- History of philosophy in Poland
The history of philosophy in Poland parallels the evolution of
philosophy inEurope generally. Polish philosophy drew upon the broader currents of European philosophy, and in turn contributed to their growth. Among the most momentous Polish contributions were made in the13th century by the Scholastic philosopher and scientistWitelo ; and in the16th century , by theRenaissance polymath Nicolaus Copernicus . [Władysław Tatarkiewicz , "Zarys dziejów filozofii w Polsce" (A Brief History of Philosophy in Poland), p. 32.]Subsequently the
Polish-Lithuanian Commonwealth partook in the intellectual ferment of the Enlightenment, which for the multi-ethnic Commonwealth ended not long after the partitions and political annihilation that would last for the next 123 years, until the collapse of the three partitioning empires inWorld War I .The period of
Messianism , between the November 1830 and January 1863 Uprisings, reflected European Romantic andIdealist trends, as well as a Polish yearning for politicalresurrection . It was a period ofmaximalist metaphysical systems.The collapse of the January 1863 Uprising prompted an agonizing reappraisal of Poland's situation. Poles gave up their earlier practice of "measuring their resources by their aspirations," and buckled down to hard work and study. " [A] Positivist," wrote the novelist
Bolesław Prus ' friend,Julian Ochorowicz , was "anyone who bases assertions on verifiable evidence; who does not express himself categorically about doubtful things, and does not speak at all about those that are inaccessible." [Władysław Tatarkiewicz , "Historia filozofii" (History of Philosophy), vol. 3, p. 177.]The
20th century brought a new quickening to Polish philosophy. There was growing interest in western philosophical currents. Rigorously trained Polish philosophers made substantial contributions to specialized fields—topsychology , thehistory of philosophy , thetheory of knowledge , and especially mathematical logic. [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 32.]Jan Łukasiewicz gained world fame with his concept ofmany-valued logic and his "Polish notation ." [Kazimierz Kuratowski , "A Half Century of Polish Mathematics", pp. 23-24, 33.]Alfred Tarski 's work intruth theory won him world renown. [Kazimierz Kuratowski , "A Half Century of Polish Mathematics", p. 30 and "passim".]After
World War II , for over four decades, world-class Polish philosophers and historians of philosophy such asWładysław Tatarkiewicz continued their work, often in the face of adversities occasioned by the dominance of a politically enforced official philosophy.The phenomenologistRoman Ingarden did influential work inesthetics and in aHusserl -stylemetaphysics ; his studentKarol Wojtyła acquired a unique influence on the world stage as PopeJohn Paul II .cholasticism
[
Witelo ).] The formal history ofphilosophy inPoland may be said to begin in the15th century , following the revival of the University of Kraków by King Władysław II Jagiełło in 1400. [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 5.]The true beginnings of Polish philosophy, however, reach back to the
13th century andWitelo (ca. 1230 - ca. 1314), aSilesia n born to a Polish mother and aThuringia n settler, a contemporary ofThomas Aquinas who had spent part of his life inItaly at centers of the highest intellectual culture. In addition to being aphilosopher , he was ascientist who specialized inoptics . His famous treatise, "Perspectiva", while drawing on the Arabic "Book of Optics " by Alhazen, was unique inLatin literature, [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 5.] and in turn helped inspireRoger Bacon 's best work, Part V of his "Opus maius", "On Perspectival Science," as well as his supplementary treatise "On the Multiplication of Vision". [Will Durant , "The Age of Faith", p. 1011.] Witelo's "Perspectiva" additionally made important contributions topsychology : it held that vision "per se" apprehends onlycolor s andlight while all else, particularly the distance and size of objects, is established by means of association and unconscious deduction. [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 5.]Witelo's concept of
being was one rare in theMiddle Ages , neither Augustinian as among conservatives nor Aristotelian as among progressives, but Neoplatonist. It was an emanationist concept that heldradiation to be the prime characteristic of being, and ascribed to radiation the nature oflight . This "metaphysic of light" inclined Witelo to optical research, or perhaps "vice versa" his optical studies led to hismetaphysic . [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", pp. 5–6.]According to the Polish historian of philosophy,
Władysław Tatarkiewicz , no Polish philosopher sinceWitelo has enjoyed so eminent a European standing as this thinker who belonged, in a sense, to theprehistory of Polish philosophy. [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 6.]From the beginning of the
