Large countable ordinal

Large countable ordinal

In the mathematical discipline of set theory, there are many ways of describing specific countable ordinals. The smallest ones can be usefully and non-circularly expressed in terms of their Cantor normal forms. Beyond that, many ordinals of relevance to proof theory still have computable ordinal notations. However, it is not possible to decide effectively whether a given putative ordinal notation is a notation or not (for reasons somewhat analogous to the unsolvability of the halting problem); various more-concrete ways of defining ordinals that definitely have notations are available.

Since there are only countably many notations, all ordinals with notations are exhausted well below the first uncountable ordinal ω1; their supremum is called "Church–Kleene ω1" or ω1CK (not to be confused with ω1), described below. Ordinal numbers below ω1CK are the recursive ordinals (see below). Countable ordinals larger than this may still be defined, but do not have notations.

Due to the focus on countable ordinals, ordinal arithmetic is used throughout, except where otherwise noted. The ordinals described here are not as large as the ones described in large cardinals, but they are large among those which have constructive notations (descriptions). Larger and larger ordinals can be defined, but they become more and more difficult to describe.

Generalities on recursive ordinals

Ordinal notations

Recursive ordinals (or computable ordinals) are certain countable ordinals: loosely speaking those which can be represented by a computable function. There are several equivalent definitions of this: the simplest is to say that a computable ordinal is the order-type of some recursive (i.e., computable) well-ordering of the natural numbers; so, essentially, an ordinal is recursive when we can present the set of smaller ordinals in such a way that a computer (Turing machine, say) can manipulate them (and, essentially, compare them).

A different definition uses Kleene's system of ordinal notations: briefly, an ordinal notation is either the name zero (describing the ordinal 0), or the successor of an ordinal notation (describing the successor of the ordinal described by that notation), or a Turing machine (computable function) which produces an increasing sequence of ordinal notations (describing the ordinal which is the limit of the sequence), and ordinal notations are (partially) ordered so as to make the successor of "o" greater than "o" and to make the limit greater than any term of the sequence (this order is computable; however, the set O of ordinal notations itself is highly non-recursive, owing to the impossibility of deciding whether a given Turing machine does indeed produce a sequence of notations); a recursive ordinal is then an ordinal which is described by some ordinal notation.

Any ordinal smaller than a recursive ordinal is itself recursive, so the set of all recursive ordinals forms a certain (countable) ordinal, the Church-Kleene ordinal (see below).

It is tempting to forget about ordinal notations and only speak of the recursive ordinals themselves: and some statements are made about recursive ordinals which, in fact, concern the notations for these ordinals. This can lead to difficulties, however, as even the smallest infinite ordinal, ω, has many notations, some of which cannot be proven to be equivalent to the obvious notation (the limit of the simplest program which enumerates all natural numbers).

Relation to systems of arithmetic

We briefly (and somewhat informally) mention an important relation between computable ordinals and certain formal systems (containing arithmetic, that is, at least a reasonable fragment of Peano arithmetic).

In a nutshell, the idea is that certain computable ordinals are so large that while they can be given by a certain ordinal notation "o", a given formal system might not be sufficiently powerful to show that "o" is, indeed, an ordinal notation: the system does not show transfinite induction for such large ordinals.

For example, the usual first-order Peano axioms do not prove transfinite induction for (or beyond) ε0: while the ordinal ε0 can easily be arithmetically described (it is countable), the Peano axioms are not strong enough to show that it is indeed an ordinal; in fact, transfinite induction on ε0 proves the consistency of Peano's axiom (a theorem by Gentzen), so by Gödel's incompleteness theorem, Peano's axiom cannot formalize that reasoning. (This is at the basis of the Kirby-Paris theorem on Goodstein sequences.) We say that ε0 measures the proof-theoretic strength of Peano's axioms.

But we can do this for systems far beyond Peano's axioms. For example, the proof-theoretic strength of Kripke-Platek set theory is the Bachmann-Howard ordinal (see below), and, in fact, merely adding to Peano's axioms the axioms which state the well-ordering of all ordinals below the Bachmann-Howard ordinal is sufficient to obtain all arithmetical consequences of Kripke-Platek set theory.

Specific recursive ordinals

Predicative definitions and the Veblen hierarchy

We have already mentioned (see Cantor normal form) the ordinal ε0, which is the smallest satisfying the equation omega^alpha = alpha, so it is the limit of the sequence 0, 1, omega, omega^omega, omega^{omega^omega}, etc. The next ordinal satisfying this equation is called ε1: it is the limit of the sequence

:varepsilon_0+1, omega^{varepsilon_0+1}=varepsilon_0cdotomega, omega^{omega^{varepsilon_0+1=(varepsilon_0)^omega, etc.

