Collatz conjecture

Collatz conjecture
Directed graph showing the orbits of small numbers under the Collatz map. The Collatz conjecture is equivalent to the statement that all paths eventually lead to 1.
Directed graph showing the orbits of the first 1000 numbers.
x axis represents starting number, y axis represents the highest number reached during the chain to 1

The Collatz conjecture is a conjecture in mathematics named after Lothar Collatz, who first proposed it in 1937. The conjecture is also known as the 3n + 1 conjecture, the Ulam conjecture (after Stanisław Ulam), Kakutani's problem (after Shizuo Kakutani), the Thwaites conjecture (after Sir Bryan Thwaites), Hasse's algorithm (after Helmut Hasse), or the Syracuse problem;[1] the sequence of numbers involved is referred to as the hailstone sequence or hailstone numbers,[2] or as wondrous numbers.[3]

Take any natural number n. If n is even, divide it by 2 to get n / 2, if n is odd multiply it by 3 and add 1 to obtain 3n + 1. Repeat the process (which has been called "Half Or Triple Plus One", or HOTPO[4]) indefinitely. The conjecture is that no matter what number you start with, you will always eventually reach 1. The property has also been called oneness.[5]

Paul Erdős said, allegedly, about the Collatz conjecture: "Mathematics is not yet ripe for such problems"[6] and also offered $500 for its solution.

In 2006, researchers Kurtz and Simon, building on earlier work by J.H. Conway in the 1970s, proved that a natural generalization of the Collatz problem is algorithmically undecidable.[7] However, as this proof depends upon the generalization, it cannot be applied to the original Collatz problem.

Contents

Statement of the problem

Consider the following operation on an arbitrary positive integer:

  • If the number is even, divide it by two.
  • If the number is odd, triple it and add one.

In modular arithmetic notation, define the function f as follows:

 f(n) = \begin{cases} n/2 &\mbox{if } n \equiv 0 \pmod{2}\\ 3n+1 & \mbox{if } n\equiv 1 \pmod{2} \end{cases}
Numbers from 1 to 9999 and their corresponding total stopping time.

Now, form a sequence by performing this operation repeatedly, beginning with any positive integer, and taking the result at each step as the input at the next.

In notation:[citation needed]

 a_i = \begin{cases}n & \mbox{for } i = 0 \\ f(a_{i-1}) & \mbox{for } i > 0. \end{cases}

(that is: ai is the value of f applied to n recursively i times; ai = fi(n))

or


{a_{i}} = \frac{1}{2}{a_{i-1}} - \frac{1}{4}(5a_{i-1}+2)((-1)^{a_{i-1}}-1)

(which yields \frac{a_{i-1}}{2} for even ai and 3 * ai − 1 + 1 for odd ai).

The Collatz conjecture is: This process will eventually reach the number 1, regardless of which positive integer is chosen initially.

That smallest i such that ai=1 is called the total stopping time of n. The conjecture asserts that every n has a well-defined stopping time. If, for some n, such an i doesn't exist, we say that n has infinite total stopping time and the conjecture is false.

If the conjecture is false, it can only be because there is some starting number which gives rise to a sequence which does not contain 1. Such a sequence might enter a repeating cycle that excludes 1, or increase without bound. No such sequence has been found.

Examples

For instance, starting with n = 6, one gets the sequence 6, 3, 10, 5, 16, 8, 4, 2, 1.

n = 11, for example, takes longer to reach 1: 11, 34, 17, 52, 26, 13, 40, 20, 10, 5, 16, 8, 4, 2, 1.

The sequence for n = 27, listed and graphed below, takes 111 steps, climbing over 9000 before descending to 1.

