Pierre Louis Maupertuis

Pierre Louis Maupertuis
Pierre Louis Maupertuis

Maupertuis, wearing "lapmudes"
from his Lapland expedition.
Born 17 July 1698(1698-07-17)
Saint-Malo, France
Died 27 July 1759(1759-07-27) (aged 61)
Basel, Switzerland
Nationality French
Fields Mathematics, physics, biology, metaphysic, moral philosophy, astronomy, geography
Institutions French Academy, Berlin Academy
Known for Principle of least action, precursor of transmutation
Influences Leibniz, Newton, Descartes, Malebranche, Harvey, Berkeley, Aristoteles, Seneca
Influenced Euler, Buffon, Kant

Pierre-Louis Moreau de Maupertuis (French pronunciation: [mopɛʁtɥi]; Saint-Malo, 17 July 1698 – Basel, 27 July 1759)[1] was a French mathematician, philosopher and man of letters. He became the Director of the Académie des Sciences, and the first President of the Berlin Academy of Science, at the invitation of Frederick the Great.

Maupertuis made an expedition to Lapland to determine the shape of the earth. He is often credited with having invented the principle of least action; a version is known as Maupertuis' principle – an integral equation that determines the path followed by a physical system. His work in natural history has its interesting points, since he touched on aspects of heredity and the struggle for life.

Contents

Biography

Maupertuis was born at Saint-Malo, France, to a moderately wealthy family of merchant-corsairs[citation needed]. He was educated in mathematics by a private tutor, and upon completing his formal education his father secured him a largely honorific cavalry commission. After three years in the cavalry, during which time he became acquainted with fashionable social and mathematical circles, he moved to Paris and began building his reputation as a mathematician and literary wit. In 1723 he was admitted to the Académie des Sciences.

His early mathematical work revolved around the vis viva controversy, for which Maupertuis developed and extended the work of Isaac Newton (whose theories were not yet widely accepted outside England) and argued against the waning Cartesian mechanics. In the 1730s, the shape of the Earth became a flashpoint in the battle among rival systems of mechanics. Maupertuis, based on his exposition of Newton (with the help of his mentor Johan Bernoulli) predicted that the Earth should be oblate, while his rival Jacques Cassini measured it astronomically to be prolate. In 1736 Maupertuis acted as chief of the French Geodesic Mission sent by King Louis XV to Lapland to measure the length of a degree of arc of the meridian. His results, which he published in a book detailing his procedures, essentially settled the controversy in his favor. The book included an adventure narrative of the expedition, and an account of the Käymäjärvi Inscriptions. On his return home he became a member of almost all the scientific societies of Europe.[2]

OblateSpheroid.PNG ProlateSpheroid.png
Maupertuis'
opinion
Cassini's
opinion

After the Lapland expedition, Maupertuis set about generalizing his earlier mathematical work, proposing the principle of least action as a metaphysical principle that underlies all the laws of mechanics. He also expanded into the biological realm, anonymously publishing a book that was part popular science, part philosophy, and part erotica: Vénus physique. In that work, Maupertuis proposed a theory of generation (i.e., reproduction) in which organic matter possessed a self-organizing “intelligence” that was analogous to the contemporary chemical concept of affinities, which was widely read and commented upon favorably by Georges-Louis Leclerc, Comte de Buffon. He later developed his views on living things further in a more formal pseudonymous work that explored heredity, collecting evidence that confirmed the contributions of both sexes and treated variations as statistical phenomena.

In 1740 Maupertuis went to Berlin at the invitation of Frederick II of Prussia, and took part in the Battle of Mollwitz, where he was taken prisoner by the Austrians. On his release he returned to Berlin, and thence to Paris, where he was elected director of the Academy of Sciences in 1742, and in the following year was admitted into the Académie française. Returning to Berlin in 1744, again at the desire of Frederick II, he was chosen president of the Prussian Royal Academy of Sciences in 1746, which he controlled with the help of Leonhard Euler until his death. His position became extremely awkward with the outbreak of the Seven Years' War between his home country and his patron's, and his reputation suffered in both Paris and Berlin. Finding his health declining, he retired in 1757 to the south of France, but went in 1758 to Basel, where he died a year later. Maupertuis' difficult disposition involved him in constant quarrels, of which his controversies with Samuel König and Voltaire during the latter part of his life are examples.

