- Measurement in quantum mechanics
-
Quantum mechanics
Introduction
Mathematical formulationsFundamental conceptsQuantum state · Wave function
Superposition · Entanglement
Complementarity · Duality
Uncertainty · Measurement
Exclusion · Decoherence
Ehrenfest theorem
Tunnelling · NonlocalityExperimentsDouble-slit · Davisson–Germer
Stern–Gerlach · Bell's inequality
Popper · Schrödinger's cat
Elitzur–Vaidman bomb tester
Quantum eraser
Delayed choice quantum eraser
Wheeler's delayed choiceFormulationsEquationsInterpretationsde Broglie–Bohm
Consciousness-caused
Consistent histories · Copenhagen
Ensemble · Hidden variables
Many-worlds · Objective collapse
Pondicherry · Quantum logic
Relational · Stochastic
TransactionalScientistsBell · Bohm · Bohr · Born · Bose
de Broglie · Dirac · Ehrenfest
Everett · Feynman · Heisenberg
Jordan · Kramers · von Neumann
Pauli · Planck · Schrödinger
Sommerfeld · Wien · WignerThe framework of quantum mechanics requires a careful definition of measurement. The issue of measurement lies at the heart of the problem of the interpretation of quantum mechanics, for which there is currently no consensus.
Contents
- 1 Measurement from a practical point of view
- 2 Wavefunction collapse
- 3 Philosophical problems of quantum measurements
- 4 See also
- 5 External links
- 6 Further reading
- 7 References
Measurement from a practical point of view
Measurement is viewed in different ways in the many interpretations of quantum mechanics; however, despite the considerable philosophical differences, they almost universally agree on the practical question of what results from a routine quantum-physics laboratory measurement. To describe this, a simple framework to use is the Copenhagen interpretation, and it will be implicitly used in this section; the utility of this approach has been verified countless times, and all other interpretations are necessarily constructed so as to give the same quantitative predictions as this in almost every case.
Qualitative overview
The quantum state of a system is a mathematical object that fully describes the quantum system. One typically imagines some experimental apparatus and procedure which "prepares" this quantum state; the mathematical object then reflects the setup of the apparatus. Once the quantum state has been prepared, some aspect of it is measured (for example, its position or energy). If the experiment is repeated, so as to measure the same aspect of the same quantum state prepared in the same way, the result of the measurement will often be different.
The expected result of the measurement is in general described by a probability distribution that specifies the likelihoods that the various possible results will be obtained. (This distribution can be either discrete or continuous, depending on what is being measured.)
The measurement process is often said to be random and indeterministic. (However, there is considerable dispute over this issue; in some interpretations of quantum mechanics, the result merely appears random and indeterministic, in other interpretations the indeterminism is core and irreducible.) This is because an important aspect of measurement is wavefunction collapse, the nature of which varies according to the interpretation adopted.
What is universally agreed, however, is that if the measurement is repeated, without re-preparing the state, one finds the same result as the first measurement. As a result, after measuring some aspect of the quantum state, we normally update the quantum state to reflect the result of the measurement; it is this updating that ensures that if an immediate re-measurement is repeated without re-preparing the state, one finds the same result as the first measurement. The updating of the quantum state model is called wavefunction collapse.
Quantitative details
The mathematical relationship between the quantum state and the probability distribution is, again, widely accepted among physicists, and has been experimentally confirmed countless times. This section summarizes this relationship, which is stated in terms of the mathematical formulation of quantum mechanics.
Measurable quantities ("observables") as operators
Main article: ObservableIt is a postulate of quantum mechanics that all measurements have an associated operator (called an observable operator, or just an observable), with the following properties:
- The observable is a Hermitian (self-adjoint) operator mapping a Hilbert space (namely, the state space, which consists of all possible quantum states) into itself.
- The observable's eigenvalues are real. The possible outcomes of the measurement are precisely the eigenvalues of the given observable.
- For each eigenvalue there are one or more corresponding eigenvectors (which in this context are called eigenstates), which will make up the state of the system after the measurement.
- The observable has a set of eigenvectors which span the state space. It follows that each observable generates an orthonormal basis of eigenvectors (called an eigenbasis). Physically, this is the statement that any quantum state can always be represented as a superposition of the eigenstates of an observable.
Important examples of observables are:
- The Hamiltonian operator, representing the total energy of the system; with the special case of the nonrelativistic Hamiltonian operator: .
- The momentum operator: (in the position basis).
- The position operator: , where (in the momentum basis).