{ 27, 82, 41, 124, 62, 31, 94, 47, 142, 71, 214, 107, 322, 161, 484, 242, 121, 364, 182, 91, 274, 137, 412, 206, 103, 310, 155, 466, 233, 700, 350, 175, 526, 263, 790, 395, 1186, 593, 1780, 890, 445, 1336, 668, 334, 167, 502, 251, 754, 377, 1132, 566, 283, 850, 425, 1276, 638, 319, 958, 479, 1438, 719, 2158, 1079, 3238, 1619, 4858, 2429, 7288, 3644, 1822, 911, 2734, 1367, 4102, 2051, 6154, 3077, 9232, 4616, 2308, 1154, 577, 1732, 866, 433, 1300, 650, 325, 976, 488, 244, 122, 61, 184, 92, 46, 23, 70, 35, 106, 53, 160, 80, 40, 20, 10, 5, 16, 8, 4, 2, 1 }
Collatz5.svg

Starting values with longer stopping time than any smaller starting value are known as "high water marks". The high water mark for numbers less than 100 million is 63,728,127, with 949 steps. The high water mark for numbers less than 1 billion is 670,617,279, with 986 steps. The high water mark for numbers less than 10 billion is 9,780,657,630, with 1132 steps. High water marks are given by sequence OEISA006877 in On-Line Encyclopedia of Integer Sequences, and the number of steps for each starting value are given by OEISA006878. An example for a number above 100 billion that has over 45,000 digits terminates in 1,093,105 iterations.

The powers of two converge to one quickly because 2n is halved n times to reach one, and is never increased.

Program to calculate Hailstone sequences

A specific Hailstone sequence can be easily computed, as is shown by this pseudocode example:

function hailstone(n)
while n > 1
show n
if n is odd then
set n = 3n + 1
else
set n = n / 2
endif
endwhile
show n

This program halts when the sequence reaches 1, in order to avoid printing an endless cycle of 4, 2, 1. If the Collatz conjecture is true, the program will always halt (stop) no matter what positive starting integer is given to it. (See Halting Problem for a discussion of the relationship between open-ended computer programs and unsolved mathematics problems. Another variation of this is the Millhollen obstacle.)

m-cycles cannot occur

The proof of the conjecture can indirectly be done by proving the following:

  • no infinite divergent trajectory occurs
  • no cycle occurs

thus all numbers have a trajectory down to 1.

In 1977, R. Steiner, and in 2000 and 2002, J. Simons and B. de Weger (based on Steiner's work), proved the nonexistence of certain types of cycles.

Notation

To explain this we refer to the definition as given in the section Syracuse function below:

Define the transformation for odd positive integer numbers a and b, positive integer numbers A:

b = T(a;A) meaning b = (3a + 1)/2A

where A has the maximum value which leaves b an integer.

Example:
a = 7. Then b = T(7, A) and 3a + 1 = 22,
so A = 1
b = (3×7 + 1)/21 = 11
11 = T(7;1)

Define the concatenation (extensible up to arbitrary length):

b = T(T(a;A);B) = T(a;A,B)
Example:

b = T(7; A, B) = T(7;1,1) = ((3×7 + 1)/21×3 + 1)/2B = (3×11 + 1)/2B = 34/21 = 17

17 = T(7;1,1)

Define a "one-peak-transformation" of L ascending and 1 descending exponents/steps:

b = T(a;1,1,1,1,1,....,1,A) = T(a;(1)L,A)

with L (arbitrary) many exponents 1 and exactly one exponent A > 1

Example:
b = T(7;1,1,A) = T(7;(1)2, A) = (17×3 + 1)/2A = 52/22 = 13
13 = T(7;(1)2,2)

then call the construction

a = T(a; (1)L,A) // arbitrary positive value for number of increasing steps L

a "1-cycle" of length N = L + 1 (steps).

Theorems

  • Steiner proved in 1977 there is no 1-cycle. However many L steps may be chosen, a number x satisfying the loop-condition is never an integer.
  • Simons proved in 2000 (based on Steiner's method) there is no 2-cycle a = T(a;(1)L,A,(1)M,B) however many L and M steps may be chosen.
  • Simons/deWeger in 2003 extended their own proof up to "68-cycles": there is no m-cycle up to m=68 a=T(a;(1)L1,A1,(1)L2,A2,...,(1)L68,A68). Whatever number of steps in L1 to L68 and whatever exponents A1 to A68 one may choose, there is no positive odd integer number a satisfying the cycle condition. Steiner claimed in a usenet discussion he could extend this up to m=71.[8]
Comment: These theorems were derived by results of the theory of rational approximation of transcendental numbers. Simons/deWeger concluded their article with the comment, that this method of approximation is exhausted with that results, and a completely different approach is needed to be able to proceed qualitatively.

