- Intersection theory (mathematics)
In
mathematics , intersection theory is a branch ofalgebraic geometry , where subvarieties are intersected on analgebraic variety , and ofalgebraic topology , where intersections are computed within thecohomology ring . The theory for varieties is older, with roots inBézout's theorem on curves andelimination theory . On the other hand the topological theory more quickly reached a definitive form.Topological intersection form
For a connected oriented manifold "M" of dimension 2"n" the intersection form is defined on the "n"th
cohomology group (what is usually called the 'middle dimension') in the form of thecup product (in what follows, we can drop the orientability condition and work with coefficients). Stated precisely, there is abilinear form :
given by
:
This is a
quadratic form for "n" even, and analternating form for "n" odd, because of thegraded-commutative nature of the cohomology ring.These forms are important
topological invariant s. For example, a theorem ofMichael Freedman states thatsimply connected compact 4-manifold s are (almost) determined by their intersection forms up tohomeomorphism .By
Poincaré duality , it turns out that there is a way to think of this geometrically. Choose representative "n"-dimensional submanifolds "A", "B" for the Poincaré duals of "a" and "b". Then "Q""M"("a", "b") is the oriented intersection number of "A" and "B", which is well-defined because of the dimensions of "A" and "B". This explains the terminology "intersection form".Intersection theory in algebraic geometry
William Fulton in "Intersection Theory" (1984) writes
:" ... if A and B are subvarieties of a non-singular variety X, the intersection product A.B should be an equivalence class of algebraic cycles closely related to the geometry of how A∩B, A and B are situated in X. Two extreme cases have been most familiar. If the intersection is" proper", i.e. dim(A∩B) = dim A + dim B − dim X, then A.B is a linear combination of the irreducible components of A∩B, with coefficients the intersection multiplicities. At the other extreme, if A = B is a non-singular subvariety, the self-intersection formula says that A.B is represented by the top
Chern class of thenormal bundle of A in X."To give a definition, in the general case, of the intersection multiplicity was the major concern of
André Weil 's 1946 book "Foundations of Algebraic Geometry". Work in the 1920s of B. L. van der Waerden had already addressed the question; in theItalian school of algebraic geometry the ideas were well known, but foundational questions were not addressed in the same spirit.Moving cycles
A well-working machinery of intersecting
algebraic cycles "V" and "W" requires more than taking just the set-theoretic intersection of the cycles in question. Certainly, the intersection "V ∩ W" or, more commonly called "intersection product", denoted "V · W", should consist of the set-theoretic intersection of the two subvarieties. However it occurs that cycles are in bad position, e.g. two parallel lines in the plane, or a plane containing a line (intersecting in 3-space). In both cases the intersection should be a point, because, again, if one cycle is moved, this would be the intersection. The intersection of two cycles "V" and "W" is called "proper" if thecodimension of the (set-theoretic) intersection "V ∩ W" is the sum of the codimensions of "V" and "W", respectively, i.e. the "expected" value.Therefore the concept of "moving cycles" using appropriate
equivalence relations on algebraic cycles is used. The equivalence must be broad enough that given any two cycles "V" and "W", there are equivalent cycles "V' " and "W' " such that the intersection "V' ∩ W' " is proper. Of course, on the other hand, for a second equivalent "V" and "W", "V' ∩ W' " needs to be equivalent to "V" ∩ W".For the purposes of intersection theory, "rational equivalence" is the most important one. Briefly, two "r"-dimensional cycles on a variety "X" are rationally equivalent if there is a rational function "f" on a ("k+1")-dimensional subvariety "Y", i.e. an element of the
function field "k(Y)" or equivalently a function "f : Y" → P1, such that "V - W = f-1(0) - f-1(∞)", where "f-1(-)" is counted with multiplicities. Rational equivalence accomplishes the needs sketched above.Intersection multiplicities
The guiding principle in the definition of intersection multiplicities of cycles is continuity in a certain sense. Consider the following elementary example: the intersection of a parabola "y = x2" and an axis "y=0" should be "2·(0,0)", because if one of the cycles moves (yet in an undefined sense), there are precisely two intersection points which both converge to "(0,0)" when the cycles approach the depicted position. (The picture is misleading insofar as the apparently empty intersection of the parabola and the line "y=-3" is empty, because only the real solutions of the equations are depicted).
