Completeness (order theory)

Completeness (order theory)

In the mathematical area of order theory, completeness properties assert the existence of certain infima or suprema of a given partially ordered set (poset). A special use of the term refers to complete partial orders or complete lattices. However, many other interesting notions of completeness exist.

The motivation for considering completeness properties derives from the great importance of suprema (least upper bounds, joins, "\vee") and infima (greatest lower bounds, meets, "\wedge") to the theory of partial orders. Finding a supremum means to single out one distinguished least element from the set of upper bounds. On the one hand, these special elements often embody certain concrete properties that are interesting for the given application (such as being the least common multiple of a set of numbers or the union of a collection of sets). On the other hand, the knowledge that certain types of subsets are guaranteed to have suprema or infima enables us to consider the computation of these elements as total operations on a partially ordered set. For this reason, posets with certain completeness properties can often be described as algebraic structures of a certain kind. In addition, studying the properties of the newly obtained operations yields further interesting subjects.

Contents

Types of completeness properties

All completeness properties are described along a similar scheme: one describes a certain class of subsets of a partially ordered set that are required to have a supremum or infimum. Hence every completeness property has its dual, obtained by inverting the order-dependent definitions in the given statement. Some of the notions are usually not dualized while others may be self-dual (i.e. equivalent to their dual statements).

Least and greatest elements

The easiest example of a supremum is the empty one, i.e. the supremum of the empty set. By definition, this is the least element among all elements that are greater than each member of the empty set. But this is just the least element of the whole poset. Other common names for the least element are bottom and zero (0). The dual notion, the empty lower bound, is the greatest element, top, or unit (1).

Posets that have a bottom are sometimes called pointed, while posets with a top are called unital or topped. An order that has both a least and a greatest element is bounded. However, this should not be confused with the notion of bounded completeness given below.

Finite completeness

Further simple completeness conditions arise from the consideration of all non-empty finite sets. An order in which all finite sets have both a supremum and an infimum is called a lattice. It is easy to see that it suffices to require that all suprema and infima of two elements exist to obtain all finite ones. A straightforward induction shows that every finite non-empty supremum/infimum can be decomposed into a finite number of binary suprema/infima. Thus the central operations of lattices are binary suprema \vee and infima \wedge. It is in this context that the terms meet for \wedge and join for \vee are most common.

A poset in which only non-empty finite suprema are known to exist is therefore called a join-semilattice. The dual notion is meet-semilattice.

Further completeness conditions

The strongest form of completeness is the existence of all suprema and all infima. The posets with this property are the complete lattices. However, using the given order, one can restrict to further classes of (possibly infinite) subsets, that do not yield this strong completeness at once.

If all directed subsets of a poset have a supremum, then the order is a directed complete partial order or dcpo. These are especially important in domain theory. The seldom considered dual notion of a dcpo is the filtered complete poset. Dcpos with a least element ("pointed dcpos") are called complete partial order or cpo.

If every subset that has some upper bounds has also a least upper bound, then the respective poset is called bounded complete. The term is used widely with this definition that focuses on suprema and there is no common name for the dual property. However, bounded completeness can be expressed in terms of other completeness conditions that are easily dualized (see below). Although concepts with the names "complete" and "bounded" were already defined, confusion is unlikely to occur since one would rarely speak of a "bounded complete poset" when meaning a "bounded cpo" (which is just a "cpo with greatest element"). Likewise, "bounded complete lattice" is almost unambiguous, since one would not state the boundedness property for complete lattices, where it is implied anyway. Also note that the empty set usually has upper bounds (if the poset is non-empty) and thus a bounded complete poset has a least element.

One may also consider the subsets of a poset which are totally ordered, i.e. the chains. If all chains have a supremum, the order is called chain-complete (sometimes also "omega-complete", written ω-complete). Again, this concept is rarely needed in the dual form.

Relationships between completeness properties

It was already observed that binary meets/joins yield all non-empty finite meets/joins. Likewise, many other (combinations) of the above conditions are equivalent.

  • The most well-known example is the existence of all suprema, which is in fact equivalent to the existence of all infima. Indeed, for any subset X of a poset, one can consider its set of lower bounds B. The supremum of B is then equal to the infimum of X: since each element of X is an upper bound of B, sup B is smaller than all elements of X, i.e. sup B is in B. It is obvious that it is the greatest element of B and hence the infimum of X. In a dual way, the existence of all infima implies the existence of all suprema.
  • Bounded completeness can also be characterized differently. By an argument similar to the above, one finds that the supremum of a set with upper bounds is the infimum of the set of upper bounds. Consequently, bounded completeness is equivalent to the existence of all non-empty lower bounded infima.
  • A poset is a complete lattice if and only if it is a cpo and a join-semilattice. Indeed, for any subset X, the set of all finite suprema (joins) of X is directed and the supremum of this set (which exists by directed completeness) is equal to the supremum of X. Thus every set has a supremum and by the above observation we have a complete lattice. The other direction of the proof is trivial.
A poset is chain-complete if and only if it is a dcpo.