Operators can be noncommuting. Two Hermitian operators commute if (and only if) there is at least one basis of vectors, each of which is an eigenvector of both operators (this is sometimes called a simultaneous eigenbasis). Noncommuting observables are said to be incompatible and cannot in general be measured simultaneously. In fact, they are related by an uncertainty principle, as a consequence of the Robertson-Schrödinger relation.
Measurement probabilities and wavefunction collapse
There are a few possible ways to mathematically describe the measurement process (both the probability distribution and the collapsed wavefunction). The most convenient description depends on the spectrum (i.e., set of eigenvalues) of the observable.
Discrete, nondegenerate spectrum
Let be an observable, and suppose that it has discrete eigenstates (in bra-ket notation) for n = 1,2,3,... and corresponding eigenvalues O1,O2,O3,..., no two of which are equal.
Assume the system is prepared in state . Since the eigenstates of an observable form a basis (the eigenbasis), it follows that can be written in terms of the eigenstates as
(where c1,c2,... are complex numbers). Then measuring can yield any of the results O1,O2,O3,..., with corresponding probabilities given by
Usually is assumed to be normalized, in which case this expression reduces to
If the result of the measurement is On, then the system's quantum state after the measurement is
so any repeated measurement of will yield the same result On. (This phenomenon is called wavefunction collapse.)
Continuous, nondegenerate spectrum
Let be an observable, and suppose that it has a continuous spectrum of eigenvalues filling the interval (a,b). Assume further that each eigenvalue x in this range is associated with a unique eigenstate .
Assume the system is prepared in state , which can be written in terms of the eigenbasis as
(where c(x) is a complex-valued function). Then measuring can yield a result anywhere in the interval (a,b), with probability density function | c(x) | 2; i.e., a result between y and z will occur with probability
Again, is often assumed to be normalized, in which case this expression reduces to
If the result of the measurement is x, then the new wave function will be
Alternatively, it is often possible and convenient to analyze a continuous-spectrum measurement by taking it to be the limit of a different measurement with a discrete spectrum. For example, an analysis of scattering involves a continuous spectrum of energies, but by adding a "box" potential (which bounds the volume in which the particle can be found), the spectrum becomes discrete. By considering larger and larger boxes, this approach need not involve any approximation, but rather can be regarded as an equally valid formalism in which this problem can be analyzed.
Degenerate spectra
If there are multiple eigenstates with the same eigenvalue (called degeneracies), the analysis is a bit less simple to state, but not essentially different. In the discrete case, for example, instead of finding a complete eigenbasis, it is a bit more convenient to write the Hilbert space as a direct sum of eigenspaces. The probability of measuring a particular eigenvalue is the squared component of the state vector in the corresponding eigenspace, and the new state after measurement is the projection of the original state vector into the appropriate eigenspace.
Density matrix formulation
Main article: Density matrixInstead of performing quantum-mechanics computations in terms of wavefunctions (kets), it is sometimes necessary to describe a quantum-mechanical system in terms of a density matrix. The analysis in this case is formally slightly different, but the physical content is the same, and indeed this case can be derived from the wavefunction formulation above. The result for the discrete, degenerate case, for example, is as follows:
Let be an observable, and suppose that it has discrete eigenvalues O1,O2,O3,..., associated with eigenspaces V1,V2,... respectively. Let Pn be the projection operator into the space Vn.
Assume the system is prepared in the state described by the density matrix ρ. Then measuring can yield any of the results O1,O2,O3,..., with corresponding probabilities given by
- Pr(On) = Tr(Pnρ)
where Tr denotes trace. If the result of the measurement is n, then the new density matrix will be
Alternatively, one can say that the measurement process results in the new density matrix
ρ'' = ∑ PnρPn n where the difference is that ρ ' ' is the density matrix describing the entire ensemble, whereas ρ ' is the density matrix describing the sub-ensemble whose measurement result was n.
Statistics of measurement
As detailed above, the result of measuring a quantum-mechanical system is described by a probability distribution. Some properties of this distribution are as follows:
Suppose we take a measurement corresponding to observable , on a state whose quantum state is .
- The mean (average) value of the measurement is (see Expectation value (quantum mechanics))
- .
- The variance of the measurement is
- The standard deviation of the measurement is
These are direct consequences of the above formulas for measurement probabilities.
Example
Suppose that we have a particle in a 1-dimensional box, set up initially in the ground state . As can be computed from the time-independent Schrödinger equation, the energy of this state is (where m is the particle's mass and L is the box length), and the spatial wavefunction is . If the energy is now measured, the result will always certainly be E1, and this measurement will not affect the wavefunction.
Next suppose that the particle's position is measured. The position x will be measured with probability density
If the measurement result was x=S, then the wavefunction after measurement will be the position eigenstate . If the particle's position is immediately measured again, the same position will be obtained.