Supporting arguments

Although the conjecture has not been proven, most mathematicians who have looked into the problem think the conjecture is true because experimental evidence and heuristic arguments support it.

Experimental evidence

The conjecture has been checked by computer for all starting values up to 20 × 258 ≈ 5.764×1018.[9] All initial values tested so far eventually end in the repeating cycle {4,2,1}, which has only three terms. It is also known that {4,2,1} is the only repeating cycle possible with fewer than 35400 terms.[10]

Such computer evidence is not a proof that the conjecture is true. As shown in the cases of the Pólya conjecture, the Mertens conjecture and the Skewes' number, sometimes a conjecture's only counterexamples are found when using very large numbers. Since sequentially examining all natural numbers is a process which can never be completed, such an approach can never demonstrate that the conjecture is true, merely that no counterexamples have yet been discovered.

A probabilistic heuristic

If one considers only the odd numbers in the sequence generated by the Collatz process, then each odd number is on average 3/4 of the previous one.[11] (More precisely, the geometric mean of the ratios of outcomes is 3/4.) This yields a heuristic argument that every Hailstone sequence should decrease in the long run, although this is not evidence against other cycles, only against divergence. The argument is not a proof because it assumes that Hailstone sequences are assembled from uncorrelated probabilistic events. (It does rigorously establish that the 2-adic extension of the Collatz process has 2 division steps for every multiplication step for almost all 2-adic starting values.)

Rigorous bounds

Although it is not known rigorously whether all positive numbers eventually reach one according to the Collatz iteration, it is known that many numbers do so. In particular, Krasikov and Lagarias showed that the number of integers in the interval [1,x] that eventually reach one is at least proportional to x0.84.[12]

Other formulations of the conjecture

In reverse

The first 20 levels of the Collatz graph generated in bottom-up fashion. The graph includes all numbers with an orbit length of 20 or less.

There is another approach to prove the conjecture, which considers the bottom-up method of growing the so called Collatz graph. The Collatz graph is a graph defined by the inverse relation

 R(n) = \begin{cases} \{2n\} & \mbox{if } n\equiv 0,1,2,3,5 \\ \{2n,(n-1)/3\} & \mbox{if } n\equiv 4 \end{cases} \pmod{6}.

So, instead of proving that all natural numbers eventually lead to 1, we can prove that 1 leads to all natural numbers. For any integer n, n ≡ 1 (mod 2) iff 3n + 1 ≡ 4 (mod 6). Equivalently, (n − 1)/3 ≡ 1 (mod 2) iff n ≡ 4 (mod 6). Conjecturally, this inverse relation forms a tree except for the 1-2-4 loop (the inverse of the 1-4-2 loop of the unaltered function f defined in the statement of the problem above). When the relation 3n + 1 of the function f is replaced by the common substitute "shortcut" relation (3n + 1)/2, the Collatz graph is defined by the inverse relation,

 R(n) = \begin{cases} \{2n\} & \text{if } n\equiv 0,1 \\ \{2n,(2n-1)/3\} & \text{if } n\equiv 2 \end{cases} \pmod{3}.

Conjecturally, this inverse relation forms a tree except for a 1-2 loop (the inverse of the 1-2 loop of the function f(n) revised as indicated above).

As an abstract machine that computes in base two

Repeated applications of the Collatz function can be represented as an abstract machine that handles strings of bits. The machine will perform the following three steps on any odd number until only one "1" remains:

  1. Append 1 to the (right) end of the number in binary (giving 2n + 1);
  2. Add this to the original number by binary addition (giving 2n + 1 + n = 3n + 1);
  3. Remove all trailing "0"s (i.e. repeatedly divide by two until the result is odd).

This prescription is plainly equivalent to computing a Hailstone sequence in base two.

Example

The starting number 7 is written in base two as 111. The resulting Hailstone sequence is:

         111
        1111
       10110
      10111
     100010
    100011
    110100
   11011
  101000
 1011
10000

As a parity sequence

For this section, consider the Collatz function in the slightly modified form

 f(n) = \begin{cases} n/2 &\mbox{if } n \equiv 0 \\ (3n +1)/2 & \mbox{if } n \equiv 1. \end{cases} \pmod{2}

This can be done because when n is odd, 3n + 1 is always even.