Completions of domains

According to Clinger [1981], often there is an intuitive sense in which some elements of partially ordered sets are finite. E.g., in denotational semantics, they may be partial functions defined for only finitely many values or they may be finite partial computations in the Actor model. This sense of finiteness lies behind the following abstract definition:

Let (D, ≤) be a partially ordered set. An element xD is isolated if and only if whenever AD is directed, ∪A exists and x≤∪A, there exists aA with xa. In other words, x is isolated if one must go through x to get up to or above x via the limit process. As examples, the finite sets are the isolated elements of the power set of ω ordered by inclusion; the ordinal ω+1 is isolated in the set of countable ordinals under the usual ordering.

The least element of a partially ordered set is always isolated provided it exists. 0 is the least element of the nonnegative rationals under the usual ordering, and it is also the only isolated element. The entire set of rationals has no isolated elements under the usual ordering.

For purposes of programming language semantics, partially ordered sets with least elements form too general a category. The partially ordered sets of greatest interest for computer science are those whose isolated elements are dense in the sense that every element is a least upper bound of a countable set of isolated elements. To avoid transfinite induction, and to make directed completeness equivalent to ω-completeness, it is convenient to assume also that there are only countably many isolated elements which motivates the following definition.

Definition. A domain is a partially ordered set (D, ≤) such that
  1. D has a least element Λ
  2. Every element of D is the least upper bound of a countable increasing sequence of isolated elements.
  3. The isolated elements of D are countable.

The above definition is a generalization of the traditional definition. The traditional definition requires also that D be ω-complete, so that ω-continuous functions from D to D will have fixed points.

An ω-complete domain is complete in the sense that every directed subset has a least upper bound. An ω-complete domain is also known as a countably algebraic complete partial order [Smyth 1978].

Every domain D can be embedded in an ω-complete domain completion[D] (called the ω-completion or simply the completion of D) that is, in a precise sense, the smallest ω-complete domain containing D. The isolated elements of completion[D] are precisely the isolated elements of D,[1] but in general completion[D] contains limit points that are not found in D. completion[D] is uniquely determined up to isomorphism. In Clinger [1981], it is shown that for any domain D the power domain of D is isomorphic to the power domain of completion[D]. So why not use ω-complete domains only, as is traditional? Because the power domain is interpreted with reference to the domain from which it is built. As explained in denotational semantics of concurrency, the underlying domain is incomplete in Actor semantics.

Completeness in terms of universal algebra

As explained above, the presence of certain completeness conditions allows to regard the formation of certain suprema and infima as total operations of an ordered set. It turns out that in many cases it is possible to characterize completeness solely by considering appropriate algebraic structures in the sense of universal algebra, which are equipped with operations like \vee or \wedge. By imposing additional conditions (in form of suitable identities) on these operations, one can then indeed derive the underlying partial order exclusively from such algebraic structures. Details on this characterization can be found in the articles on the "lattice-like" structures for which this is typically considered: see semilattice, lattice, Heyting algebra, and Boolean algebra. Note that the latter two structures extend the application of these principles beyond mere completeness requirements by introducing an additional operation of negation.

Completeness in terms of adjunctions

Another interesting way to characterize completeness properties is provided through the concept of (monotone) Galois connections, i.e. adjunctions between partial orders. In fact this approach offers additional insights both in the nature of many completeness properties and in the importance of Galois connections for order theory. The general observation on which this reformulation of completeness is based is that the construction of certain suprema or infima provides left or right adjoint parts of suitable Galois connections.

Consider a partially ordered set (X, ≤). As a first simple example, let 1 = {*} be a specified one-element set with the only possible partial ordering. There is an obvious mapping j: X → 1 with j(x) = * for all x in X. Now it is easy to see that X has a least element if and only if the function j has a lower adjoint j*: 1 → X. Indeed the definition for Galois connections yields that in this case j*(*) ≤ x if and only if * ≤ j(x), where the right hand side obviously holds for any x. Dually, the existence of an upper adjoint for j is equivalent to X having a greatest element.

Another simple mapping is the function q: X → (X x X) given by q(x) = (x, x). Naturally, the intended ordering relation for (X x X) is just the usual product order. Now it is easy to see that q has a lower adjoint q* if and only if all binary joins in X exist. Conversely, the join operation \vee: (X x X) → X can always provide the (necessarily unique) lower adjoint for q. Dually, q allows for an upper adjoint if and only if X has all binary meets. Thus the meet operation \wedge, if it exists, always is an upper adjoint. If both \vee and \wedge exist and, in addition, \wedge is also a lower adjoint, then the poset X is a Heyting algebra -- another important special class of partial orders.