15th century , Polish philosophy, centered at Kraków University, pursued a normal course. It no longer harbored exceptional thinkers such as Witelo, but it did feature representatives of all wings of matureScholasticism , "via antiqua" as well as "via moderna". [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 6.] The first of these to reach Kraków was "via moderna", then the more widespread movement inEurope . [Tatarkiewicz, "Historia filozofii", vol. 1, p. 311.] Inphysics ,logic andethics ,Terminism (Nominalism ) prevailed in Kraków, under the influence of the French Scholastic,Jean Buridan (died ca. 1359), who had beenrector of theUniversity of Paris and an exponent of views ofWilliam of Ockham . Buridan had formulated thetheory of "impetus"—theforce that causes a body, once set inmotion , to persist in motion—and stated that impetus is proportional to thevelocity of, and amount ofmatter comprising, a body: Buridan thus anticipatedGalileo andIsaac Newton . His theory of impetus was momentous in that it also explained the motions of celestial bodies without resort to thespirit s—"intelligentiae"—to which thePeripatetics (followers ofAristotle ) had ascribed those motions. [Tatarkiewicz, "Historia filozofii", vol. 1, pp. 303–4.] AtKraków , physics was now expounded by (St.) Jan Kanty (1390-1473), who developed this concept of "impetus." [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 6.]A general trait of the Kraków
Scholastics was a provlivity forcompromise —for reconcilingNominalism with the older tradition; for example, the Nominalist, Benedict Hesse, while in principle accepting the theory ofimpetus , did not apply it to the heavenly spheres. [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 6.]In the second half of the
15th century , at Kraków, "via antiqua" became dominant.Nominalism retreated, and the oldScholasticism triumphed. [Tatarkiewicz, "Historia filozofii", vol. 1, p. 311.]In this period,
Thomism had its chief center atCologne , whence it influenced Kraków. Cologne, formerly the home ground ofAlbertus Magnus , had preserved Albert's mode of thinking. Thus the Cologne philosophers formed two wings, the Thomist and Albertist, and even Cologne's Thomists showed Neoplatonist traits characteristic of Albert, affirmingemanation , ahierarchy ofbeing , and ametaphysic oflight . [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 6.]The chief Kraków adherents of the Cologne-style Thomism included
Jan of Głogów (ca. 1445 - 1507) andJakub of Gostynin (ca. 1454 - 1506). Another teacher of Thomism wasMichał Falkener ofWrocław (ca. 1460 - 1534). [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", pp. 6–7.]Almost at the same time,
Scotism appeared in Poland, having been brought fromParis first byMichał Twaróg ofBystrzyków (ca. 1450 - 1520). Twaróg had studied at Paris in 1473-77, in the period when, following theanathema tization of theNominalist s (1473), the Scotist school was there enjoying its greatest triumphs. A prominent student of Twaróg's,Jan of Stobnica (ca. 1470 - 1519), was already a moderate Scotist who took account of the theories of theOckham ists,Thomist s and Humanists. [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 7.]When
Nominalism was revived inwestern Europe at the turn of the16th century , particularly thanks toJacques Lefèvre d'Étaples ("Faber Stapulensis"), it presently reappeared inKraków and began taking the upper hand there once more overThomism andScotism . It was reintroduced particularly by Lefèvre's pupil,Jan Szylling , a native of Kraków who had studied at Paris in the opening years of the16th century . Another follower of Lefèvre's wasGrzegorz of Stawiszyn , a Kraków professor who, beginning in 1510, published the Frenchman's works at Kraków. [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 7.]Thus
Poland had made her appearance as a separate philosophical center only at the turn of the15th century , at a time when the creative period of Scholastic philosophy had already passed. Throughout the15th century , Poland harbored all the currents of Scholasticism. The advent ofHumanism in Poland would find a Scholasticism more vigorous than in other countries. Indeed, Scholasticism would survive the 16th and 17th centuries and even part of the 18th at Kraków and Wilno Universities and at numerousJesuit , Dominican andFranciscan colleges. [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", pp. 7–8.]To be sure, in the
16th century , with the arrival of theRenaissance ,Scholasticism would enter upon a decline; but during the17th century 'sCounter-reformation , and even into the early18th century , Scholasticism would again become Poland's chief philosophy. [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", pp. 7-8.]Renaissance
The spirit of
Humanism , which had reached Poland by the middle of the15th century , was not very "philosophical." Rather, it lent its stimulus tolinguistic studies,political thought, and scientific research. But these manifested a philosophical attitude different from that of the previous period. [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 8.]Empirical natural science had flourished atKraków as early as the15th century , side by side with speculative philosophy. The most perfect product of this blossoming wasNicolaus Copernicus (1473-1543, _pl. Mikołaj Kopernik). He was not only a scientist but a philosopher. According to Tatarkiewicz, he may have been the greatest—in any case, the most renowned—philosopher that Poland ever produced. He drew the inspiration for his cardinal discovery from philosophy; he had become acquainted throughMarsilio Ficino with the philosophies ofPlato and thePythagoreans ; and through the writings of the philosophersCicero andPlutarch he had learned about theancients who had declared themselves in favor of the earth's movement. [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", pp. 8–9.] Copernicus may also have been influenced by Kraków philosophy: during his studies there, Terministphysics had been taught, with special emphasis on "impetus"." His own thinking was guided by philosophical considerations. He arrived at theheliocentric thesis (as he was to write in a youthful treatise) "ratione postea equidem sensu": it was notobservation but the discovery of alogic alcontradiction inPtolemy 's system, that served him as a point of departure that led to the new astronomy. In his dedication toPope Paul III , he submitted his work for judgment by "philosophers." [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 9.]In its turn, Copernicus' theory transformed man's view of the structure of the
