- Category of sets
In
mathematics , the category of sets, denoted as Set, is the category whose objects are all sets and whosemorphism s are all functions. It is the most basic and the most commonly used category in mathematics.Properties of the category of sets
The
epimorphism s in Set are thesurjective maps, themonomorphism s are theinjective maps, and theisomorphism s are thebijective maps.The
empty set serves as theinitial object in Set withempty function s as morphisms. Every singleton is aterminal object , with the functions mapping all elements of the source sets to the single target element as morphisms. There are thus nozero object s in Set.The category Set is complete and co-complete. The product in this category is given by the
cartesian product of sets. The coproduct is given by thedisjoint union : given sets "A""i" where "i" ranges over some index set "I", we construct the coproduct as the union of "A""i"×{"i"} (the cartesian product with "i" serves to insure that all the components stay disjoint).Set is the prototype of a
concrete category ; other categories are concrete if they "resemble" Set in some well-defined way.Every two-element set serves as a
subobject classifier in Set. The power object of a set "A" is given by itspower set , and theexponential object of the sets "A" and "B" is given by the set of all functions from "A" to "B". Set is thus atopos (and in particular cartesian closed).Set is not abelian, additive or preadditive; it does not even have
zero morphism s.Every not initial object in Set is injective and (assuming the
axiom of choice ) also projective.Foundations for the category of sets
In
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory the collection of all sets is not a set, this follows from theaxiom of foundation . In this situation, one refers to the collection of all sets as aproper class . In ZF set theory, proper classes do not have any formal status. This is a problem: it means that the category of sets cannot be formalized straightforwardly in this setting.One way to resolve the problem is to work in a system that gives formal status to proper classes, such as
NBG set theory . In this setting, categories formed from sets are said to be "small" and those (like Set) that are formed from proper classes are said to be be "large".Another solution is to assume the existence of
Grothendieck universe s. Roughly speaking, a Grothendieck universe is a set which is itself a model of ZF(C) (for instance if a set belongs to a universe, its elements or its powerset will belong to the universe). The existence of universes is not implied by the usual ZF axioms; it is an additional, independent axiom. Assuming this extra axiom, the objects of Set can be defined to be the elements of a particular universe, rather than all the sets.Various other solutions, and variations on the above, have been proposed [Mac Lane, S. One universe as a foundation for category theory. Springer Lect. Notes Math. 106 (1969): 192–200. ] [Feferman, S. Set-theoretical foundations of category theory. Springer Lect. Notes Math. 106 (1969): 201–247.] [Blass, A. [http://www.math.lsa.umich.edu/~ablass/interact.pdf The interaction between category theory and set theory] . Contemporary Mathematics 30 (1984).] .
The same issues arise with other concrete categories, such as the
category of groups or thecategory of topological spaces .References
* (Volume 5 in the series
Graduate Texts in Mathematics )
Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.