If P(…) is the parity of a number, that is P(2n) = 0 and P(2n + 1) = 1, then we can define the Hailstone parity sequence for a number n as pi = P(ai), where a0 = n, and ai+1 = f(ai).

Using this form for f(n), it can be shown that the parity sequences for two numbers m and n will agree in the first k terms if and only if m and n are equivalent modulo 2k. This implies that every number is uniquely identified by its parity sequence, and moreover that if there are multiple Hailstone cycles, then their corresponding parity cycles must be different.

The proof is simple: it is easy to verify by hand that applying the f function k times to the number a·2k + b will give the result a·3c + d, where d is the result of applying the f function k times to b, and c is how many odd numbers were encountered during that sequence. So the parity of the first k numbers is determined purely by b, and the parity of the (k+1)th number will change if the least significant bit of a is changed.

The Collatz Conjecture can be rephrased as stating that the Hailstone parity sequence for every number eventually enters the cycle 0 → 1 → 0.

As a tag system

For the Collatz function in the form

 f(n) = \begin{cases} n/2 &\text{if } n \equiv 0 \\ (3n +1)/2 & \text{if } n \equiv 1. \end{cases} \pmod{2}

Hailstone sequences can be computed by the extremely simple 2-tag system with production rules abc, ba, caaa. In this system, the positive integer n is represented by a string of n a's, and iteration of the tag operation halts on any word of length less than 2. (Adapted from De Mol.)

The Collatz conjecture equivalently states that this tag system, with an arbitrary finite string of a's as the initial word, eventually halts (see Example: Computation of Collatz sequences for a worked example).

Extensions to larger domains

Iterating on all integers

An obvious extension is to include all integers, not just positive integers. In this case there are a total of 5 known cycles, which all integers seem to eventually fall into under iteration of f. These cycles are listed here, starting with the well-known cycle for positive n.

Odd values are listed in bold. Each cycle is listed with its member of least absolute value (which is always odd or zero) first.

Cycle Odd-value cycle length Full cycle length
1 → 4 → 2 → 1 1 3
0 → 0 0 1
−1 → −2 → −1 1 2
−5 → −14 → −7 → −20 → −10 → −5 2 5
−17 → −50 → −25 → −74 → −37 → −110 → −55 → −164 → −82 → −41 → −122 → −61 → −182 → −91 → −272 → −136 → −68 → −34 → −17 7 18

The Generalized Collatz Conjecture is the assertion that every integer, under iteration by f, eventually falls into one of these five cycles.

Iterating with odd denominators or 2-adic integers

The standard Collatz map can be extended to (positive or negative) rational numbers which have odd denominators when written in lowest terms. The number is taken to be odd or even according to whether its numerator is odd or even. A closely related fact is that the Collatz map extends to the ring of 2-adic integers, which contains the ring of rationals with odd denominators as a subring.

The parity sequences as defined above are no longer unique for fractions. However, it can be shown that any possible parity cycle is the parity sequence for exactly one fraction: if a cycle has length n and includes odd numbers exactly m times at indices k0, …, km−1, then the unique fraction which generates that parity cycle is

\frac{3^{m-1} 2^{k_0} + ... + 3^0 2^{k_{m-1}}}{2^n - 3^m}.

For example, the parity cycle (1 0 1 1 0 0 1) has length 7 and has 4 odd numbers at indices 0, 2, 3, and 6. The unique fraction which generates that parity cycle is

\frac{3^3 2^0 + 3^2 2^2 + 3^1 2^3 + 3^0 2^6}{2^7 - 3^4} = \frac{151}{47},

the complete cycle being: 151/47 → 250/47 → 125/47 → 211/47 → 340/47 → 170/47 → 85/47 → 151/47

Although the cyclic permutations of the original parity sequence are unique fractions, the cycle is not unique, each permutation's fraction being the next number in the loop cycle:

(0 1 1 0 0 1 1) → \frac{3^3 2^1 + 3^2 2^2 + 3^1 2^5 + 3^0 2^6}{2^7 - 3^4} = \frac{250}{47}


(1 1 0 0 1 1 0) → \frac{3^3 2^0 + 3^2 2^1 + 3^1 2^4 + 3^0 2^5}{2^7 - 3^4} = \frac{{125}}{47}