The first fully satisfactory definition of intersection multiplicities was given by
Serre : Let the ambient variety "X" be smooth (or all local rings regular). Further let "V" and "W" be two (irreducible reduced closed) subvarieties, such that their intersection is proper. The construction is local, therefore the varieties may be represented by two ideals "I" and "J" in the coordinate ring of "X". Let "Z" be an irreducible component of the set-theoretic intersection "V ∩ W" and "z" itsgeneric point . The multiplicity of "Z" in the intersection product "V · W" is defined by:, the alternating sum over the length over the local ring of "X" in "z" of torsion groups of the factor rings corresponding to the subvarieties. This expression is sometimes referred to as "Serre's Tor-formula".Remarks:
*The first summand, the length of is the "naive" guess of the multiplicity; however, as Serre shows, it is not sufficient.
*The sum is finite, because the regular local ring has finite Tor-dimension.
*If the intersection of "V" and "W" is not proper, the above multiplicity will be zero. If it is proper, it is strictly positive. (Both statements are not obvious from the definition).
*Using aspectral sequence argument, it can be shown that .The Chow ring
The
Chow ring is the group of algebraic cycles modulo rational equivalence together with the following commutative "intersection product"::where "V ∩ W = ∪︀ Zi" is the decomposition of the set-theoretic intersection into irreducible components.elf-intersection
Given two subvarieties "V" and "W," one can take their intersection , but it is also possible, though more subtle, to define the "self"-intersection of a single subvariety.
Given, for instance, a curve "C" on a surface "S", its intersection with itself (as sets) is just itself: . This clearly correct, but on the other hand unsatisfactory: given any two "distinct" curves on a surface (with no component in common), they intersect in some set of points, which for instance one can count, obtaining an "intersection number", and we may wish to do the same for a given curve: the analogy is that intersecting distinct curves is like multiplying two numbers: , while self-intersection is like squaring a single number: . Formally, the analogy is stated as a
symmetric bilinear form (multiplication) and aquadratic form (squaring).A geometric solution to this is to intersect the curve "C," not with itself, but with a slightly pushed off version of itself. In the plane, this just means translating the curve "C" in some direction, but in general one talks about taking a curve that is linearly equivalent to "C", and counting the intersection , thus obtaining an intersection number, denoted . Note that "unlike" for distinct curves "C" and "D", the "actual points of intersection" are not defined, because they depend on a choice of , but the “self intersection points of "C"” can be interpreted as "k"
generic point s on "C," where . More properly, the self-intersection points of "C" is "the" generic point of "C," taken with multiplicity .Alternatively, one can “solve” (or motivate) this problem algebraically by dualizing, and looking at the class of the – this both gives a number, and raises the question of a geometric interpretation. Note that passing to cohomology "classes" is analogous to replacing a curve by a linear system.
Note that self-intersection number can be negative, as the below example illustrates!
Examples
Consider a line "L" in the
projective plane : it has self-intersection number 1 since all other lines cross it once: one can push "L" off to , and (for any choice) of , hence . In terms of intersection forms, we say the plane has one of type (there is only one class of lines, and they all intersect with each other).Note that on the "affine" plane, one might push off to a parallel line, so (thinking geometrically) the number of intersection points depends on the choice of push-off. One says that “the affine plane does not have a good intersection theory”, and intersection theory on non-projective varieties is much more difficult.
A line on a (which can also be interpreted as the non-singular
quadric "Q" in "P"3) has self-intersection 0, since a line can be moved off itself. (It is aruled surface .) In terms of intersection forms, we say has one of type (which can also be stated under achange of basis ) – there are two basic classes of lines, which intersect each other in one point (), but have zero self-intersection (no or terms).Blow-ups
A key example of self-intersection numbers are the singular curve of a blow-up, which is a central operation in
birational geometry .Given an
algebraic surface "S",blowing up at a point creates a curve "C". This curve "C" is recognisable by its genus, which is 0, and its self-intersection number, which is −1. (This is not obvious.)Note that as a corollary, and are minimal surfaces (they are not blow-ups), since they do not have any curves with negative self-intersection.
In fact, Castelnuovo’s
contraction theorem states the converse: every -curve is the singular curve of some blow-up (it can be “blown down”).References
* | year=1998 | volume=2
* | year=1965 | volume=11
Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.