Further completeness statements can be obtained by exploiting suitable completion procedures. For example, it is well-known that the collection of all lower sets of a poset X, ordered by subset inclusion, yields a complete lattice D(X) (the downset-lattice). Furthermore, there is an obvious embedding e: XD(X) that maps each element x of X to its principal ideal {y in X | yx}. A little reflection now shows that e has a lower adjoint if and only if X is a complete lattice. In fact, this lower adjoint will map any lower set of X to its supremum in X. Composing this with the function that maps any subset of X to its lower closure (again an adjunction for the inclusion of lower sets in the powerset), one obtains the usual supremum map from the powerset 2X to X. As before, another important situation occurs whenever this supremum map is also an upper adjoint: in this case the complete lattice X is constructively completely distributive. See also the articles on complete distributivity and distributivity (order theory).

The considerations in this section suggest a reformulation of (parts of) order theory in terms of category theory, where properties are usually expressed by referring to the relationships (morphisms, more specifically: adjunctions) between objects, instead of considering their internal structure. For more detailed considerations of this relationship see the article on the categorical formulation of order theory.

See also

Notes

  1. ^ Hence completion[D] differs from completions that do not preserve least upper bounds, such as the basis completion [Markowsky and Rosen 1976] and the ω-completion of [Bloom 1976]. completion[D] is isomorphic to the basis completion of {xD | x is isolated in D}. Traditional notions of completeness a can be found in any textbook in this area. See especially the literature for order theory.

References

  • G. Markowsky and B.K. Rosen. Bases for chain-complete posets IBM Journal of Research and Development. March 1976.
  • Stephen Bloom. Varieties of ordered algebras Journal of Computer and System Sciences. October 1976.
  • Michael Smyth. Power domains Journal of Computer and System Sciences. 1978.
  • Daniel Lehmann. On the algebra of order Journal of Computer and System Sciences. August 1980.
  • Will Clinger, Foundations of Actor Semantics. MIT Mathematics Doctoral Dissertation, June 1981.

Actor model


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Нужно сделать НИР?

Look at other dictionaries:

  • List of order theory topics — Order theory is a branch of mathematics that studies various kinds of binary relations that capture the intuitive notion of ordering, providing a framework for saying when one thing is less than or precedes another. An alphabetical list of many… …   Wikipedia

  • Order theory — For a topical guide to this subject, see Outline of order theory. Order theory is a branch of mathematics which investigates our intuitive notion of order using binary relations. It provides a formal framework for describing statements such as… …   Wikipedia

  • Glossary of order theory — This is a glossary of some terms used in various branches of mathematics that are related to the fields of order, lattice, and domain theory. Note that there is a structured list of order topics available as well. Other helpful resources might be …   Wikipedia

  • Ideal (order theory) — In mathematical order theory, an ideal is a special subset of a partially ordered set (poset). Although this term historically was derived from the notion of a ring ideal of abstract algebra, it has subsequently been generalized to a different… …   Wikipedia

  • Completeness of the real numbers — Intuitively, completeness implies that there are not any “gaps” (in Dedekind s terminology) or “missing points” in the real number line. This contrasts with the rational numbers, whose corresponding number line has a “gap” at each irrational… …   Wikipedia

  • Completeness — In general, an object is complete if nothing needs to be added to it. This notion is made more specific in various fields. Contents 1 Logical completeness 2 Mathematical completeness 3 Computing 4 …   Wikipedia

  • Theory (mathematical logic) — This article is about theories in a formal language, as studied in mathematical logic. For other uses, see Theory (disambiguation). In mathematical logic, a theory (also called a formal theory) is a set of sentences in a formal language. Usually… …   Wikipedia

  • Lattice (order) — See also: Lattice (group) The name lattice is suggested by the form of the Hasse diagram depicting it. Shown here is the lattice of partitions of a four element set {1,2,3,4}, ordered by the relation is a refinement of . In mathematics, a… …   Wikipedia

  • List of order topics — This is a list of order topics, by Wikipedia page.An alphabetical list of many notions of order theory can be found in the order theory glossary. See also inequality, extreme value, optimization (mathematics), domain theory.Basic… …   Wikipedia

  • Gödel's completeness theorem — is a fundamental theorem in mathematical logic that establishes a correspondence between semantic truth and syntactic provability in first order logic. It was first proved by Kurt Gödel in 1929. A first order formula is called logically valid if… …   Wikipedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”