(1 0 0 1 1 0 1) → \frac{3^3 2^0 + 3^2 2^3 + 3^1 2^4 + 3^0 2^6}{2^7 - 3^4} = \frac{211}{47}


(0 0 1 1 0 1 1) → \frac{3^3 2^2 + 3^2 2^3 + 3^1 2^5 + 3^0 2^6}{2^7 - 3^4} = \frac{340}{47}


(0 1 1 0 1 1 0) → \frac{3^3 2^1 + 3^2 2^2 + 3^1 2^4 + 3^0 2^5}{2^7 - 3^4} = \frac{170}{47}


(1 1 0 1 1 0 0) → \frac{3^3 2^0 + 3^2 2^1 + 3^1 2^3 + 3^0 2^4}{2^7 - 3^4} = \frac{85}{47}

Also, for uniqueness, the parity sequence should be "prime", i.e., not partitionable into identical sub-sequences. For example, parity sequence (1 1 0 0 1 1 0 0) can be partitioned into two identical sub-sequences (1 1 0 0)(1 1 0 0). Calculating the 8-element sequence fraction gives

(1 1 0 0 1 1 0 0) → \frac{3^3 2^0 + 3^2 2^1 + 3^1 2^4 + 3^0 2^5}{2^8 - 3^4} = \frac{125}{175}

But when reduced to lowest terms {5/7}, it is the same as that of the 4-element sub-sequence

(1 1 0 0) → \frac{3^1 2^0 + 3^0 2^1}{2^4 - 3^2} = \frac{5}{7}.

And this is because the 8-element parity sequence actually represents two circuits of the loop cycle defined by the 4-element parity sequence.

In this context, the Collatz conjecture is equivalent to saying that (0 1) is the only cycle which is generated by positive whole numbers (i.e. 1 and 2).

Iterating on real or complex numbers

Cobweb plot of the orbit 10-5-8-4-2-1-2-1-2-1-etc. in the real extension of the Collatz map (optimized by replacing "3n + 1" with "(3n + 1)/2" )

The Collatz map can be viewed as the restriction to the integers of the smooth real and complex map

f(z)=\frac 1 2 z \cos^2\left(\frac \pi 2 z\right)+(3z+1)\sin^2\left(\frac \pi 2 z\right),

which simplifies to \frac{1}{4}(2 + 7z - (2 + 5z)\cos(\pi z)).

If the standard Collatz map defined above is optimized by replacing the relation 3n + 1 with the common substitute "shortcut" relation (3n + 1)/2, it can be viewed as the restriction to the integers of the smooth real and complex map

f(z)=\frac 1 2 z \cos^2\left(\frac \pi 2 z\right)+\frac 1 2 (3z+1)\sin^2\left(\frac \pi 2 z\right),

which simplifies to \frac{1}{4}(1 + 4z - (1 + 2z)\cos(\pi z)).

Collatz fractal

Iterating the above optimized map in the complex plane produces the Collatz fractal.

The point of view of iteration on the real line was investigated by Chamberland (1996), and on the complex plane by Letherman, Schleicher, and Wood (1999).

Collatz map fractal in a neighbourhood of the real line

Optimizations

The As a parity sequence section above gives a way to speed up simulation of the sequence. To jump ahead k steps on each iteration (using the f function from that section), break up the current number into two parts, b (the k least significant bits, interpreted as an integer), and a (the rest of the bits as an integer). The result of jumping ahead k steps can be found as:

f k(a 2k + b) = a 3c(b) + d(b).

The c and d arrays are precalculated for all possible k-bit numbers b, where d(b) is the result of applying the f function k times to b, and c(b) is the number of odd numbers encountered on the way. For example, if k=5, you can jump ahead 5 steps on each iteration by separating out the 5 least significant bits of a number and using:

c(0..31) = {0,3,2,2,2,2,2,4,1,4,1,3,2,2,3,4,1,2,3,3,1,1,3,3,2,3,2,4,3,3,4,5}
d(0..31) = {0,2,1,1,2,2,2,20,1,26,1,10,4,4,13,40,2,5,17,17,2,2,20,20,8,22,8,71,26,26,80,242}.

This requires 2k precomputation and storage to speed up the resulting calculation by a factor of k, a space-time tradeoff.