More generally, the iota-th ordinal such that omega^alpha = alpha is called varepsilon_iota. We could define eta_0 as the smallest ordinal such that varepsilon_alpha=alpha, but since the Greek alphabet does not have transfinitely many letters it is better to use a more robust notation: define ordinals varphi_gamma(eta) by transfinite induction as follows: let varphi_0(eta) = omega^eta and let varphi_{gamma+1}(eta) be the eta-th fixed point of varphi_gamma (i.e., the eta-th ordinal such that varphi_gamma(alpha)=alpha; so for example, varphi_1(eta) = varepsilon_eta), and when delta is a limit ordinal, define varphi_delta(alpha) as the alpha-th common fixed point of the varphi_gamma for all gamma. This family of functions is known as the Veblen hierarchy. (There are inessential variations in the definition, such as letting, for delta a limit ordinal, varphi_delta(alpha) be the limit of the varphi_gamma(alpha) for gamma: this essentially just shifts the indices by 1, which is harmless.) varphi_gamma is called the gamma^{th} Veblen function (to the base omega).

Ordering: varphi_alpha(eta) < varphi_gamma(delta) if and only if either (alpha = gamma and eta < delta) or (alpha < gamma and eta < varphi_gamma(delta)) or (alpha > gamma and varphi_alpha(eta) < delta).

The Feferman-Schütte ordinal and beyond

The smallest ordinal such that varphi_alpha(0) = alpha is known as the Feferman-Schütte ordinal and generally written Gamma_0. It can be described as the set of all ordinals which can be written as finite expressions, starting from zero, using only the Veblen hierarchy and addition. The Feferman-Schütte ordinal is important because, in a sense that is rather complicated to make precise, it is the smallest (infinite) ordinal which cannot be (“predicatively”) described using smaller ordinals. It measures the strength of such systems as “arithmetical transfinite recursion”.

More generally, Γα enumerates the ordinals that cannot be obtained from smaller ordinals using addition and the Veblen functions.

It is, of course, possible to describe ordinals beyond the Feferman-Schütte ordinal. One could continue to seek fixed points in more and more complicated manner: enumerate the fixed points of alphamapstoGamma_alpha (the first of which is the Ackermann ordinal), then enumerate the fixed points of "that", and so on, and then look for the first ordinal α such that α is obtained in α steps of this process, and continue diagonalizing in this "ad hoc" manner. This leads to the definition of the “small” and “large” Veblen ordinals.

Impredicative ordinals

To go far beyond the Feferman-Schütte ordinal, one needs to introduce new methods. Unfortunately there is not yet any standard way to do this: every author in the subject seems to have invented their own system of notation, and it is quite hard to translate between the different systems. The first such system was introduced by Bachmann in 1950 (in an "ad hoc" manner), and different extensions and variations of it were described by Buchholz, Takeuti (ordinal diagrams), Feferman (θ systems), Aczel, Bridge, Schütte, and Pohlers. However most systems use the same basic idea, of constructing new countable ordinals by using the existence of certain uncountable ordinals. Here is an example of such a definition, described in much greater detail in the article on ordinal collapsing function:
*ψ(α) is defined to be the smallest ordinal that cannot be constructed by starting with 0, 1, ω and Ω, and repeatedly applying addition, multiplication and exponentiation, and ψ to previously constructed ordinals (except that ψ can only be applied to arguments less than α, to ensure that it is well defined).Here Ω = ω1 is the first uncountable ordinal. It is put in because otherwise the function ψ gets "stuck" at the smallest ordinal σ such that εσ=σ: in particular ψ(α)=σ for any ordinal α satisfying σ≤α≤Ω. However the fact that we included Ω allows us to get past this point: ψ(Ω+1) is greater than σ. The key property of Ω that we used is that it is greater than any ordinal which will be produced by ψ. This definition is impredicative, because it uses the uncountable ordinal Ω, which in some sense already uses all the countable ordinals we are trying to construct in its construction. Also, the least-fixed-point operator used in the Veblen hierarchy is not predicative. Predicativity beyond Gamma 0 [http://www.math.wustl.edu/~nweaver/gamma0.pdf] ]

To construct still larger ordinals, we can extend the definition of ψ by throwing in more ways of constructing uncountable ordinals. There are several ways to do this, described to some extent in the article on ordinal collapsing function.