universe , and of the place held in it by the earth and by man, and thus attained a far-reaching philosophical importance. [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 9.]Copernicus was involved not only in
natural science andnatural philosophy but also—by his studies in the theory of value andmoney (see "Gresham's Law ")—in the philosophy of man. [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 9.]In the early
16th century ,Plato , who had become a model for philosophy inItaly , especially in MediceanFlorence , was represented inPoland in some ways byAdam of Łowicz , author of "Conversations about Immortality". [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 9.] Generally speaking, though, Poland remained Aristotelian.Sebastian Petrycy ofPilzno (1554-1626) laid stress, in thetheory of knowledge , onexperiment andinduction ; and inpsychology , onfeeling andwill ; while inpolitics he preacheddemocratic ideas. Petrycy's central feature was his linking of philosophical theory with the requirements of practical national life. In 1601-18, a period whentranslation s intomodern language s were still rarities, he accomplished translations ofAristotle 's practical works. With Petrycy, Polish philosophicalterminology began to develop not much later than did the French and German. [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", pp. 9–10.]Yet another
Renaissance current, the newStoicism , was represented in Poland byJakub Górski (ca. 1525 - 1585), author of a famous "Dialectic" (1563) and of many works ingrammar ,rhetoric ,theology andsociology . He tended towardeclecticism , attempting to reconcile theStoics withAristotle . [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 10.]A later, purer representative of
Stoicism in Poland wasAdam Burski (ca. 1560 - 1611), author of a "Dialectica Ciceronis" (1604) boldly proclaiming Stoic sensualism andempiricism and—beforeFrancis Bacon —urging the use of inductive method. [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 10.] A star among the pleiade of progressivepolitical philosophers during thePolish Renaissance wasAndrzej Frycz Modrzewski (1503-72), who advocated on behalf of equality for all before the law, the accountability ofmonarch andgovernment to the nation, and social assistance for the weak and disadvantaged. [Tatarkiewicz, "Historia filozofii", vol. 2, p. 38.] His chief work was "De Republica emendanda" (On Reform of the Republic, 1551-54). Another notable political thinker was
thumb|150px|1733_English_translation_of_Goślicki's "De optimo senatore"Wawrzyniec Grzymała Goślicki (1530-1607), best known in Poland and abroad for his book "De optimo senatore" (The Accomplished Senator, 1568). It propounded the view—which for long got the book banned inEngland , as subversive ofmonarchy —that a ruler may legitimately govern only with the sufferance of the people. [Joseph Kasparek, "The Constitutions of Poland and of the United States: Kinships and Genealogy", pp. 245–50.]After the first decades of the
17th century , thewar s,invasion s and internaldissension s that beset thePolish-Lithuanian Commonwealth , brought a decline in philosophy. If in the ensuing period there was independent philosophical thought, it was among the religiousdissenter s, particularly the PolishArian s, [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 11.] also known variously asAntitrinitarian s,Archicatholic s,Socinian s, andPolish Brethren —forerunners of the British and American Socinians,Unitarian s andDeist s who were to figure prominently in the intellectual and political currents of the 17th, 18th and 19th centuries. [Kasparek, "The Constitutions...", pp. 218–24.]The Polish
dissenter s created an originalethical theory radically condemning evil andviolence . Centers of intellectual life such as that atLeszno hosted notable thinkers such as the Czechpedagogue ,Jan Amos Komensky (Comenius), and the Pole,Jan Jonston . Jonston was tutor and physician to theLeszczyński family, a devotee of Bacon and experimental knowledge, and author of "Naturae constantia", published inAmsterdam in 1632, whosegeometrical method and naturalistic, almostpantheistic concept of the world may have influencedBenedict Spinoza . [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 11.]The
Leszczyński family itself would produce an 18th-century Polish-Lithuanian king,Stanisław Leszczyński (1677-1766; reigned in thePolish-Lithuanian Commonwealth 1704-11 and again 1733-36), "le philosophe bienfaisant" ("the beneficent philosopher")—in fact, an independent thinker whose views onculture were in advance ofJean-Jacques Rousseau 's, and who was the first to introduce into Polish intellectual life on a large scale the French influences that were later to become so strong. [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 11.]Enlightenment
After a decline of a century and a half, in the mid-