For the special purpose of searching for a counterexample to the Collatz conjecture, this precomputation leads to an even more important acceleration due to Tomás Oliveira e Silva and is used in the record confirmation of the Collatz conjecture. If, for some given b and k, the inequality

f k(a 2k + b) = a 3c(b) + d(b) < a 2k+b

holds for all a, then the first counterexample, if it exists, cannot be b modulo 2k. For instance, the first counterexample must be odd because f(2n) = n; and it must be 3 mod 4 because f3(4n + 1) = 3n + 1. For each starting value a which is not a counterexample to the Collatz conjecture, there is a k for which such an inequality holds, so checking the Collatz conjecture for one starting value is as good as checking an entire congruence class. As k increases, the search only needs to check those residues b that are not eliminated by lower values of k. On the order of 3k/2 residues survive.[citation needed] For example, the only surviving residues mod 32 are 7, 15, 27, and 31; only 573,162 residues survive mod 225 = 33,554,432.

Syracuse function

If k is an odd integer, then 3k + 1 is even, so we can write 3k + 1 = 2ak′, with k' odd and a ≥ 1. We define a function f from the set I of odd integers into itself, called the Syracuse function, by taking f (k) = k′ (sequence A075677 in OEIS).

Some properties of the Syracuse function are:

  • f (4k + 1) = f (k) for all k in I.
  • For all p ≥ 2 and h odd, fp−1(2p h − 1) = 2·3p − 1h − 1 (here, f p−1 is function iteration notation).
  • For all odd h, f(2h − 1) ≤ (3h − 1)/2

The Syracuse conjecture is that for all k in I, there exists an integer n ≥ 1 such that fn(k) = 1. Equivalently, let E be the set of odd integers k for which there exists an integer n ≥ 1 such that fn(k) = 1. The problem is to show that E = I. The following is the beginning of an attempt at a proof by induction:

1, 3, 5, 7, and 9 are known to be elements of E. Let k be an odd integer greater than 9. Suppose that the odd numbers up to and including k − 2 are in E and let us try to prove that k is in E. As k is odd, k + 1 is even, so we can write k + 1 = 2ph for p ≥ 1, h odd, and k = 2ph − 1. Now we have:

  • If p = 1, then k = 2h − 1. It is easy to check that f (k) < k , so f (k) ∈ E; hence kE.
  • If p ≥ 2 and h is a multiple of 3, we can write h = 3h′. Let k′ = 2p + 1h′ − 1; then f (k′) = k , and as k′ < k , k′ is in E; therefore k = f (k′) ∈ E.
  • If p ≥ 2 and h is not a multiple of 3 but h ≡ (−1)p mod 4, we can still show that kE.

The problematic case is that where p ≥ 2 , h not multiple of 3 and h ≡ (−1)p+1 mod 4. Here, if we manage to show that for every odd integer k′, 1 ≤ k′ ≤ k − 2 ; 3k′ ∈ E we are done.

See also

Notes

  1. ^ Maddux, Cleborne D.; Johnson, D. Lamont (1997). Logo: A Retrospective. New York: Haworth Press. p. 160. ISBN 0789003740. "The problem is also known by several other names, including: Ulam's conjecture, the Hailstone problem, the Syracuse problem, Kakutani's problem, Hasse's algorithm, and the Collatz problem." 
  2. ^ Pickover, Clifford A. (2001). Wonders of Numbers. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 116–118. ISBN 0195133420. 
  3. ^ Hofstadter, Douglas R. (1979). Gödel, Escher, Bach. New York: Basic Books. pp. 400–402. ISBN 0465026850. 
  4. ^ Friendly, Michael (1988). Advanced Logo: A Language for Learning. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. ISBN 0898599334. 
  5. ^ Paul Bourke (December 1992). "Decision Procedure for "Oneness"". University of West Alabama. http://local.wasp.uwa.edu.au/~pbourke/fractals/oneness/. 
  6. ^ R. K. Guy: Don't try to solve these problems, Amer. Math. Monthly, 90(1983), 35–41.
  7. ^ Kurtz, Stuart A.; Simon, Janos (2007). "The Undecidability of the. Generalized Collatz Problem". In Cai, J.-Y.; Cooper, S.B.; Zhu, H.. Proceedings of the 4th International Conference on Theory and Applications of Models of Computation, TAMC 2007, held in Shanghai, China in May 2007. pp. 542–553. doi:10.1007/978-3-540-72504-6_49. ISBN 3540725032. http://books.google.com/books?id=mhrOkx-xyJIC&pg=PA542.  Also available here: http://www.cs.uchicago.edu/~simon/RES/collatz.pdf
  8. ^ http://groups.google.com/group/sci.math/msg/1ed7cd277079efdd
  9. ^ http://www.ieeta.pt/~tos/3x+1.html
  10. ^ Garner, Lynn E. (1981). "On the Collatz 3n + 1 Algorithm". Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society 82 (1): 19–22. doi:10.2307/2044308. JSTOR 2044308. 
  11. ^ http://www.cecm.sfu.ca/organics/papers/lagarias/paper/html/node3.html
  12. ^ Krasikov, Ilia; Lagarias, Jeffrey C. (2003). "Bounds for the 3x + 1 problem using difference inequalities". Acta Arithmetica 109 (3): 237–258. doi:10.4064/aa109-3-4. MR1980260 .