The Bachmann-Howard ordinal (sometimes just called the Howard ordinal, ψ(εΩ+1) with the notation above) is an important one, because it describes the proof-theoretic strength of Kripke-Platek set theory. Indeed, the main importance of these large ordinals, and the reason to describe them, is their relation to certain formal systems as explained above. However, such powerful formal systems as full second-order arithmetic, let alone Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory, seem beyond reach for the moment.

&ldquo;Unrecursable&rdquo; recursive ordinals

By dropping the requirement of having a useful description, even larger recursive countable ordinals can be obtained as the ordinals measuring the strengths of various strong theories; roughly speaking, these ordinals are the smallest ordinals that the theories cannot prove are well ordered. By taking stronger and stronger theories such as second-order arithmetic, Zermelo set theory, Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory, or Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory with various large cardinal axioms, one gets some extremely large recursive ordinals. (Strictly speaking it is not known that all of these really are ordinals: by construction, the ordinal strength of a theory can only be proven to be an ordinal from an even stronger theory. So for the large cardinal axioms this becomes quite unclear.)

Beyond recursive ordinals

The Church-Kleene ordinal

The set of recursive ordinals is an ordinal which is the smallest ordinal which "cannot" be described in a recursive way (it is not the order type of any recursive well-ordering of the integers). That ordinal is a countable ordinal called the Church-Kleene ordinal, omega_1^{mathrm{CK. Thus, omega_1^{mathrm{CK is the smallest non-recursive ordinal, and there is no hope of precisely “describing” any ordinals from this point on &mdash; we can only "define" them. But it is still far less than the first uncountable ordinal, omega_1. However, as its symbol suggests, it behaves in many ways rather like omega_1.

Admissible ordinals

The Church-Kleene ordinal is again related to Kripke-Platek set theory, but now in a different way: whereas the Bachmann-Howard ordinal (described above) was the smallest ordinal for which KP does not prove transfinite induction, the Church-Kleene ordinal is the smallest α such that the construction of the Gödel universe, "L", up to stage α, yields a model L_alpha of KP. Such ordinals are called admissible, thus omega_1^{mathrm{CK is the smallest admissible ordinal (beyond ω in case the axiom of infinity is not included in KP).

By a theorem of Sacks, the countable admissible ordinals are exactly those which are constructed in a manner similar to the Church-Kleene ordinal but for Turing machines with oracles. One sometimes writes omega_alpha^{mathrm{CK for the alpha-th ordinal which is either admissible or limit of admissible.

Beyond admissible ordinals

An ordinal which is both admissible and a limit of admissibles, or equivalently such that alpha is the alpha-th admissible ordinal, is called "recursively inaccessible". There exists a theory of large ordinals in this manner which is highly parallel to that of (small) large cardinals. For example, we can define recursively Mahlo ordinals: these are the alpha such that every alpha-recursive closed unbounded subset of alpha contains an admissible ordinal (a recursive analog of the definition of a Mahlo cardinal). But note that we are still talking about possibly countable ordinals here! (While the existence of inaccessible or Mahlo cardinals cannot be proved in Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory, that of recursively inaccessible or recursively Mahlo ordinals is a theorem of ZFC: in fact, any regular cardinal is recursively Mahlo and more, but even if we limit ourselves to countable ordinals, ZFC proves the existence of recursively Mahlo ordinals. They are, however, beyond the reach of Kripke-Platek set theory.)

An admissible ordinal alpha is called "nonprojectible" if there is no total alpha-recursive injective function mapping alpha into a smaller ordinal. (This is trivially true for regular cardinals; however, we are mainly interested in countable ordinals.) Being nonprojectible is a much stronger condition than being admissible, recursively inaccessible, or even recursively Mahlo. It is equivalent to the statement that the Gödel universe, "L", up to stage α, yields a model L_alpha of KP + Sigma_1-separation.

&ldquo;Unprovable&rdquo; ordinals

We can imagine even larger ordinals which are still countable: for example, if ZFC has a transitive model (a hypothesis stronger than the mere hypothesis of consistency, and which is implied by the existence of an inaccessible cardinal), then there exists a countable alpha such that L_alpha is a model of ZFC. Such ordinals are beyond the strength of ZFC in the sense that it cannot (by construction) prove their existence. Even larger countable ordinals can be defined by indescribability conditions.

A pseudo-well-ordering

Within the scheme of notations of Kleene there are some which represent ordinals and some which do not. One can define a recursive total ordering which is a subset of the Kleene notations and has an initial segment which is well-ordered with order-type omega_1^{mathrm{CK. Every recursively enumerable (or even hyperarithmetic) subset of this total ordering has a least element. So it resembles a well-ordering in some respects. For example, one can define the arithmetic operations on it. Yet it is not possible to effectively determine exactly where the initial well-ordered part ends and the part lacking a least element begins.