"The brilliance of much of what he did was undermined by his tendency to leave work unfinished, his failure to realise his own potential. It was the insight of genius that led him to least-action principle, but a lack of intellectual energy or rigour that prevented his giving it the mathematical foundation that Lagrange would provide... He reveals remarkable powers of perception in heredity, in understanding the mechanism by which species developed, even in immunology, but no fully elaborated theory. His philosophical work is his most enthralling: bold, exciting, well argued."[3]

Evolution

Some historians of science point to his work in biology as a significant precursor to the development of evolutionary theory, specifically the theory of natural selection.[4] Other writers contend that his remarks are cursory, vague, or incidental to that particular argument. Mayr's verdict was "He was neither an evolutionist, nor one of the founders of the theory of natural selection [but] he was one of the pioneers of genetics". Maupertuis espoused a theory of pangenesis, postulating particles from both mother and father as responsible for the characters of the child.[5] Bowler credits him with studies on heredity, with the natural origin of human races, and with the idea that forms of life may have changed with time.[6]

Maupertuis was a strong critic of the natural theologians, pointing to phenomena incompatible with a concept of a good and wise Creator. He was also one of the first to consider animals in terms of variable populations, in opposition to the natural history tradition that emphasized description of individual specimens.

The difficulty of interpreting Maupertius can be gauged by reading the original works. Below is a translation from Vénus Physique, followed by the original French passage:

Could one not say that, in the fortuitous combinations of the productions of nature, as there must be some characterized by a certain relation of fitness[7] which are able to subsist, it is not to be wondered at that this fitness is present in all the species that are currently in existence? Chance, one would say, produced an innumerable multitude of individuals; a small number found themselves constructed in such a manner that the parts of the animal were able to satisfy its needs; in another infinitely greater number, there was neither fitness nor order: all of these latter have perished. Animals lacking a mouth could not live; others lacking reproductive organs could not perpetuate themselves... The species we see today are but the smallest part of what blind destiny has produced...
[8]

Ne pourrait-on pas dire que, dans la combinaison fortuite des productions de la nature, comme il n'y avait que celles où se trouvaient certain rapport de convenance qui puissent subsister, il n'est pas marveilleux que cette convenance se trouve dans toutes les espèces qui existent actuellement? Le hasard, dirait-on, avait produit une multitude innombrable d'individus; un petit nombre se trouvait construit de manière que les parties de l'animal pouvaient satisfaire à ses besoins; dans un autre infiniment plus grand, il n'y avait ni convenance, ni ordre: tous ces derniers ont péri; des animaux sans bouche ne pouvaient pas vivre, d'autres qui manquaient d'organes pour la génération ne pouvaient se perpétuer... les espèces que nous voyons aujourd'hui ne sont que la plus petite partie de ce qu'un destin aveugle avait produit...

A nearly identical argument may be found in Maupertuis' 1746 work Les loix du mouvement et du repos déduites d'un principe metaphysique (translation: s:Derivation of the laws of motion and equilibrium from a metaphysical principle). King-Hele (1963) points to similar, though not identical, ideas of thirty years later by David Hume in his Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion (1777).

The chief debate that Maupertuis was engaged in was one that treated the competing theories of generation (i.e. preformationism and epigenesis). His account of life involved spontaneous generation of new kinds of animals and plants, together with massive elimination of deficient forms. These ideas avoid the need for a Creator, but are not part of modern thinking on evolution.[9] The date of these speculations, 1745, is concurrent with Carolus Linnaeus's own work, and so predates any firm notion of species. Also, the work on genealogy, coupled with the tracing of phenotypic characters through lineages, foreshadows later work done in genetics.

Least Action Principle

The principle of least action states that in all natural phenomena a quantity called ‘action’ tends to be minimized. Maupertuis developed such a principle over two decades. For him, action could be expressed mathematically as the product of the mass of the body involved, the distance it had traveled and the velocity at which it was traveling.

In 1741, he gave a paper to the Paris Academy of Sciences, Loi du repos des corps, (Law of bodies at rest). In it he showed that a system of bodies at rest tends to reach a position in which any change would create the smallest possible change in a quantity that he argued could be assimilated to action.

In 1744, in another paper to the Paris Academy, he gave his Accord de plusieurs lois naturelles qui avaient paru jusqu’ici incompatibles (Agreement of several natural laws that had hitherto seemed to be incompatible) to show that the behaviour of light during refraction – when it bends on entering a new medium – was such that the total path it followed, from a point in the first medium to a point in the second, minimised a quantity which he again assimilated to action.