References and external links

Papers

Books

General


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Поможем написать курсовую

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Conjecture de Collatz — Conjecture de Syracuse En mathématiques, on appelle suite de Syracuse une suite d entiers naturels définie de la manière suivante : On part d un nombre entier plus grand que zéro ; s’il est pair, on le divise par 2 ; s’il est… …   Wikipédia en Français

  • Conjecture De Syracuse — En mathématiques, on appelle suite de Syracuse une suite d entiers naturels définie de la manière suivante : On part d un nombre entier plus grand que zéro ; s’il est pair, on le divise par 2 ; s’il est impair, on le multiplie par… …   Wikipédia en Français

  • Conjecture de syracuse — En mathématiques, on appelle suite de Syracuse une suite d entiers naturels définie de la manière suivante : On part d un nombre entier plus grand que zéro ; s’il est pair, on le divise par 2 ; s’il est impair, on le multiplie par… …   Wikipédia en Français

  • Collatz — can refer to: Lothar Collatz, German mathematician, who proposed several ideas: Collatz conjecture, number theory conjecture on Collatz sequences This disambiguation page lists articles associated with the same title. If an …   Wikipedia

  • Conjecture de Syracuse — En mathématiques, on appelle suite de Syracuse une suite d entiers naturels définie de la manière suivante : On part d un nombre entier plus grand que zéro ; s’il est pair, on le divise par 2 ; s’il est impair, on le multiplie par… …   Wikipédia en Français

  • Collatz-Problem — Das Collatz Problem, auch als (3n + 1) Vermutung bezeichnet, ist ein ungelöstes mathematisches Problem, das 1937 von Lothar Collatz gestellt wurde. Inhaltsverzeichnis 1 Problemstellung 2 Ursprung und Geschichte 2.1 Publizierte Quellen …   Deutsch Wikipedia

  • Conjecture — For text reconstruction, see Conjecture (textual criticism). A conjecture is a proposition that is unproven but is thought to be true and has not been disproven. Karl Popper pioneered the use of the term conjecture in scientific philosophy.… …   Wikipedia

  • Problème de Collatz — Conjecture de Syracuse En mathématiques, on appelle suite de Syracuse une suite d entiers naturels définie de la manière suivante : On part d un nombre entier plus grand que zéro ; s’il est pair, on le divise par 2 ; s’il est… …   Wikipédia en Français

  • Collatz — Lothar Collatz Lothar Collatz (6 juillet 1910, Arnsberg, Westphalie 26 septembre 1990, Varna, Bulgarie) était un mathématicien allemand. En 1937, il énonça la fameuse conjecture de Collatz connue également sous le nom de conjecture de Syracuse.… …   Wikipédia en Français

  • Collatz-Algorithmus — Das Collatz Problem, auch als (3n + 1) Vermutung bezeichnet, ist ein ungelöstes mathematisches Problem, das 1937 von Lothar Collatz entdeckt wurde. Inhaltsverzeichnis 1 Problemstellung 2 Ursprung und Geschichte 2.1 Publizierte Quellen 2.2 …   Deutsch Wikipedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”