18th century , Polish philosophy began to revive. The hub of this movement wasWarsaw . While Poland's capital then had no institution of higher learning, neither were those ofKraków ,Zamość or Wilno any longer agencies of progress. The initial impetus for the revival came from religious thinkers: from members of thePiarist and other teaching orders. A leading patron of the new ideas wasBishop Andrzej Stanisław Załuski . [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 11.]Scholasticism , which until then had dominated Polish philosophy, was followed by the Enlightenment. Initially the major influence was Christian Wolff and, indirectly,Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz . ThePolish-Lithuanian Commonwealth 's elected king,August III the Saxon , and the relations between Poland and her neighbor,Saxony , heightened the Germaninfluence . Wolff's doctrine was brought to Warsaw in 1740 by theTheatine , Portalupi; from 1743, its chief Polish champion wasWawrzyniec Mitzler de Kolof (1705-40), court physician toAugust III . [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", pp. 11–12.] Under thePolish-Lithuanian Commonwealth 's last king,Stanisław August Poniatowski (reigned 1764-95), thePolish Enlightenment was radicalized and came under French influence. The philosophical foundation of the movement ceased to be theRationalist doctrine of Wolff and became the Sensualism of Condillac. This spirit pervaded Poland'sCommission of National Education , which completed the reforms begun by thePiarist priest,Stanisław Konarski . The Commission's members were in touch with the FrenchEncyclopedists andfreethinker s, withd'Alembert andCondorcet , Condillac and Rousseau. The Commission abolished school instruction intheology , even in philosophy. [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 12.]This
empiricist andpositivist Enlightenment philosophy produced several outstanding Polish thinkers. Though active in the reign ofStanisław August Poniatowski , they published their chief works only after the loss of thePolish-Lithuanian Commonwealth 's independence in 1795. The most important of these figures wereJan Śniadecki ,Stanisław Staszic andHugo Kołłątaj . [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", pp. 12–13.]Another adherent of this empirical Enlightenment philosophy was the minister of education under the
Duchy of Warsaw and under theCongress Kingdom established by theCongress of Vienna ,Stanisław Kostka Potocki (1755-1821). In some places, as atKrzemieniec and itsLyceum in southeastern Poland, this philosophy was to survive well into the19th century . Though a belated philosophy from a western perspective, it was at the same time the philosophy of the future. This was the period betweend'Alembert and Comte; and even as this variety ofpositivism was temporarily fading in the West, it was carrying on in Poland. [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 13.]At the turn of the
19th century , asImmanuel Kant 's fame was spreading over the rest of Europe, in Poland the Enlightenment philosophy was still in full flower. Kantism found here a hostile soil. Even before Kant had been understood, he was condemned by the most respected writers of the time: byJan Śniadecki , Staszic, Kołłątaj,Tadeusz Czacki , later byAnioł Dowgird (1776-1835).Jan Śniadecki warned against this "fanatical, dark and apocalyptic mind," and wrote: "To revise Locke and Condillac, to desire "a priori" knowledge of things that human nature can grasp only by their consequences, is a lamentable aberration of mind." [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 14.]Jan Śniadecki's younger brother, however,
Jędrzej Śniadecki , was the first respected Polish scholar to declare (1799) for Kant. And in applying Kantian ideas to thenatural sciences , he did something new that would not be undertaken until much later byJohannes Müller ,Hermann Ludwig Ferdinand von Helmholtz and other famous scientists of the19th century . [Tatarkiewicz, "Historia filozofii", vol. 2, pp. 187–88.]Another Polish proponent of Kantism was
Józef Kalasanty Szaniawski (1764-1843), who had been a student of Kant's atKönigsberg . But, having accepted the fundamental points of the critical theory of knowledge, he still hesitated between Kant's metaphysical agnosticism and the new metaphysics ofIdealism . Thus this one man introduced to Poland both the antimetaphysical Kant and the post-Kantian metaphysics. [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", pp. 14–15.]In time, Kant's foremost Polish sympathizer would be
Feliks Jaroński (1777-1827), who lectured at Kraków in 1809-18. Still, his Kantian sympathies were only partial. And this half-heartedness was typical of Polish Kantism generally. In Poland there was no actual Kantian period. [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 15.]For a generation, between the age of the
French Enlightenment and that of the Polish nationalmetaphysic , the Scottish philosophy ofcommon sense became the dominant outlook in Poland. At the beginning of the19th century , theScottish School of Common Sense held sway in most European countries—in Britain till mid-century, and nearly as long in France. But in Poland, from the first, the Scottish philosophy fused with Kantism, in this regard anticipating the West. [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", pp. 15–16.]The Kantian and Scottish ideas were united in typical fashion by
Jędrzej Śniadecki (1768-1838). The younger brother ofJan Śniadecki , Jędrzej was an illustrious scientist, biologist and physician, and the more creative mind of the two. He had been educated at the universities ofKraków ,Padua andEdinburgh and was from 1796 a professor atWilno , where he held a chair ofchemistry andpharmacy . He was a foe ofmetaphysics , holding that the fathoming offirst cause s ofbeing was "impossible to fulfill and unnecessary." But foe of metaphysics that he was, he was not anEmpiricist —and this was his link with Kant. "Experiment and observation can only gather... the materials from whichcommon sense alone can build science." [Tatarkiewicz, "Historia filozofii", vol. 2, p. 189.]An analogous position, shunning both