The new wavefunction can, like any wavefunction, be written as a superposition of eigenstates of any observable. In particular, using energy eigenstates, , we have
If we now leave this state alone, it will smoothly evolve in time according to the Schrödinger equation. But suppose instead that an energy measurement is immediately taken. Then the possible energy values En will be measured with relative probabilities:
and moreover if the measurement result is En, then the new state will be the energy eigenstate .
So in this example, due to the process of wavefunction collapse, a particle initially in the ground state can end up in any energy level, after just two subsequent non-commuting measurements are made.
Wavefunction collapse
Main article: Wave function collapseThe process in which a quantum state becomes one of the eigenstates of the operator corresponding to the measured observable is called "collapse", or "wavefunction collapse". The final eigenstate appears randomly with a probability equal to the square of its overlap with the original state. The process of collapse has been studied in many experiments, most famously in the double-slit experiment. The wavefunction collapse raises serious questions regarding "the measurement problem",[1] as well as, questions of determinism and locality, as demonstrated in the EPR paradox and later in GHZ entanglement. (See below.)
In the last few decades, major advances have been made toward a theoretical understanding of the collapse process. This new theoretical framework, called quantum decoherence, supersedes previous notions of instantaneous collapse and provides an explanation for the absence of quantum coherence after measurement. While this theory correctly predicts the form and probability distribution of the final eigenstates, it does not explain the randomness inherent in the choice of final state.
von Neumann measurement scheme
The von Neumann measurement scheme, the ancestor of quantum decoherence theory, describes measurements by taking into account the measuring apparatus which is also treated as a quantum object. Let the quantum state be in the superposition , where are eigenstates of the operator that needs to be measured. In order to make the measurement, the measured system described by needs to interact with the measuring apparatus described by the quantum state , so that the total wave function before the interaction is . During the interaction of object and measuring instrument the unitary evolution is supposed to realize the following transition from the initial to the final total wave function:
where are orthonormal states of the measuring apparatus. The unitary evolution above is referred to as premeasurement. The relation with wave function collapse is established by calculating from the final total wave function the final density operator of the object as This density operator is interpreted by von Neumann as describing an ensemble of objects being after the measurement with probability in the state
The transition
is often referred to as weak von Neumann projection, the wave function collapse or strong von Neumann projection
being thought to correspond to an additional selection of a subensemble by means of observation.
In case the measured observable has a degenerate spectrum, weak von Neumann projection is generalized to Lüders projection
in which the vectors for fixed n are the degenerate eigenvectors of the measured observable. For an arbitrary state described by a density operator Lüders projection is given by
Measurements of the second kind
In a measurement of the second kind the unitary evolution during the interaction of object and measuring instrument is supposed to be given by
in which the states of the object are determined by specific properties of the interaction between object and measuring instrument. They are normalized but not necessarily mutually orthogonal. The relation with wave function collapse is analogous to that obtained for measurements of the first kind, the final state of the object now being with probability Note that many present-day measurement procedures are measurements of the second kind, some even functioning correctly only as a consequence of being of the second kind (for instance, a photon counter, detecting a photon by absorbing and hence annihilating it, thus ideally leaving the electromagnetic field in the vacuum state rather than in the state corresponding to the number of detected photons; also the Stern-Gerlach experiment would not function at all if it really were a measurement of the first kind[2]). [pdf]
Decoherence in quantum measurement
One can also introduce the interaction with the environment , so that, in a measurement of the first kind, after the interaction the total wave function takes a form
which is related to the phenomenon of decoherence.
The above is completely described by the Schrödinger equation and there are not any interpretational problems with this. Now the problematic wavefunction collapse does not need to be understood as a process on the level of the measured system, but can also be understood as a process on the level of the measuring apparatus, or as a process on the level of the environment. Studying these processes provides considerable insight into the measurement problem by avoiding the arbitrary boundary between the quantum and classical worlds, though it does not explain the presence of randomness in the choice of final eigenstate. If the set of states
- , , or
represents a set of states that do not overlap in space, the appearance of collapse can be generated by either the Bohm interpretation or the Everett interpretation which both deny the reality of wavefunction collapse. Both of these are stated to predict the same probabilities for collapses to various states as the conventional interpretation by their supporters. The Bohm interpretation is held to be correct only by a small minority of physicists, since there are difficulties with the generalization for use with relativistic quantum field theory. However, there is no proof that the Bohm interpretation is inconsistent with quantum field theory, and work to reconcile the two is ongoing. The Everett interpretation easily accommodates relativistic quantum field theory.
Philosophical problems of quantum measurements
What physical interaction constitutes a measurement?
