Saturated model

Saturated model

In mathematical logic, and particularly in its subfield model theory, a saturated model M is one which realizes as many complete types as may be "reasonably expected" given its size. For example, an ultrapower model of the hyperreals is countably saturated, meaning that every descending nested sequence of internal sets has a nonempty intersection, see Goldblatt (1998).

Contents

Definition

Let κ be a finite or infinite cardinal number and M a model in some first-order language. Then M is called κ-saturated if for all subsets AM of cardinality less than κ, M realizes all complete types over A. The model M is called saturated if it is |M|-saturated where |M| denotes the cardinality of M. That is, it realizes all complete types over sets of parameters of size less than |M|. According to some authors, a model M is called countably saturated if it is \aleph_1-saturated; that is, it realizes all complete types over countable sets of parameters. According to others, it is countably saturated if it is \aleph_0-saturated; i.e. realizes all complete types over finite parameter sets.

Motivation

The seemingly more intuitive notion – that all complete types of the language are realized – turns out to be too weak (and is, appropriately, named weak saturation, which is the same as 1-saturation). The difference lies in the fact that many structures contain elements which are not definable (for example, any transcendental element of R is, by definition of the word, not definable in the field language). However, they still form a part of the structure, so we need types to describe relationships with them. Thus we allow sets of parameters from the structure in our definition of types. This argument allows us to discuss specific features of the model which we may otherwise miss – for example, a specific increasing sequence cn having a bound can be expressed as realizing the type {x > cn : n ∈ ω}, which uses countably many parameters. If the sequence is not definable, this fact about the structure cannot be described using the base language, so a weakly saturated structure may not bound the sequence, while an ω-saturated structure will.

The reason we only require parameter sets which are strictly smaller than the model is trivial: without this restriction, no infinite model is saturated. Consider a model M, and the type {xm : mM}. Each finite subset of this type is realized in the (infinite) model M, so by compactness it is consistent with M, but is trivially not realized. Any definition which is universally unsatisfied is useless; hence the restriction.

Examples

Saturated models exist for certain theories and cardinalities:

  • (Q, <) – the set of rational numbers with their usual ordering – is saturated. Intuitively, this is because any type consistent with the theory is implied by the order type; that is, the order the variables come in tells you everything there is to know about their role in the structure.
  • (R, <) – the set of real numbers with their usual ordering – is not saturated. For example, take the type (in one variable x) which contains the formula \textstyle{x> -\frac{1}{n}} for every natural number n, as well as the formula \textstyle{x<0}. This type uses ω different parameters from R. Every finite subset of the type is realized on R by some real x, so by compactness it is consistent with the structure, but it is not realized, as it would imply an upper bound to the sequence −1/n which is less than 0 (its least upper bound). Thus (R,<) is not ω1-saturated, and not saturated. However, it is ω-saturated, for essentially the same reason as Q – every finite type is given by the order type, which if consistent, is always realized, because of the density of the order.
  • The countable random graph, with the only non-logical symbol being the edge existence relation, is also saturated, because any complete type is implied by the finite subgraph consisting of the variables and paramaters used to define the type.

Both of these theories can be shown to be ω-categorical through the back-and-forth method. This can be generalized as follows: the unique model of cardinality κ of a countable κ-categorical theory is saturated.

However, the statement that every model has a saturated elementary extension is not provable in ZFC. In fact, this statement is equivalent to the existence of a proper class of cardinals κ such that κ = κ. The latter identity implies that either κ = λ+ = 2λ for some λ, or κ is weakly inaccessible.

Relationship to prime models

The notion of saturated model is dual to the notion of prime model in the following way: let T be a countable theory in a first-order language (that is, a set of mutually consistent sentences in that language) and let P be a prime model of T. Then P admits an elementary embedding into any other model of T. The equivalent notion for saturated models is that any "reasonably small" model of T is elementarily embedded in a saturated model, where "reasonably small" means cardinality no larger than that of the model in which it is to be embedded. Any saturated model is also homogeneous. However, while for countable theories there is a unique prime model, saturated models are necessarily specific to a particular cardinality. Given certain set-theoretic assumptions, saturated models (albeit of very large cardinality) exist for arbitrary theories. For λ-stable theories, saturated models of cardinality λ exist.

References

  • Chang, C. C.; Keisler, H. J. Model theory. Third edition. Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, 73. North-Holland Publishing Co., Amsterdam, 1990. xvi+650 pp. ISBN 0-444-88054-2
  • R. Goldblatt (1998). Lectures on the hyperreals. An introduction to nonstandard analysis. Springer.
  • Marker, David (2002). Model Theory: An Introduction. New York: Springer-Verlag. ISBN 0-387-98760-6
  • Poizat, Bruno; Trans: Klein, Moses (2000), A Course in Model Theory, New York: Springer-Verlag. ISBN 0-387-98655-3
  • Sacks, Gerald E. (1972), Saturated model theory, W. A. Benjamin, Inc., Reading, Mass., MR0398817 

Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Нужно решить контрольную?

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Model theory — This article is about the mathematical discipline. For the informal notion in other parts of mathematics and science, see Mathematical model. In mathematics, model theory is the study of (classes of) mathematical structures (e.g. groups, fields,… …   Wikipedia

  • Prime model — In mathematics, and in particular model theory, a prime model is a model which is as simple as possible. Specifically, a model P is prime if it admits an elementary embedding into any model M to which it is elementarily equivalent (that is, into… …   Wikipedia

  • Type (model theory) — In model theory and related areas of mathematics, a type is a set of first order formulas in a language L with free variables x1, x2,…, xn which are true of a sequence of elements of an L structure . Loosely speaking, types describe possible… …   Wikipedia

  • Institutional model theory — generalizes a large portion of first order model theory to an arbitrary logical system. The notion of logical system here is formalized as an institution. Institutions constitute a model oriented meta theory on logical systems similar to how the… …   Wikipedia

  • Color model — A color model is an abstract mathematical model describing the way colors can be represented as tuples of numbers, typically as three or four values or color components. When this model is associated with a precise description of how the… …   Wikipedia

  • RGB color model — RGB redirects here. For other uses, see RGB (disambiguation). A representation of additive color mixing. Projection of primary color lights on a screen shows secondary colors where two overlap; the combination of all three of red, green, and blue …   Wikipedia

  • CMYK color model — Color p …   Wikipedia

  • Non-random two-liquid model — VLE of the mixture of Chloroform and Methanol plus NRTL fit and extrapolation to different pressures The non random two liquid model[ …   Wikipedia

  • Hydrological transport model — An hydrological transport model is a mathematical model used to simulate river or stream flow and calculate water quality parameters. These models generally came into use in the 1960s and 1970s when demand for numerical forecasting of water… …   Wikipedia

  • MohidLand hydrology model — Overview= MOHID Land is a executable of the MOHID Water Modelling System. Watershed mathematical model or Hydrological transport model designed to simulate Drainage basin and aquifer. In MOHID Land, different processes occurring in a basin are… …   Wikipedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”