Marx's theory of the state

Marx's theory of the state

Karl Marx's ideas about the state can be divided into three subject areas: pre-capitalist states, states in the capitalist (i.e. present) era, and the state (or absence of one) in post-capitalist society. Overlaying this is the fact that his own ideas about the state changed as he grew older, differing in his early pre-communist phase, the "young Marx" phase which predates the unsuccessful 1848 uprisings in Europe, and in his mature, more nuanced work.


Contents

The bourgeois state

In Marx's 1843 Critique of Hegel's Philosophy of Right, his basic conception is that the state and civil society are separate; however, he already saw some limitations to that model:

The political state everywhere needs the guarantee of spheres lying outside it.[1]
He as yet was saying nothing about the abolition of private property, does not express a developed theory of class, and "the solution [he offers] to the problem of the state/civil society separation is a purely political solution, namely universal suffrage." (Evans, 112)

By the time of The German Ideology (1846) he is seeing the state as a creature of the bourgeois economic interest. Two years later that idea was put explosively in The Communist Manifesto[2]

The executive of the modern state is nothing but a committee for managing the common affairs of the whole bourgeoisie.[3]

This represents the high point of conformance of the state theory to a strict economic interpretation of history: The forces of production determine peoples' production relations; their production relations determine all other relations, including the political.[4] ("Determines" is the strong form of the claim, Marx also uses "conditions". Also, even "determination" is not causality, and some reciprocity of action is admitted.) The bourgeoisie control the economy, therefore they control the state. The state, in this theory, is an instrument of class rule.

Communist Manifesto

The Communist Manifesto was a short polemical work; more detail on the theories concerned can be obtained by going back to The German Ideology:

The Relation of State and Law to Property
. . . In the case of the nations which grew out of the Middle Ages, tribal property evolved through various stages - feudal landed property, corporative moveable property, capital invested in manufacture - to modern capital, determined by big industry and universal competition, i.e. pure private property, which has cast off all semblance of a communal institution and has shut out the State from any influence on the development of property. To this modern private property corresponds the modern State, which, purchased gradually by the owners of property by means of taxation, has fallen entirely into their hands through the national debt, and its existence has become wholly dependent on the commercial credit which the owners of property, the bourgeois, extend to it, as reflected in the rise and fall of State funds on the stock exchange. By the mere fact that it is a class and no longer an estate, the bourgeoisie is forced to organise itself no longer locally, but nationally, and to give a general form to its mean average interest. Through the emancipation of private property from the community, the State has become a separate entity, beside and outside civil society; but it is nothing more than the form of organisation which the bourgeois necessarily adopt both for internal and external purposes, for the mutual guarantee of their property and interests. The independence of the State is only found nowadays in those countries where the estates have not yet completely developed into classes, where the estates, done away with in more advanced countries, still have a part to play, and where there exists a mixture; countries, that is to say, in which no one section of the population can achieve dominance over the others. This is the case particularly in Germany. The most perfect example of the modern State is North America. The modern French, English and American writers all express the opinion that the State exists only for the sake of private property, so that this fact has penetrated into the consciousness of the normal man.

Economic Dependence of the State on the Bourgeoisie
With the development and accumulation of bourgeois property, i.e., with the development of commerce and industry, individuals grew richer and richer while the state fell ever more deeply into debt. This phenomenon was evident already in the first Italian commercial republics; later, since the last century, it showed itself to a marked degree in Holland, where the stock exchange speculator Pinto drew attention to it as early as 1750,[6] and now it is again occurring in England. It is therefore obvious that as soon as the bourgeoisie has accumulated money, the state has to beg from the bourgeoisie and in the end it is actually bought up by the latter. This takes place in a period in which the bourgeoisie is still confronted by another class, and consequently the state can retain some appearance of independence in relation to both of them. Even after the state has been bought up, it still needs money and, therefore, continues to be dependent on the bourgeoisie; nevertheless, when the interests of the bourgeoisie demand it, the state can have at its disposal more funds than states which are less developed and, therefore, less burdened with debts. However, even the least developed states of Europe, those of the Holy Alliance, are inexorably approaching this fate, for they will be bought up by the bourgeoisie; then Stirner will be able to console them with the identity of private and state property, especially his own sovereign, who is trying in vain to postpone the hour when political power will be sold to the “burghers” who have become “angry”.