Until the advent of quantum decoherence theory in the late 20th century, a major conceptual problem of quantum mechanics and especially the Copenhagen interpretation was the lack of a distinctive criterion for a given physical interaction to qualify as "a measurement" and cause a wavefunction to collapse. This is best illustrated by the Schrödinger's cat paradox. Certain aspects of this question are now well understood in the framework of quantum decoherence theory, such as an understanding of weak measurements, and quantifying what measurements or interactions are sufficient to destroy quantum coherence. Nevertheless, there remains less than universal agreement among physicists on some aspects of the question of what constitutes a measurement.
Does measurement actually determine the state?
The question of whether (and in what sense) a measurement actually determines the state is one which differs among the different interpretations of quantum mechanics. (It is also closely related to the understanding of wavefunction collapse.) For example, in most versions of the Copenhagen interpretation, the measurement determines the state, and after measurement the state is definitely what was measured. But according to the Many-worlds interpretation, measurement determines the state in a more restricted sense: In other "worlds", other measurement results were obtained, and the other possible states still exist.
Is the measurement process random or deterministic?
As described above, there is universal agreement that quantum mechanics appears random, in the sense that all experimental results yet uncovered can be predicted and understood in the framework of quantum mechanics measurements being fundamentally random. Nevertheless, it is not settled[3] whether this is true, fundamental randomness, or merely "emergent" randomness resulting from underlying hidden variables which deterministically cause measurement results to happen a certain way each time. This continues to be an area of active research.[4]
(If there are hidden variables, they would have to be "nonlocal", see below.)
Does the measurement process violate locality?
Main articles: Quantum nonlocality and Principle of localityIn physics, the Principle of locality is the concept that information cannot travel faster than the speed of light (also see special relativity). It is known experimentally (see Bell's theorem, which is related to the EPR paradox) that if quantum mechanics is deterministic (due to hidden variables, as described above), then it is nonlocal (i.e. violates the principle of locality). Nevertheless, there is not universal agreement among physicists on whether quantum mechanics is nondeterministic, nonlocal, or both.[3]
See also
- Measurement related problems and paradoxes
- Afshar experiment
- Measurement problem
- Wavefunction collapse
- Quantum Zeno effect
- EPR paradox
- Quantum pseudo-telepathy
- Renninger negative-result experiment
- Elitzur–Vaidman bomb-testing problem
- Schrödinger's cat
- Popper's experiment
- Interpretations of quantum mechanics
- Transactional interpretation
- Copenhagen interpretation
- Many-worlds interpretation
- Hidden variables theory
- Quantum mechanics formalism
- Quantum mechanics
- Mathematical formulation of quantum mechanics
- Schrödinger equation
- Bra-ket notation
- Generalized measurement (POVM, Positive operator valued measure)
External links
- "The Double Slit Experiment". (physicsweb.org)
- "Measurement in Quantum Mechanics" Henry Krips in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
- Decoherence, the measurement problem, and interpretations of quantum mechanics
- Measurements and Decoherence
- The conditions for discrimination between quantum states with minimum error
- Quantum behavior of measurement apparatus
- Yonina C. Eldar, Alexandre Megretski, and George C. Verghese. Designing optimal quantum detectors via semidefinite programming. IEEE Transactions on Information Theory, Vol. 49, No. 4, 1007—1012, 2003.
Further reading
- John A. Wheeler and Wojciech Hubert Zurek (eds), Quantum Theory and Measurement, Princeton University Press, (1983), ISBN 0-691-08316-9
- Vladimir B. Braginsky and Farid Ya. Khalili, Quantum Measurement, Cambridge University Press, (1992), ISBN 0-521-41928-X
- Greenstein, G. and Zajonc, A.G., The Quantum Challenge, Jones and Bartlett Publishers, (2006), ISBN 0-7367-2470-X
References
- ^ http://books.google.com/books?id=5t0tm0FB1CsC&pg=PA215&lpg=PA215&dq=wave+function+collapse&source=bl&ots=a7iUGurRDC&sig=o1ddjY7lQrj4EQdvS49xcceWq2M&hl=en&ei=RfgtSsDNL4WgM8u-rf4J&sa=X&oi=book_result&ct=result&resnum=7#PPA215,M1
- ^ M.O. Scully, W.E. Lamb, A. Barut, On the theory of the Stern-Gerlach apparatus, Foundations of Physics 17, 575-583 (1987).
- ^ a b Quantum mechanics: Myths and facts
- ^ S. Gröblacher et al., An experimental test of non-local realism, Nature 446, 871 (2007). Direct web link
Categories:- Quantum measurement
- Quantum mechanics
- Philosophy of physics
Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.