- Category theory
In
mathematics , category theory deals in an abstract way with mathematicalstructures and relationships between them: it abstracts from "sets" and "functions" to "objects" and "morphism s". Categories now appear in most branches of mathematics and in some areas oftheoretical computer science andmathematical physics , and have been a unifying notion. Categories were first introduced bySamuel Eilenberg andSaunders Mac Lane in 1942-1945, in connection withalgebraic topology .Category theory has several faces known not just to specialists, but to other mathematicians. A term dating from the 1940s, "
general abstract nonsense ", refers to its high level of abstraction, compared to more classical branches of mathematics.Homological algebra is category theory in its aspect of organising and suggesting calculations inabstract algebra .Diagram chasing is a visual method of arguing with abstract 'arrows'.Topos theory is a form of abstractsheaf theory , with geometric origins, and leads to ideas such aspointless topology .Background
The study of categories is an attempt to "axiomatically" capture what is commonly found in various classes of related "mathematical structures" by relating them to the "structure-preserving functions" between them. A systematic study of category theory then allows us to prove general results about any of these types of mathematical structures from the axioms of a category.
Consider the following example. The class Grp of groups consists of all objects having a "group structure". More precisely, Grp consists of all sets "G" endowed with a
binary operation satisfying a certain set ofaxiom s. One can proceed to provetheorem s about groups by making logical deductions from the set of axioms. For example, it is immediately proved from the axioms that theidentity element of a group is unique.Instead of focusing merely on the individual objects (e.g. groups) possessing a given structure, category theory emphasizes the
morphism s — the structure-preserving mappings — between these objects. It turns out that by studying these morphisms, we are able to learn more about the structure of the objects. In the case of groups, the morphisms are thegroup homomorphism s. A group homomorphism between two groups "preserves the group structure" in a precise sense — it is a "process" taking one group to another, in a way that carries along information about the structure of the first group into the second group. The study of group homomorphisms then provides a tool for studying general properties of groups and consequences of the group axioms.A similar type of investigation occurs in many mathematical theories, such as the study of
continuous maps betweentopological space s intopology and the study ofsmooth function s inmanifold theory .If one axiomatizes relations instead of
function s, one obtains the theory of allegories.Functors
Abstracting again, a category is "itself" a type of mathematical structure, so we can look for 'processes' which preserve this structure in some sense. Such a process is called a
functor . It associates to every object of one category an object of another category; and to every morphism in the first category a morphism in the second.In fact, what we have done is define a category "of categories and functors" – the objects are categories, and the morphisms (between categories) are functors.
By studying categories and functors, we are not just studying a class of mathematical structures and the morphisms between them, we are studying the "relationships between various classes of mathematical structures". This is a fundamental idea, which first surfaced in
algebraic topology . Difficult "topological" questions can be translated into "algebraic" questions which are often easier to solve. Basic constructions, such as thefundamental group of atopological space , can be expressed as functors in this way, and the concept is pervasive in algebra and its applications.Natural transformation
Abstracting yet again, constructions are often "naturally related", a vague notion at first sight. This leads to the clarifying concept of
natural transformation , a way to "map" one functor to another. Many important constructions in mathematics can be studied in this context. 'Naturality' is a principle, likegeneral covariance in physics, that cuts deeper than is initially apparent.Historical notes
In 1942-45,
Samuel Eilenberg andSaunders Mac Lane were the first to introduce categories, functors, and natural transformations, as part of their work intopology , especiallyalgebraic topology . Their work was an important part of the transition from intuitive and geometric homology toaxiom atichomology theory . Eilenberg and Mac Lane later wrote that their goal was to understand natural transformations; in order to do that, functors had to be defined, which required categories.Stanislaw Ulam , and some writing on his behalf, have claimed that related ideas were current in the late 1930s in Poland. Eilenberg was Polish and studied mathematics there in the 1930s. Category theory is also, in some sense, a continuation ofEmmy Noether 's (one of Mac Lane's teachers) work in formalizing abstract processes. Noether realized that in order to understand a type of mathematical structure, one needs to understand the processes preserving this structure. In order to achieve this understanding, Eilenberg and Mac Lane proposed anaxiom atic formalization of the relation between structures and the processes preserving them.The subsequent development of category theory was powered first by the computational needs of