References

Most books describing large countable ordinals are on proof theory, and unfortunately tend to be out of print.

On recursive ordinals

* W. Pohlers, "Proof theory", ISBN 0-387-51842-8 (for Veblen hierarchy and some impredicative ordinals). This is probably the most readable book on large countable ordinals (which is not saying much).
* G. Takeuti, "Proof theory", 2nd edition 1987 ISBN 0-444-10492-5 (for ordinal diagrams)
* K. Schütte, "Proof theory", Springer 1977 ISBN 0-387-07911-4 (for Veblen hierarchy and some impredicative ordinals)
*Smorynski, C. "The varieties of arboreal experience" Math. Intelligencer 4 (1982), no. 4, 182-189; contains an informal description of the Veblen hierarchy.
* "Theory of Recursive Functions and Effective Computability" by Hartley Rogers ISBN 0-262-68052-1 (describes recursive ordinals and the Church–Kleene ordinal)
* Larry W. Miller, [http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0022-4812%28197606%2941%3A2%3C439%3ANFACON%3E2.0.CO%3B2-E "Normal Functions and Constructive Ordinal Notations"] ,"The Journal of Symbolic Logic",volume 41,number 2,June 1976,pages 439 to 459.
* Hilbert Levitz, " [http://www.cs.fsu.edu/~levitz/ords.ps Transfinite Ordinals and Their Notations: For The Uninitiated] ", expository article (8 pages, in PostScript)
* Herman Ruge Jervell, [http://folk.uio.no/herman/incompleteness.pdf Truth and provability] , manuscript in progress.

Beyond recursive ordinals

*
* cite book | last=Hinman | first=Peter | middle=G. | title=Recursion-theoretic hierarchies
series = Perspectives in Mathematical Logic | publisher=Springer-Verlag | year=1978

Inline References


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Нужно сделать НИР?

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Large Veblen ordinal — In mathematics, the large Veblen ordinal is a certain large countable ordinal, named after Oswald Veblen. There is no standard notation for ordinals beyond the Feferman–Schütte ordinal Γ0. Most systems of notation use symbols such as psi;(α),… …   Wikipedia

  • Ordinal number — This article is about the mathematical concept. For number words denoting a position in a sequence ( first , second , third , etc.), see Ordinal number (linguistics). Representation of the ordinal numbers up to ωω. Each turn of the spiral… …   Wikipedia

  • Ordinal collapsing function — In mathematical logic and set theory, an ordinal collapsing function (or projection function) is a technique for defining (notations for) certain recursive large countable ordinals, whose principle is to give names to certain ordinals much larger …   Wikipedia

  • Ordinal analysis — In proof theory, ordinal analysis assigns ordinals (often large countable ordinals) to mathematical theories as a measure of their strength. The field was formed when Gerhard Gentzen in 1934 used cut elimination to prove, in modern terms, that… …   Wikipedia

  • Ordinal notation — In mathematical logic and set theory, an ordinal notation is a finite sequence of symbols from a finite alphabet which names an ordinal number according to some scheme which gives meaning to the language. There are many such schemes of ordinal… …   Wikipedia

  • Church–Kleene ordinal — In mathematics, the Church–Kleene ordinal, , is a large countable ordinal. It is the smallest non recursive ordinal. It is named after Alonzo Church and S. C. Kleene. References Church, Alonzo; Kleene, S. C. (1937), Formal definitions in the… …   Wikipedia

  • Small Veblen ordinal — In mathematics, the small Veblen ordinal is a certain large countable ordinal, named after Oswald Veblen. It is occasionally called the Ackermann ordinal, though the Ackermann ordinal described by harvtxt|Ackermann|1951 is somewhat smaller than… …   Wikipedia

  • Ackermann ordinal — In mathematics, the Ackermann ordinal is a certain large countable ordinal, named after Wilhelm Ackermann. The term Ackermann ordinal is also occasionally used for the small Veblen ordinal, a somewhat larger ordinal. Unfortunately there is no… …   Wikipedia

  • Bachmann–Howard ordinal — In mathematics, the Bachmann–Howard ordinal (or Howard ordinal) is a large countable ordinal.It is the proof theoretic ordinal of several mathematical theories, such as Kripke–Platek set theory (with the axiom of infinity) and the system CZF of… …   Wikipedia

  • Veblen ordinal — In mathematics, the Veblen ordinal is either of two large countable ordinals: *The small Veblen ordinal *The large Veblen ordinal …   Wikipedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”