Finally, in 1746 he gave a further paper, the Loix du mouvement et du repos (Laws of movement and rest), this time to the Berlin Academy of Sciences, which showed that point masses also minimise action. Point masses are bodies that can be treated for the purposes of analysis as being a certain amount of matter (a mass) concentrated at a single point. A major debate in the early part of the eighteenth century concerned the behaviour of such bodies in collisions. Cartesian and Newtonian physicists argued that in their collisions, point masses conserved both momentum and relative velocity. Leibnizians, on the other hand, argued that they also conserved what was called live force or vis viva. This was unacceptable for their opponents for two reasons: the first that live force conservation did not apply to so-called ‘hard’ bodies, bodies that were totally incompressible, whereas the other two conservation principles did; the second was that live force was defined by the product of mass and square of velocity. Why did the velocity appear twice in this quantity, as squaring it suggests? The Leibnizians argued this was simple enough: there was a natural tendency in all matter towards motion, so even at rest, there is an inherent velocity in bodies; when they begin to move, there is a second velocity term corresponding to their actual motion.

This was anathema to Cartesians and Newtonians. An inherent tendency towards motion was an ‘occult quality’ of the kind of favoured by mediaeval scholastics and to be resisted at all costs.

Today, of course, the concept of a ‘hard’ body is rejected. And mass times the square of velocity is just twice kinetic energy so modern mechanics reserves a major role for the inheritor quantity of ‘live force’.

For Maupertuis, however, it was important to retain the concept of the hard body. And the beauty of his principle of least action was that it applied just as well to hard and elastic bodies. Since he had shown that the principle also applied to systems of bodies at rest and to light, it seemed that it was truly universal.

The final stage of his argument came when Maupertuis set out to interpret his principle in cosmological terms. ‘Least action’ sounds like an economy principle, roughly equivalent to the idea of economy of effort in daily life. A universal principle of economy of effort would seem to display the working of wisdom in the very construction of the universe. This seems, in Maupertuis’s view, a more powerful argument for the existence of an infinitely wise creator than any other that can be advanced.

He published his thinking on these matters in his Essai de cosmologie (Essay on cosmology) of 1750. He shows that the major arguments advanced to prove God, from the wonders of nature or the apparent regularity of the universe, are all open to objection (what wonder is there in the existence of certain particularly repulsive insects, what regularity is there in the observation that all the planets turn in nearly the same plane – exactly the same plane might have been striking but 'nearly the same plane' is far less convincing). But a universal principle of wisdom provides an undeniable proof of the shaping of the universe by a wise creator.

Hence the principle of least action is not just the culmination of Maupertuis’s work in several areas of physics, he sees it as his most important achievement in philosophy too, giving an incontrovertible proof of God.

The flaws in his reasoning are principally that there is no obvious reason why the product of mass, velocity and distance should be particularly viewed as corresponding to action, and even less reason why its minimisation should be an ‘economy’ principle like a minimisation of effort. Indeed, the product of mass, velocity and distance is mathematically the equivalent of the integral of live force over time. Leibniz had already shown that this quantity is likely to be either minimised or maximised in natural phenomena. Minimising this quantity could conceivably demonstrate economy, but how could maximising it? (See also the corresponding principles of stationary actions by Lagrange and Hamilton).

Relation to Kant

Arthur Schopenhauer suggested that Immanuel Kant's "most important and brilliant doctrine" - contained in the Critique of Pure Reason (1781) - was asserted by Maupertuis:

But what are we to say when we find Kant's most important and brilliant doctrine, that of the ideality of space and of the merely phenomenal existence of the corporeal world, expressed already thirty years previously by Maupertuis? ... Maupertuis expresses this paradoxical doctrine so decidedly, and yet without the addition of proof, that it must be supposed that he also obtained it from somewhere else.