homological algebra ; and later by the axiomatic needs ofalgebraic geometry , the field most resistant to being grounded in eitheraxiomatic set theory or theRussell-Whitehead view of united foundations. General category theory, an extension ofuniversal algebra having many new features allowing forsemantic flexibility andhigher-order logic , came later; it is now applied throughout mathematics.Certain categories called topoi (singular "topos") can even serve as an alternative to
axiomatic set theory as a foundation of mathematics. These foundational applications of category theory have been worked out in fair detail as a basis for, and justification of, constructive mathematics. More recent efforts to introduce undergraduates to categories as a foundation for mathematics include Lawvere and Rosebrugh (2003) and Lawvere and Schanuel (1997).Categorical logic is now a well-defined field based ontype theory forintuitionistic logic s, with applications infunctional programming anddomain theory , where acartesian closed category is taken as a non-syntactic description of alambda calculus . At the very least, category theoretic language clarifies what exactly these related areas have in common (in some sense).Categories, objects and morphisms
A "category" "C" consists of the following three mathematical entities:
* A class ob("C") of "objects";
* A class hom("C") ofmorphism s. Each morphism "f" has a unique "source object a" and "target object b". We write "f": "a" → "b", and we say "f" is a morphism from "a" to "b". We write hom("a", "b") [or Hom("a", "b"), or hom"C"("a", "b")] to denote the "hom-class" of all morphisms from "a" to "b". (Some authors write Mor("a", "b") or C("a", "b").)
* Abinary operation , called "composition of morphisms", such that for any three objects "a", "b", and "c", we have hom("a", "b") × hom("b", "c") → hom("a", "c"). The composition of "f": "a" → "b" and "g": "b" → "c" is written as or "gf" (some authors write "fg"), governed by two axioms::*Associativity : If "f" : "a" → "b", "g" : "b" → "c" and "h" : "c" → "d" then , and:* Identity: For every object "x", there exists a morphism 1"x" : "x" → "x" called the "identity morphism for x", such that for every morphism "f" : "a" → "b", we have .From these axioms, it can be proved that there is exactly one
identity morphism for every object. Some authors deviate from the definition just given by identifying each object with its identity morphism.Relations among morphisms (such as "fg" = "h") are often depicted using
commutative diagram s, with "points" (corners) representing objects and "arrows" representing morphisms. The influence of commutative diagrams has been such that "arrow" andmorphism are nowsynonymous .Properties of morphisms
Some morphisms have important properties. A morphism "f" : "a" → "b" is:
* amonomorphism (or "monic") if "f"o"g"1 = "f"o"g"2 implies "g"1 = "g"2 for all morphisms "g"1, "g2" : "x" → "a".
* anepimorphism (or "epic") if "g"1o"f" = "g"2o"f" implies "g1" = "g2" for all morphisms "g1", "g2" : "b" → "x".
* anisomorphism if there exists a morphism "g" : "b" → "a" with "f"o"g" = 1"b" and "g"o"f" = 1"a". [Note that a morphism that is both epic and monic is not necessarily an isomorphism! For example, in the category consisting of two objects "A" and "B", the identity morphisms, and a single morphism "f" from "A" to "B", "f" is both epic and monic but is not an isomorphism.]
* anendomorphism if "a" = "b". end("a") denotes the class of endomorphisms of "a".
* anautomorphism if "f" is both an endomorphism and an isomorphism. aut("a") denotes the class of automorphisms of "a".Functors
Functor s are structure-preserving maps between categories. They can be thought of as morphisms in the category of all (small) categories.A (covariant) functor "F" from a category "C" to a category "D", written "F":"C" → "D", consists of:
* for each object "x" in "C", an object "F"("x") in "D"; and
* for each morphism "f" : "x" → "y" in "C", a morphism "F"("f") : "F"("x") → "F"("y"),such that the following two properties hold:
* For every object "x" in "C",
* For all morphisms "f" : "x" → "y" and "g" : "y" → "z",A contravariant functor "F": "C" → "D", is like a covariant functor, except that it "turns morphisms around" ("reverses all the arrows"). More specifically, every morphism "f" : "x" → "y" in "C" must be assigned to a morphism "F"("f") : "F"("y") → "F"("x") in "D". In other words, a contravariant functor is a covariant functor from the
opposite category "C"op to "D".Natural transformations and isomorphisms
A "natural transformation" is a relation between two functors. Functors often describe "natural constructions" and natural transformations then describe "natural homomorphisms" between two such constructions. Sometimes two quite different constructions yield "the same" result; this is expressed by a natural isomorphism between the two functors.
