem, which is related to the EPR paradox) that if quantum mechanics is deterministic (due to hidden variables, as described above), then it is nonlocal (i.e. violates the principle of locality). Nevertheless, there is not universal agreement among physicists on whether quantum mechanics is nondeterministic, nonlocal, or both.[3]

See also

External links

Further reading

References

  1. ^ http://books.google.com/books?id=5t0tm0FB1CsC&pg=PA215&lpg=PA215&dq=wave+function+collapse&source=bl&ots=a7iUGurRDC&sig=o1ddjY7lQrj4EQdvS49xcceWq2M&hl=en&ei=RfgtSsDNL4WgM8u-rf4J&sa=X&oi=book_result&ct=result&resnum=7#PPA215,M1
  2. ^ M.O. Scully, W.E. Lamb, A. Barut, On the theory of the Stern-Gerlach apparatus, Foundations of Physics 17, 575-583 (1987).
  3. ^ a b Quantum mechanics: Myths and facts
  4. ^ S. Gröblacher et al., An experimental test of non-local realism, Nature 446, 871 (2007). Direct web link

Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Нужно решить контрольную?

Look at other dictionaries:

  • quantum mechanics — quantum mechanical, adj. Physics. a theory of the mechanics of atoms, molecules, and other physical systems that are subject to the uncertainty principle. Abbr.: QM Cf. nonrelativistic quantum mechanics, relativistic quantum mechanics. [1920 25]… …   Universalium

  • Quantum mechanics — For a generally accessible and less technical introduction to the topic, see Introduction to quantum mechanics. Quantum mechanics …   Wikipedia

  • Interpretation of quantum mechanics — An interpretation of quantum mechanics is a statement which attempts to explain how quantum mechanics informs our understanding of nature. Although quantum mechanics has received thorough experimental testing, many of these experiments are open… …   Wikipedia

  • Introduction to quantum mechanics — This article is an accessible, non technical introduction to the subject. For the main encyclopedia article, see Quantum mechanics. Quantum mechanics …   Wikipedia

  • Perturbation theory (quantum mechanics) — In quantum mechanics, perturbation theory is a set of approximation schemes directly related to mathematical perturbation for describing a complicated quantum system in terms of a simpler one. The idea is to start with a simple system for which a …   Wikipedia

  • Mathematical formulation of quantum mechanics — Quantum mechanics Uncertainty principle …   Wikipedia

  • Relational quantum mechanics — This article is intended for those already familiar with quantum mechanics and its attendant interpretational difficulties. Readers who are new to the subject may first want to read the introduction to quantum mechanics. Relational quantum… …   Wikipedia

  • Quantum mind–body problem — The quantum mind–body problem refers to the philosophical discussions of the mind–body problem in the context of quantum mechanics. Since quantum mechanics involves quantum superpositions, which are not perceived by observers, some… …   Wikipedia

  • Quantum state — In quantum physics, a quantum state is a mathematical object that fully describes a quantum system. One typically imagines some experimental apparatus and procedure which prepares this quantum state; the mathematical object then reflects the… …   Wikipedia

  • Measurement problem — The measurement problem in quantum mechanics is the unresolved problem of how (or if) wavefunction collapse occurs. The inability to observe this process directly has given rise to different interpretations of quantum mechanics, and poses a key… …   Wikipedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”