positivism and metaphysical speculation, affined to the Scots but linked in some features to Kantiancritique , was held in the period before the November 1830 Uprising by virtually all the university professors in Poland: inWilno , by Dowgird; inKraków , byJózef Emanuel Jankowski (1790-1847); and inWarsaw , byAdam Ignacy Zabellewicz (1784-1831) andKrystyn Lach Szyrma (1791-1866). [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", pp. 16-17.]Messianism
In the early
19th century , following a generation imbued with Enlightenment ideas, Poland passed directly to a maximal philosophical program, to absolutemetaphysics , to syntheses, to greatsystem s, toreform of the world through philosophy; and broke withpositivism , the doctrines of the Enlightenment, and the precepts of Common Sense. [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 17.]The Polish metaphysical blossoming occurred between the November 1830 and January 1863 Uprisings, and stemmed from the spiritual aspirations of a politically humiliated people. [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 17.] The Poles' metaphysic, though drawing on German
Idealism , differed considerably from it; it wasSpiritualist rather than Idealist. It was characterized by atheistic belief in a personalGod , in the everlastingness ofsoul s, and in the superiority of spiritual over corporeal forces. [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 17.]The Polish metaphysic saw the mission of philosophy not only in the search for
truth , but in thereform ation of life and in thesalvation ofmankind . It was permeated with a faith in the metaphysical import of thenation and convinced that man could fulfill hisvocation only within the communion ofspirit s that was the nation, that nations determined the evolution of mankind, and more particularly that the Polish nation had been assigned the role ofMessiah to the nations. [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 17.]It was these three traits—the founding of a
metaphysic on the concept of thesoul and on the concept of thenation , and the assignment to the latter ofreform ative-soteriological tasks—that distinguished the Polish metaphysicians. Some, such as Hoene-Wroński, saw the Messiah inphilosophy itself; others, such as the poet Mickiewicz, saw Him in thePolish nation . Hence Hoene-Wroński, and later Mickiewicz, adopted for their doctrines the name, "Messianism ." It came to apply generically to Polish metaphysics of the19th century , much as the term "Idealism " does to German metaphysics. [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 18.] In the first half of the19th century , there appeared in Poland a host of metaphysicians unanimous as to these basic precepts, if strikingly at variance as to details. Their only center wasParis , which hostedJózef Maria Hoene-Wroński (1778-1853). Otherwise they lived in isolation:Bronisław Trentowski (1808-69) inGermany ;Józef Gołuchowski (1797-1858) in theCongress Kingdom ;August Cieszkowski (1814-94) andKarol Libelt (1807-75) inWielkopolska (western Poland);Józef Kremer (1806-75) inKraków . Most of them became active only after the November 1830 Uprising. [Tatarkiewicz, "Historia filozofii", vol. 2, p. 229.]An important role in the Messianist movement was also played by the Polish
Romantic poet s,Adam Mickiewicz (1798-1855),Juliusz Słowacki (1809-49) andZygmunt Krasiński (1812-59), as well as religious activists such asAndrzej Towiański (1799-1878). [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 18.]Between the
philosopher s and thepoet s, the method of reasoning, and often the results, differed. The poets desired to create a specifically "Polish" philosophy, the philosophers—an absolute "universal" philosophy. The Messianist philosophers knew contemporary European philosophy and drew from it; the poets created more of a home-grown metaphysic. [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys", p. 18.]The most important difference among the Messianists was that some were
rationalist s, others—mystics. Wroński's philosophy was no less rationalist thanHegel 's, while the poets voiced a mystical philosophy. [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 18.]The Messianists were not the only Polish philosophers active in the period between the 1830 and 1863 Uprisings. Much more widely known in Poland were
Catholic thinkers such as FatherPiotr Semeneńko (1814-86),Florian Bochwic (1779-1856) andEleonora Ziemięcka (1819-69), Poland's first woman philosopher. The Catholic philosophy of the period was more widespread and fervent than profound or creative. [Tatarkiewicz, "Historia filozofii", vol. 3, p. 173.]Also active were pure
Hegelian s such asTytus Szczeniowski (1808-80) and leftist Hegelians such asEdward Dembowski (1822-46). [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 24.]An outstanding representative of the philosophy of Common Sense,
Michał Wiszniewski (1794-1865), had studied at that Enlightenment bastion,Krzemieniec ; in 1820, inFrance , had attended the lectures ofVictor Cousin ; and in 1821, in Britain, had met the head of theScottish School of Common Sense at the time,Dugald Stewart . [Tatarkiewicz, "Historia filozofii", vol. 3, p. 174.]Active as well were s of