[7]

Modifications

By the early 1850s, political events in Europe, which he covered in articles for the New York Daily Tribune as well as a number of more substantial pieces, were forcing Marx to modify his theory to allow considerably more autonomy for the state. By 1851, the mid century rebellions had all given way to conservativism the principal countries of Europe had autocratic or aristocratic governments: Napoleon III in France, Frederick Wilhelm IV in Germany, and in England a parliament populated mainly by members of the aristocratic class, whether Whig or Conservative. Yet at the same time the bourgeoisie had economic power in those places. For an economic determinist, this was clearly an anomalous situation, and Marx gave it considerable attention.[8]

His solution is what Elster has described as the "abdication" or "abstention" theory.[9] It contends that the bourgeoisie found that the advantages of wielding direct power were, under the circumstances, outweighed by various costs and disadvantages, so they were willing to tolerate an aristocratic or despotic government as long as it did not act too detrimentally to their interests. Marx makes several points. Regarding England, he says of the bourgeoisie: "if the aristocracy is their vanishing opponent the working class is their arising enemy. They prefer to compromise with the vanishing opponent rather than to strengthen the rising enemy, to whom the future belongs."[10]

He also suggests that it would be better for the bourgeoisie not to wield power directly because this would make their dominince too obvious, creating a clear target for proletarian attack.[11] Better to make the workers fight a "two front war" (Elster) against the aristocracy in government and the bourgeoisie in the economy. This would, among other things, make it difficult for the proletarians to form a clear conception of who was their principal enemy. Regarding France, he suggests that the bourgeoisie recognised that they had been better off under the monarchy (1830-1848) than during the brief period when they wielded power themselves (1848-1851) "since they must now confront the subjugated classes and contend against them without mediation, without the concealment afforded by the crown."[12]

Source

Michael Evans, Karl Marx. London, 1975.

References

  1. ^ Separation but with limitations: Evans, p 112. The quote is from the Critique, p 115, in Evans, p 112.
  2. ^ http://www.marxists.org/archive/works/marx/1848/communist-manifesto/ch01.htm
  3. ^ The sentence is about a quarter of the way through Chapter I: "Bourgeois and Proletarians"
  4. ^ The economic interpretation of history, also called historical materialism, is expounded in The German Ideology, Chapter 1; and in the Preface to A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy (1859). Chapter 3 of The German Ideology has material on its connection to the state.
  5. ^ http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1859/german-ideology/ch01c.htm --Chapter 1, section C:"The Real Basis of Ideology"
  6. ^ Isaac Pinto, Lettre sur la Jalousie du Commerce in Traité de la Circulation et du Crédit
  7. ^ http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1845/german-ideology/ch03j.htm#c --Chapter 3, "The New Testament: "Ego", "The Owner", "My Power", "Law".
  8. ^ Evans, p 126: "for Marx the failure of the bourgeoisie to act as a ruling class, to give their economic power political substance, was one of the major features of the post-1848 situation, as true of England and France as of Germany."
  9. ^ Elster, Chap 8.
  10. ^ "The Chartists", New York Daily Tribune, 25 August 1852; in Evans, p 126.
  11. ^ Evans, p 116. He cites Eighteenth Brumaire of Lous Napoleon.
  12. ^ Karl Marx, The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte (New York: International Publishers, 1963)p 49;In Elster, p 147. .

Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Нужно сделать НИР?

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Marx's theory of alienation — Part of a series on Marxism …   Wikipedia

  • Marx's theory of human nature — Part of a series on Marxism …   Wikipedia

  • Marx's theory of history — Part of a series on Marxism …   Wikipedia

  • The Origin of the Family, Private Property and the State — Friedrich Engels Part of a series on …   Wikipedia

  • Justification for the state — The justification of the state is a term that refers to the source of legitimate authority for the state or government. Typically, a justification of the state explains why the state should exist, and what a legitimate state should or should not… …   Wikipedia

  • Evolutionary theory and the political left — have had a sometimes wary relationship with one another. Some on the political left, especially Marxists and communists, have been critical of aspects of the theory of evolution by natural selection (Darwinism). Some of this opposition appears… …   Wikipedia

  • State — A state is a political association with effective sovereignty over a geographic area and representing a population. These may be nation states, sub national states or multinational states. A state usually includes the set of institutions that… …   Wikipedia

  • State —    A central concept in Marxism is the state, although Karl Marx himself did not set out a systematic theory of it. Marx’s basic view of the state is set out in the Communist Manifesto (1848) where he wrote, “The executive of the modern state is… …   Historical dictionary of Marxism

  • State (polity) — This article is about the general concept of the state. For the subjects of international law, see Sovereign state. For other uses, see State (disambiguation). The frontispiece of Thomas Hobbes Leviathan A state is an organised political… …   Wikipedia

  • The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Napoleon — 1852 publication in Die Revolution …   Wikipedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”