If "F" and "G" are (covariant) functors between the categories "C" and "D", then a natural transformation from "F" to "G" associates to every object "x" in "C" a morphism η"x" : "F"("x") → "G"("x") in "D" such that for every morphism "f" : "x" → "y" in "C", we have η"y" o "F"("f") = "G"("f") o η"x"; this means that the following diagram is commutative:
The two functors "F" and "G" are called "naturally isomorphic" if there exists a natural transformation from "F" to "G" such that η"x" is an isomorphism for every object "x" in "C".
Universal constructions, limits, and colimits
Using the language of category theory, many areas of mathematical study can be cast into appropriate categories, such as the categories of all sets, groups, topologies, and so on. These categories surely have some objects that are "special" in a certain way, such as the
empty set or the product of two topologies. Yet, in the definition of a category, objects are considered to be atomic; i.e., "we do not know" whether an object "A" is a set, a topology, or any other abstract concept. Hence, the challenge is to define special objects without referring to the internal structure of these objects. But how can we define the empty set without referring to elements, or the product topology without referring to open sets?The solution is to characterize these objects in terms of their relations to other objects, as given by the morphisms of the respective categories. Thus the task is to find "universal properties" that uniquely determine the objects of interest. Indeed, it turns out that numerous important constructions can be described in a purely categorical way. The central concept which is needed for this purpose is called categorical "limit", and can be dualized to yield the notion of a "colimit".
Equivalent categories
It is a natural question to ask, under which conditions two categories can be considered to be "essentially the same", in the sense that theorems about one category can readily be transformed into theorems about the other category. The major tool one employs to describe such a situation is called "equivalence of categories". It is given by appropriate functors between two categories. Categorical equivalence has found numerous applications in mathematics.
Further concepts and results
The definitions of categories and functors provide only the very basics of categorical algebra. Additional important topics are listed below. Although there are strong interrelations between all of these topics, the given order can be considered as a guideline for further reading.
* Thefunctor category "D""C" has as objects the functors from "C" to "D" and as morphisms the natural transformations of such functors. TheYoneda lemma is one of the most famous basic results of category theory; it describes representable functors in functor categories.
* Duality: Every statement, theorem, or definition in category theory has a "dual" which is essentially obtained by "reversing all the arrows". If one statement is true in a category "C" then its dual will be true in the dual category "C"op. This duality, which is transparent at the level of category theory, is often obscured in applications and can lead to surprising relationships.
*Adjoint functors : A functor can be left (or right) adjoint to another functor that maps in the opposite direction. Such a pair of adjoint functors typically arises from a construction defined by a universal property; it can be seen as a more abstract and powerful view on universal properties.Higher-dimensional categories
Many of the above concepts, especially equivalence of categories, adjoint functor pairs, and functor categories, can be situated into the context of "higher-dimensional categories". Briefly, if we consider a morphism between two objects as a "process taking us from one object to another", then higher-dimensional categories allow us to profitably generalize this by considering "higher-dimensional processes".
For example, a (strict)
2-category is a category together with "morphisms between morphisms", i.e. processes which allow us to transform one morphism into another. We can then "compose" these "bimorphisms" both horizontally and vertically, and we require a 2-dimensional "exchange law" to hold, relating the two composition laws. In this context, the standard example is Cat, the 2-category of all (small) categories, and in this example, bimorphisms of morphisms are simplynatural transformation s of morphisms in the usual sense. Another basic example is to consider a 2-category with a single object—these are essentially monoidal categories. Bicategories are a weaker notion of 2-dimensional categories where the composition of morphisms is not strictly associative, but only associative "up to" an isomorphism.This process can be extended for all
natural number s "n", and these are called "n"-categories. There is even a notion of "ω-category" corresponding to theordinal number ω. For a conversational introduction to these ideas, see [http://math.ucr.edu/home/baez/week73.html Baez (1996).]See also
*
List of category theory topics
* Important publications in category theory
*Glossary of category theory
*Domain theory
* Enriched category theory
*Higher category theory
*Timeline of category theory and related mathematics Notes
References
Freely available online:
* Adámek, Jiří, Herrlich, Horst, & Strecker, George E. (1990) [http://katmat.math.uni-bremen.de/acc/acc.htm "Abstract and concrete categories"] . John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 0-471-60922-6.