Positivism such asJózef Supiński (1804-93) andDominik Szulc (1797-1860)—links between the earlier Enlightenment age of the brothers Śniadecki and the coming age ofPositivism . [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 24. Tatarkiewicz, "Historia filozofii", vol. 3, p. 175.]Positivism
The Positivist philosophy that took form in Poland after the January 1863 Uprising was hardly identical with the philosophy of
Auguste Comte . It was in fact a return to the line ofJan Śniadecki andHugo Kołłątaj —a line that had remained unbroken even during the Messianist period—now enriched with the ideas of Comte. [Tatarkiewicz, "Historia filozofii", vol. 3, p. 176.] However, it belonged only partly tophilosophy . It combined Comte's ideas with those ofJohn Stuart Mill andHerbert Spencer , for it was interested in what was common to them all: a sober,empirical attitude to life. [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 25.]The Polish Positivism was a
reaction against philosophical speculation, but also againstromanticism in poetry andidealism in politics. It was less a scholarly movement than literary, political and social. Few original books were published, but many were translated from the philosophical literature of the West—not Comte himself, but easier writers:Hippolyte Taine , Mill, Spencer,Alexander Bain ,Thomas Henry Huxley , the GermansWilhelm Wundt andFriedrich Albert Lange , the Danish philosopherHöffding . [Tatarkiewicz, "Historia filozofii", vol. 3, p. 176.] The disastrous outcome of the January 1863 Uprising had produced a distrust of romanticism, an aversion to ideals and illusions, and turned the search for redemption toward sober thought and work directed at realistic goals. The watchword became "organic work"—a term for the campaign for economic improvement, which was regarded as a prime requisite for progress. Poles prepared for such work by studying thenatural sciences andeconomics : they absorbedCharles Darwin 's biological theories, Mill'seconomic theories,Henry Thomas Buckle 's deterministic theory ofcivilization . At length they became aware of the connection between their own convictions and aims and the Positivist philosophy ofAuguste Comte , and borrowed its name and watchwords. [Tatarkiewicz, "Historia filozofii", vol. 3, p. 177.]This movement, which had begun still earlier in
Austria n-ruled Galicia, became concentrated with time in theRussia n-ruledCongress Kingdom centered aboutWarsaw and is therefore commonly known as the "Warsaw Positivism." [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", pp. 25–26.] Its chief venue was the Warsaw "Przegląd Tygodniowy" (Weekly Review); [Tatarkiewicz, "Historia filozofii", vol. 3, p. 177.]Warsaw University (the "Main School") had been closed by theRussia ns in 1869. The pioneers of the Warsaw Positivism werenatural scientist s andphysician s rather than philosophers, and still more sojournalist s andmen of letters :Aleksander Świętochowski (1849-1938),Piotr Chmielowski (1848-1904),Adolf Dygasiński (1839-1902), [Tatarkiewicz, "Historia filozofii", vol. 3, p. 177.]Bolesław Prus (1847-1912). Prus developed an original Utilitarian-inspired ethical system in his book, "The Most General Life Ideals". [Edward Pieścikowski, "Bolesław Prus", pp. 138-39.]The movement's leader was Prus' friend,
Julian Ochorowicz (1850-1917), a trained philosopher with a doctorate from theUniversity of Leipzig . In 1872 he wrote: "We shall call a Positivist, anyone who bases assertions on verifiable evidence; who does not express himself categorically about doubtful things, and does not speak at all about those that are inaccessible." [Tatarkiewicz, "Historia filozofii", vol. 3, p. 177.]The Warsaw Positivists—who included faithful
Catholic s such as FatherFranciszek Krupiński (1836-98)—formed a common front against Messianism together with theNeo-Kantian s. The PolishKantian s were rather loosely associated with Kant and belonged to the Positivist movement. They includedWładysław Mieczysław Kozłowski (1858-1935),Piotr Chmielowski (1848-1904) andMarian Massonius (1862-1945). [Tatarkiewicz, "Historia filozofii", vol. 3, pp. 177–78.]The most brilliant philosophical mind in this period was
Adam Mahrburg (1855-1913). He was aPositivist in his understanding of philosophy as a discipline and in his uncompromising ferreting out of speculation, and aKantian in his interpretation of mind and in his centering of philosophy upon thetheory of knowledge . [Tatarkiewicz, "Historia filozofii", vol. 3, pp. 177-78.]In
Kraków , FatherStefan Pawlicki (1839-1916), professor of philosophy at theUniversity of Kraków , was a man of broad culture and philosophical bent, but lacked talent for writing or teaching. Under his over-thirty-year tenure, Kraków philosophy became mainly a historical discipline, alien to what was happening in the West and in Warsaw. [Tatarkiewicz, "Historia filozofii", vol. 3, p. 175.]Twentieth century
Even before Poland regained independence at the end of
World War I , her intellectual life continued to develop. This was the case particularly inRussia n-ruledWarsaw , where in lieu of underground lectures and secret scholarly organizations a "Wolna Wszechnica Polska " (Free Polish University) was created in 1905 and the tirelessWładysław Weryho (1868-1916) had in 1898 founded Poland's first philosophical journal, "Przegląd Filozoficzny" (The Philosophical Review), and in 1904 a Philosophical Society. [Tatarkiewicz, "Historia filozofii", vol. 3, p. 356.]In 1907 Weryho founded a Psychological Society, and subsequently Psychological and Philosophical Institutes. About 1910 the small number of professionally trained philosophers increased sharply, as individuals returned who had been inspired by Mahrburg's underground lectures to study philosophy in