The World as Will and Representation, Vol. II, Ch. IV

Main works

Honors

Notes

  1. ^ some sources give the birth date as 28 September 1698.
  2. ^ Terrall, Mary 2002. The man who flattened the Earth – Maupertuis and the sciences in the Enlightenment. Chicago. ISBN 0-226-79361-3
  3. ^ D Beeson 1992. Maupertuis: an intellectual biography. Oxford.
  4. ^ Bently Glass: Maupertius, pioneer of genetics and evolution, in Glass, B., Temkin O. & Straus W.L.Jr 1959. Forerunners of Darwin 1745–1859. p51–83
  5. ^ Mayr, Ernst. 1981. The growth of biological thought. Harvard. p328 and p646.
  6. ^ Bowler, Peter J. 2003. Evolution: the history of an idea. Berkeley, CA. p73–75
  7. ^ Fitness: not to be read as having the precision of the modern technical term fitness in population genetics.
  8. ^ http://cogweb.ucla.edu/EarlyModern/Maupertuis_1745.html
  9. ^ Roger, Jacques 1963. Les sciences de la vie dans la pensée Francaise du XVIIe et XVIIIe sicle. Armand, Paris.
  10. ^ Schmadel, Lutz D.; International Astronomical Union (2003). Dictionary of minor planet names. Berlin; New York: Springer-Verlag. p. 273. ISBN 978-3-540-00238-3. http://books.google.com/books?id=KWrB1jPCa8AC&pg=PA273. Retrieved 9 September 2011. 

References

External links

Preceded by
Charles-Irénée Castel de Saint-Pierre
Seat 8
Académie française

1743–1759
Succeeded by
Jean-Jacques Lefranc, marquis de Pompignan
Persondata
Name Maupertuis, Pierre Louis
Alternative names
Short description
Date of birth 17 July 1698
Place of birth Saint-Malo, France
Date of death 27 July 1759
Place of death Basel, Switzerland

Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Поможем написать реферат

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Pierre Louis Maupertuis — Saltar a navegación, búsqueda Pierre Louis Maupertuis …   Wikipedia Español

  • Pierre Louis Maupertuis — Pierre Louis Moreau de Maupertuis Pierre Louis de Maupertuis Pierre Louis Moreau de Maupertuis, né le 7 juillet 1698 à Saint Malo et mort à Bâle le 27 juillet 1759, est un mathématicien et astronome français …   Wikipédia en Français

  • Pierre Louis Maupertuis — Pierre Louis de Maupertuis Pierre Louis Moreau de Maupertuis (* 7. Juli 1698, Saint Malo; † 27. Juli 1759, Basel) war ein französischer Mathematiker, Astronom und Philosoph, der das Prinzip der kleinsten Wirkung …   Deutsch Wikipedia

  • Pierre de Maupertuis — Pierre Louis de Maupertuis Pierre Louis Moreau de Maupertuis (* 7. Juli 1698, Saint Malo; † 27. Juli 1759, Basel) war ein französischer Mathematiker, Astronom und Philosoph, der das Prinzip der kleinsten Wirkung …   Deutsch Wikipedia

  • Pierre-Louis Moreau de Maupertuis — Pierre Louis de Maupertuis Pierre Louis Moreau de Maupertuis (* 28. September 1698 in Saint Malo; † 27. Juli 1759 in Basel) war ein französischer Mathematiker, Astronom und Philosoph, der das Prinzip der kleinsten …   Deutsch Wikipedia

  • Pierre Louis de Maupertuis — Pierre Louis Moreau de Maupertuis Pierre Louis de Maupertuis Pierre Louis Moreau de Maupertuis, né le 7 juillet 1698 à Saint Malo et mort à Bâle le 27 juillet 1759, est un mathématicien et astronome français …   Wikipédia en Français

  • Pierre louis moreau de maupertuis — Pierre Louis de Maupertuis Pierre Louis Moreau de Maupertuis, né le 7 juillet 1698 à Saint Malo et mort à Bâle le 27 juillet 1759, est un mathématicien et astronome français …   Wikipédia en Français

  • Pierre-Louis de Maupertuis — Pierre Louis Moreau de Maupertuis (* 7. Juli 1698, Saint Malo; † 27. Juli 1759, Basel) war ein französischer Mathematiker, Astronom und Philosoph, der das Prinzip der kleinsten Wirkung …   Deutsch Wikipedia

  • Pierre Louis Moreau de Maupertuis — Pierre Louis de Maupertuis Pierre Louis Moreau de Maupertuis (* 7. Juli 1698, Saint Malo; † 27. Juli 1759, Basel) war ein französischer Mathematiker, Astronom und Philosoph, der das Prinzip der kleinsten Wirkung …   Deutsch Wikipedia

  • Pierre-Louis — bzw. Pierre Louis ist der Familienname folgender Personen: Joseph Nemours Pierre Louis (1900–1966), haitianische Politiker, Präsident von Haiti Michèle Pierre Louis (* 1947), haitianische Politikerin Pierre Louis bzw. Pierre Louis ist der Vorname …   Deutsch Wikipedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”