* Freyd, Peter J. (1964) " [http://www.tac.mta.ca/tac/reprints/articles/3/tr3abs.html Abelian Categories.] " New York: Harper and Row.
* Michael Barr and Charles Wells (1999) " [http://folli.loria.fr/cds/1999/library/pdf/barrwells.pdf Category Theory Lecture Notes.] " Based on their book "Category Theory for Computing Science".
* -------- (2002) [http://www.cwru.edu/artsci/math/wells/pub/ttt.html "Toposes, triples and theories.] " Revised and corrected translation of "Grundlehren der mathematischen Wissenschaften" (Springer-Verlag, 1983).
* Leinster, Tom (2004) " [http://www.maths.gla.ac.uk/~tl/book.html Higher operads, higher categories] " (London Math. Society Lecture Note Series 298). Cambridge Univ. Press.
* Schalk, A. and Simmons, H. (2005) " [http://www.cs.man.ac.uk/~hsimmons/BOOKS/CatTheory.pdf An introduction to Category Theory in four easy movements.] " Notes for a course offered as part of the MSc. inMathematical Logic ,Manchester University .
* Turi, Daniele (1996-2001) " [http://www.dcs.ed.ac.uk/home/dt/CT/categories.pdf Category Theory Lecture Notes.] " Based on Mac Lane (1998).
* Goldblatt, R (1984) [http://dlxs2.library.cornell.edu/cgi/t/text/text-idx?c=math;cc=math;view=toc;subview=short;idno=Gold010 "Topoi: the Categorial Analyis of Logic"] A clear introduction to categories, with particular emphasis on the recent applications to logic.
* A. Martini, H. Ehrig, and D. Nunes (1996) [http://citeseer.ist.psu.edu/martini96element.html "Elements of Basic Category Theory"] (Technical Report 96-5, Technical University Berlin)Other:
* Awodey, Steven (2006) "Category Theory" (Oxford Logic Guides 49). Oxford University Press.
* Borceux, Francis (1994) "Handbook of categorical algebra" (Encyclopedia of Mathematics and its Applications 50-52). Cambridge Univ. Press.
* Freyd, Peter J. & [http://www.cis.upenn.edu/~scedrov/ Scedrov, Andre] , (1990) "Categories, allegories" (North Holland Mathematical Library 39). North Holland.
*Hatcher, William S. (1982) "The Logical Foundations of Mathematics", 2nd ed. Pergamon. Chpt. 8 is an idiosyncratic introduction to category theory, presented as afirst order theory .
* Lawvere, William, & Rosebrugh, Robert (2003) "Sets for mathematics". Cambridge University Press.
* Lawvere, William, & Schanuel, Steve (1997) "Conceptual mathematics: a first introduction to categories". Cambridge University Press.
* Mac Lane, Saunders (1998) "Categories for the Working Mathematician ". 2nd ed. (Graduate Texts in Mathematics 5). Springer-Verlag.
*-------- andGarrett Birkhoff (1967) "Algebra". 1999 reprint of the 2nd ed., Chelsea. ISBN 0-8218-1646-2. An introduction to the subject making judicious use of category theoretic concepts, especiallycommutative diagram s.
*May, Peter (1999) "A Concise Course in Algebraic Topology". University of Chicago Press, ISBN 0-226-51183-9.
*Pedicchio, Maria Cristina & Tholen, Walter (2004) "Categorical foundations" (Encyclopedia of Mathematics and its Applications 97). Cambridge Univ. Press.
*Taylor, Paul, 1999. "Practical Foundations of Mathematics". Cambridge University Press. An introduction to the connection between category theory andconstructive mathematics .
*Pierce, Benjamin, 1991. "Basic Category Theory for Computer Scientists". MIT Press.External links
*
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy : " [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/category-theory/ Category Theory] " -- by Jean-Pierre Marquis. Extensive bibliography.
* [http://www.mta.ca/~cat-dist/categories.html Homepage of the Categories mailing list,] with extensive resource list.
* Baez, John, 1996," [http://math.ucr.edu/home/baez/week73.html The Tale of "n"-categories.] " An informal introduction to higher order categories.
* [http://www.youtube.com/user/TheCatsters The catsters] " a Youtube channel about category theory.
*planetmath reference|id=5622|title=Category Theory
* [http://categorieslogicphysics.wikidot.com/ Categories, Logic and the Foundations of Physics] , Webpage dedicated to the use of Categories and Logic in the Foundations of Physics.
Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.