Austria n-ruledLwów andKraków or abroad. [Tatarkiewicz, "Historia filozofii", vol. 3, p. 356.]Kraków as well, especially after 1910, saw a quickening of the philosophical movement, particularly at thePolish Academy of Learning , where upon the prompting ofWładysław Heinrich there came into being in 1911 a Committee for the History of Polish Philosophy and there was an immense growth in the number of philosophical papers and publications, no longer only of ahistorical character. [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 27.]At
Lwów ,Kazimierz Twardowski from 1895 stimulated a lively philosophical movement, in 1904 founded the Polish Philosophical Society, ["Twardowski, Kazimierz," "Encyklopedia powszechna PWN", vol. 4, p. 512.] and in 1911 began publication of "Ruch Filozoficzny " (The Philosophical Movement). [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 27.]There was growing interest in western philosophical currents, and much discussion of
Pragmatism and Bergsonism,psychoanalysis ,Henri Poincaré 'sConventionalism ,Edmund Husserl 'sPhenomenology , theMarburg School , and the social-science methodologies ofWilhelm Dilthey andHeinrich Rickert . At the same time, original ideas developed on Polish soil. [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 27.]Those who distinguished themselves in Polish philosophy in these pre-
World War I years of the20th century , formed two groups.One group developed apart from institutions of higher learning andlearned societies , and appealed less to trained philosophers than to broader circles, which it (if but briefly) captured. It constituted a reaction against the preceding period ofPositivism , and included Stanisław Brzozowski (1878-1911),Wincenty Lutosławski (1863-1954) and, to a degree,Edward Abramowski (1868-1918). [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", pp. 27–28.]The second group of philosophers who started off Polish philosophy in the
20th century had anacademic character. They includedWładysław Heinrich (1869-1957) inKraków ,Kazimierz Twardowski (1866-1938) inLwów , andLeon Petrażycki (1867-1931) abroad—all three, active members of thePolish Academy of Learning . Despite the considerable differences among them, they shared some basic features: all three wereempiricist s concerned not with metaphysics but with the foundations of philosophy; they were interested in philosophy itself, not merely its history; they understood philosophy in positive terms, but none of them was a Positivist in the old style. [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", pp. 29-30.]Following the restoration of Poland's independence in 1918, the two older universities (Kraków University,
Lwów University ) were joined by four new ones (Warsaw University ,Poznań University ,Wilno University ,Lublin University ). New philosophical journals appeared; all the university cities formed philosophical associations; conventions of Polish philosophers were held; philosophy became more professional, academic, scholarly. [Tatarkiewicz, "Historia filozofii", vol. 3, pp. 363–64.]A characteristic of the
interbellum was thatmaximalist , metaphysical currents began to fade away. [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 30.] The dominant ambition in philosophical theory now was not breadth butprecision . This was a period ofspecialization , consistent with the conviction that general philosophy would not yield precise results such as could be obtained inlogic ,psychology or thehistory of philosophy . [Tatarkiewicz, "Historia filozofii", vol. 3, p. 366.]A few individuals did develop a general philosophical outlook: notably,
Tadeusz Kotarbiński (1886-1981),Stanisław Ignacy Witkiewicz (1885-1939), andRoman Ingarden (1893-1970). [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", pp. 30–31.]Otherwise, however,
specialization was the rule. The Kraków school, true to tradition, showed an eminently historical character and produced amedievalist of world renown, FatherKonstanty Michalski (1879-1947). [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 31.] The Lwów school concentrated on the analysis ofconcept s; and in doing so, it considered both their aspects, the subjective and objective—hence, thepsychological and thelogical . Twardowski himself continued working at the border of psychology and logic; his pupils, however, generally split in their interests, specializing in either psychology or logic. [Tatarkiewicz, "Historia filozofii", vol. 3, p. 366.]The analytical program that Twardowski passed on to his pupils, and which they in turn spread throughout Poland, was affined to that of
Franz Brentano 's school (Twardowski's "alma mater ") inAustria and to that of the British analytic school, which likewise had arisen as a reaction against speculative systems. [Tatarkiewicz, "Historia filozofii", vol. 3, p. 368.]The
alumni of the Lwów school entered three distinct fields. Some devoted themselves topsychology :Stefan Błachowski (1889-1962), professor atPoznań , entirely;Władysław Witwicki (1878-1948), professor atWarsaw , partly. Others pursued thetheory of knowledge : they includedKazimierz Ajdukiewicz (1890-1963), professor atLwów , and afterWorld War II atPoznań , whose views resembledNeopositivism and who developed an original theory of radicalConventionalism . The third group worked in mathematical, or symbolic, logic. [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 31.]The most important center for mathematical logic was Warsaw. The Warsaw school of logic was headed by
