Drinker paradox

Drinker paradox

The drinker paradox is a theorem of classical predicate logic that states: There is someone in the pub such that, if he is drinking, everyone in the pub is drinking. The actual theorem is

\exists x.\ [D(x) \rightarrow \forall y.\ D(y)]. \,

The paradox was popularised by the mathematical logician Raymond Smullyan, who called it the "drinking principle" in his book What Is the Name of this Book?[1]

Contents

Proof of the paradox

The paradox is valid due to the nature of material implication in formal logic, which states that "If P, then Q" is always true if P (the condition or antecedent) is false.

The proof begins by recognizing it is true that either everyone in the pub is drinking (in this particular round of drinks), or at least one person in the pub isn't drinking.

On the one hand, suppose everyone is drinking. For any particular person, it can't be wrong to say that if that particular person is drinking, then everyone in the pub is drinking — because everyone is drinking.

Because everyone is drinking, then that one person must drink because when ' that person ' drinks ' everybody ' drinks, everybody includes that person.

Suppose, on the other hand, that at least one person isn't drinking. For any particular nondrinking person, it still can't be wrong to say that if that particular person is drinking, then everyone in the pub is drinking — because that person is, in fact, not drinking. In this case the condition is false, so the statement is true.

Either way, there is someone in the pub such that, if he is drinking, everyone in the pub is drinking. Hence the paradox.

Discussion

This proof illustrates several properties of classical predicate logic that do not always agree with ordinary language.

Non-empty domain

First, we didn't need to assume there was anyone in the pub. The assumption that the domain is non-empty is built into the inference rules of classical predicate logic. We can deduce D(x) from \forall x D(x), but of course if the domain were empty (in this case, if there were nobody in the pub), the proposition D(x) is not well-formed for any closed expression x.

Nevertheless, free logic, which allows for empty domains, still has something like the drinker paradox in the form of the theorem:

\exists x.\ [x=x] \rightarrow \exists x.\ [D(x) \rightarrow \forall y.\ D(y)]

Or in words:

If there is anyone in the pub at all, then there is someone such that, if they are drinking, then everyone in the pub is drinking.

Excluded middle

The above proof begins by saying that either everyone is drinking, or someone is not drinking. This uses the validity of excluded middle for the statement S = "everyone is drinking", which is always available in classical logic. If the logic does not admit arbitrary excluded middle—for example if the logic is intuitionistic—then the truth of S \or \neg S must first be established, i.e., S must be shown to be decidable.

As a simple example of one such decision procedure, if there are finitely many customers in the pub, one can find one person who doesn't drink. But if S is given no semantics, then there is no proof of the drinker paradox in intuitionistic logic. Indeed, assuming the drinkinginfinite domains leads to various classically valid but intuitionistically unacceptable conclusions.

For instance, it would allow for a simple solution of Goldbach's conjecture, which is one of the oldest unsolved problems in mathematics. It asks whether all even numbers greater than two can be expressed as the sum of two prime numbers. Applying the drinking principle, it would follow that there exists an even number greater than two, such that, if it is the sum of two primes suffice to check whether that particular number is the sum of two primes, which has a finite decision process. If it were not, then obviously it would be a refutation of the conjecture. But if it were, then all of them would be, and the conjecture would be proven.

Nevertheless, intuitionistic (free) logic still has something like the drinker paradox in the form of the theorem:

\neg \exist x.\ (\exist y.\ [N(y)] \rightarrow N(x)) \rightarrow \neg \exist x . (x=x)

If we take N(x) to be \neg D(x), that is, x is not drinking, then in words this reads:

If there isn't someone in the pub such that, if anyone in the pub isn't drinking, then they aren't drinking either, then nobody is in the pub.

In classical logic this would be equivalent to the previous statement, from which it can be derived by two transpositions.

Material versus indicative conditional

Most important to the paradox is that the conditional in classical (and intuitionistic) logic is the material conditional. It has the property that A \rightarrow B is true if B is true or if A is false (in classical logic, but not intuitionistic logic, this is also a necessary condition).

So as it was applied here, the statement "if he is drinking, everyone is drinking" was taken to be correct in one case, if everyone was drinking, and in the other case, if he was not drinking — even though his drinking may not have had anything to do with anyone else's drinking.

In natural language, on the other hand, typically "if...then..." is used as an indicative conditional.

Notes

  1. ^ Raymond Smullyan (1990). What is the Name of this Book. Penguin Books Ltd. chapter 14. ISBN 0-14-013511-1. 

References

See also


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Нужна курсовая?

Look at other dictionaries:

  • List of paradoxes — This is a list of paradoxes, grouped thematically. Note that many of the listed paradoxes have a clear resolution see Quine s Classification of Paradoxes.Logical, non mathematical* Paradox of entailment: Inconsistent premises always make an… …   Wikipedia

  • Health effects of wine — Wine has a long history of use in the world of medicine and health. The issue of wine and health is a topic of considerable discussion and research. Wine has a long history of use as an early form of medication, being recommended variously as a… …   Wikipedia

  • Wine — This article is about the beverage. For other uses, see Wine (disambiguation) …   Wikipedia

  • Life Sciences — ▪ 2009 Introduction Zoology       In 2008 several zoological studies provided new insights into how species life history traits (such as the timing of reproduction or the length of life of adult individuals) are derived in part as responses to… …   Universalium

  • Alcoholism — Classification and external resources …   Wikipedia

  • Anton Rubinstein — This article is about the 19th century Russian pianist and composer. For Anton s brother, also a composer and pianist, see Nikolai Rubinstein. For the unrelated 20th century Polish pianist, see Arthur Rubinstein .Anton Grigorevich Rubinstein ( ru …   Wikipedia

  • alcohol consumption — Introduction  the drinking of beverages containing ethyl alcohol. alcoholic beverages are consumed largely for their physiological and psychological effects, but they are often consumed within specific social contexts and may even be a part of… …   Universalium

  • List of Saturday Night Live commercials — The following is a partial list of Saturday Night Live commercial parodies. On Saturday Night Live ( SNL ), a parody advertisement is commonly shown after the host s opening monologue. Fast food, beer, feminine hygiene products, toys, and… …   Wikipedia

  • Banksy — Infobox Artist bgcolour = #6495ED name = Banksy imagesize = caption = birthname = Unknown birthdate = 1974 location = deathdate = deathplace = nationality = British field = Graffiti Art training = movement = works = patrons = influenced by =… …   Wikipedia

  • List of Saturday Night Live commercial parodies — This television related list is incomplete; you can help by expanding it. The following is a partial list of Saturday Night Live commercial parodies. On Saturday Night Live (SNL), a parody advertisement is commonly shown after the host s opening… …   Wikipedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”