Jan Łukasiewicz (1878-1956) andStanisław Leśniewski (1886-1939), professors atWarsaw University , and the first of their pupils to achieve eminence, even beforeWorld War II , wasAlfred Tarski (1902-83), [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 31.] from 1939 in theUnited States , where he became a professor at theUniversity of California, Berkeley ; another pupil of Łukasiewicz,Bolesław Sobociński , became a professor at theUniversity of Notre Dame . The Warsaw logic gained a world-wide importance similar to that of the Krakówmedievalism . [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 31.]Warsaw was not, however, the sole Polish venue for logic studies. These were initiated at
Kraków by the mathematics professor,Jan Sleszyński . At Kraków, too, and later atLwów , they were conducted byLeon Chwistek (1884-1944), a multi-faceted and somewhat eccentric thinker—mathematician, philosopher, esthetician, painter—whose name came to be associated popularly with his concept of "plural realities." [Tatarkiewicz, "Historia filozofii", vol. 3, p. 367.]After Petrażycki's death, the outstanding
legal philosopher wasCzesław Znamierowski (1888-1967), professor of philosophy at Poznań. [Tatarkiewicz, "Historia filozofii", vol. 3, pp. 367–68.] Another leading thinker of the period, active on the borderlines ofsociology andphilosophy , in bothPoland and theUnited States , wasFlorian Znaniecki (1882-1958). [Tatarkiewicz, "Historia filozofii", vol. 3, p. 361.]In the
interbellum , the philosopher members of thePolish Academy of Learning included Heinrich (Kraków), Twardowski (Lwów), Petrażycki (Warsaw), and, from the following generation: Michalski, Łukasiewicz andWładysław Tatarkiewicz (1886-1980). Michalski's historical works revolutionized prevailing views on "via moderna" in latemedieval philosophy . Łukasiewicz gained world fame with his concept ofmany-valued logic and is known for his "Polish notation ." Tatarkiewicz was the first to prepare in Polish a large-scale comprehensive history ofwestern philosophy and a "History of Aesthetics" and worked at systematizing theconcept s ofesthetics andethics . [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", pp. 31–32.]After
World War II ,Roman Ingarden ,Tadeusz Kotarbiński andAlfred Tarski became members of the Academy. [Tatarkiewicz, "Zarys...", p. 32.]For some four decades following World War II, in Poland, a disproportionately prominent official role was given to
Marxist philosophy . This, and contemporaneous sociopolitical currents, stimulatedLeszek Kołakowski , writing inexile , to publish influential critiques ofMarxist theory andcommunist practice. Kołakowski also wrote a remarkable history of "Positivist Philosophy from Hume to the Vienna Circle". [Leszek Kołakowski , "Positivist Philosophy from Hume to the Vienna Circle", Penguin Books, 1972, ASIN B000OIXO7E.]Similarly notable for his critiques of
Soviet Marxism wasJózef Maria Bocheński , a Catholic philosopher lecturing inFribourg ,Switzerland , who also produced work inlogic andethics .Other Polish philosophers of the postwar period included
Andrzej Zabłudowski , who engaged in noted polemics withNelson Goodman , andMarek Siemek , a historian of GermanTranscendental Philosophy and recipient of anhonorary doctorate fromBonn University .ee also
*
History of philosophy
*
*List of PolesNotes
References
*
Władysław Tatarkiewicz , "Historia filozofii" (History of Philosophy), 3 vols., Warsaw,Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe , 1978.
*Władysław Tatarkiewicz , "Zarys dziejów filozofii w Polsce" (A Brief History of Philosophy in Poland), [in the series:] "Historia nauki polskiej w monografiach" (History of Polish Learning in Monographs), [volume] XXXII, Kraków, "Polska Akademia Umiejętności" (Polish Academy of Learning ), 1948. This monograph draws from pertinent sections in earlier editions of the author's "Historia filozofii" (History of Philosophy).
*Will Durant , "The Age of Faith: A History of Medieval Civilization – Christian, Islamic, and Judaic – from Constantine toDante : A.D. 325-1300", [in the series:] "The Story ofCivilization ", New York,Simon and Schuster , 1950.
* Joseph Kasparek, "The Constitutions of Poland and of the United States: Kinships and Genealogy", Miami, American Institute of Polish Culture, 1980.
* Edward Pieścikowski, "Bolesław Prus ", 2nd edition, Warsaw,Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe , 1985.
*Kazimierz Kuratowski , "A Half Century of Polish Mathematics: Remembrances and Reflections", Oxford,Pergamon Press , 1973, ISBN 0-08-023046-6.
*Leszek Kołakowski , "Positivist Philosophy from Hume to the Vienna Circle", Penguin Books, 1972.
* [http://www.fmag.unict.it/~fconiglione/Sito/Home_Coniglione.html Francesco Coniglione] , "Nel segno della scienza. La filosofia polacca del Novecento", FrancoAngeli, Milano,1996.
* "Encyklopedia Powszechna PWN " (PWN Universal Encyclopedia), 4 vols., Warsaw,Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe , 1976.
* "Encyklopedia Polski ", Kraków, Wydawnictwo Ryszard Kluszczyński, 1996.
* "Polski słownik biograficzny".
* "ZNAK ", 5/2005/600, pp. 23-102.External links
* [http://skowronski.krzysztof.w.interia.pl/Contemporary%20Updated%20Nov.htm Dr. Skowroński, Contemporary Polish Philosophy (for foreign students)]
* [http://www.fmag.unict.it/~polphil/PolHome.html Polish Philosophy Page]
Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.