- Intentionality
The term intentionality is often simplistically summarised as "aboutness". According to the Oxford English Dictionary, it is "the distinguishing property of mental phenomena of being necessarily directed upon an object, whether real or imaginary". [ [http://dictionary.oed.com/cgi/entry/50118718?single=1&query_type=word&queryword=intentionality&first=1&max_to_show=10 "intentionality, n."
Oxford English Dictionary Additions Series.1993 .] OED Online.Oxford University Press . 17 Aug.2008 .] Originally intentionality was a concept from scholastic philosophy. The concept of intentionality was reintroduced in 19th-century contemporaryphilosophy by the philosopher and psychologistFranz Brentano in his work "Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint" (1874). Brentano defined intentionality as one characteristic of "mental phenomena", by which they could be distinguished from "physical phenomena" ("physische Phänomene"), using such phrases as "reference to a content", the "direction towards an object" and "the immanent objectivity".Overview
The theory of intentionality states that every mental phenomenon (that is, every psychological act) has a content, and is directed at an object (the "intentional object"). Intentionality states that every belief, desire, etc. has an object that it is about: the believed, the wanted, etc.. Brentano used the expression "intentional inexistence" (existence in) to indicate the status of the objects of thought in the mind. The property of being intentional, of having an intentional object, was the key feature to distinguish mental phenomena and physical phenomena, because physical phenomena lack intentionality altogether.
Through the works of Husserl, who took it over from Brentano, the concept of intentionality received more widespread attention in current philosophy, both continental and analytic. French philosopher
Jean-Paul Sartre , in "Being and Nothingness ", identified intentionality withconsciousness , stating that they were indistinguishable from one another, a position that was a stark contrast to Brentano's position that intentionality is but one quality of mental phenomena. German philosopherMartin Heidegger , in "Being and Time ", defined intentionality as "care" ("Sorge"), a sentient condition where an individual's existentiality, facticity, and forfeiture to the world identifies their ontological significance, in contrast to that which is the mereontic (thinghood).Modern views
Other twentieth century philosophers such as
Gilbert Ryle andA J Ayer have been critical of Husserl's concept of intentionality and his many layers of consciousness, Ryle insisting that perceiving is not a process and Ayer that describing one's knowledge is not to describe mental processes. The effect of these positions is that consciousness is so fully intentional that the mental act has been emptied of all content and the idea of pure consciousness is that it is nothing (Sartre also referred to "consciousness" as "nothing ").Platonist Roderick Chisholm has revived the Brentano thesis through linguistic analysis, distinguishing two parts to Brentano's concept, the ontological aspect and the psychological aspect. Chisholm's writings have attempted to summarize the suitable and unsuitable criteria of the concept since the Scholastics, arriving at a criterion of intentionality identified by the two aspects of Brentano's thesis and defined by the logical properties that distinguish language describing psychological phenomena from language describing non-psychological phenomena. Chisholm's criteria for the intentional use of sentences are:existence independence ,truth-value indifference , and referential opacity.In current
artificial intelligence andphilosophy of mind intentionality is a controversial subject and sometimes claimed to be something that a machine will never achieve.John Searle argued for this position with theChinese room thought experiment, according to which nosyntactic operations that occurred in a computer would provide it withsemantic content. As he noted in the article, Searle's view was a minority position in artificial intelligence and philosophy of mind.
=Dennett'sTaxonomy of Current Theories about Intentionality=Daniel Dennett offers a taxonomy of the current theories about intentionality in Chapter 10 of his book "The Intentional Stance". Most, if not all, current theories on intentionality accept Brentano's thesis of the irreducibility of intentional idiom. From this thesis the following positions emerge:
*intentional idiom is problematic for science;
*intentional idiom is not problematic for science, which is divided into:
**Eliminative Materialism ;
**Realism;
**Quinean double standard (see below) which is divided into:
***adherence to Normative Principle, which is divided into:
****who makes anAssumption of Rationality ;
****who follows the Principle of Charity;
***adherence toProjective Principle .Is Intentional Idiom problematic for Science?
Chisholm (1956), Anscombe (1957), Geach (1957), and Taylor (1964) all adhere to the former position, namely that intentional idiom is problematic and cannot be integrated with the natural sciences. Members of this category also maintain realism in regard to intentional objects, which may imply some kind of dualism (though this is debatable).
The latter position, which maintains the unity of intentionality with the natural sciences, is further divided into three standpoints:
*Eliminative Materialism, supported by
W.V. Quine (1960) and Churchland (1981)
*Realism, advocated byJerry Fodor (1975), as well as Burge, Dretske, Kripke, and the earlyHilary Putnam
*those who adhere to the Quinean double standard.Intentionality is not problematic for science
Proponents of the eliminative materialism, understand intentional idiom, such as "belief", "desire", and the like, to be replaceable either with behavioristic language (e.g. Quine) or with the language of neuroscience (e.g. Churchland).
Holders of realism argue, in contrast to those in support of C, that there is a deeper fact of the matter to both translation and belief attribution. In other words, manuals for translating one language into another cannot be set up in different yet behaviorally identical ways and ontologically there are intentional objects. Famously, Fodor has attempted to ground such realist claims about intentionality in a language of thought. Dennett comments on this issue, Fodor "attempt [s] to make these irreducible realities acceptable to the physical sciences by grounding them (somehow) in the 'syntax' of a system of physically realized mental representations" (Dennett 1987, 345).
Those who adhere to the so-called Quinean double standard (namely that "ontologically there is nothing intentional, but that the language of intentionality is indispensable"), accept Quine's thesis of the indeterminacy of radical translation and its implications, while the other positions so far mentioned do not. As Quine puts it, indeterminacy of radical translation is the thesis that "manuals for translating one language into another can be set up in divergent ways, all compatible with the totality of speech dispositions, yet incompatible with one another" (Quine 1960, 27). Quine (1960) and
Wilfrid Sellars (1958) both comment on this intermediary position. One such implication would be that there is, in principle, no deeper fact of the matter that could settle two interpretative strategies on what belief to attribute to a physical system. In other words, the behavior (including speech dispositions) of any physical system, in theory, could be interpreted by two different predictive strategies and both would be equally warranted in their belief attribution. This category can be seen to be a medial position between the realists and the eliminativists since it attempts to blend attributes of both into a theory of intentionality. Dennett, for example, argues in "True Believers" (1981) that intentional idiom (or "folk psychology ") is a predictive strategy and if such a strategy successfully and voluminously predicts the actions of a physical system, then that physical system can be said to have those beliefs attributed to it. Dennett calls this predictive strategy theintentional stance .They are further divided into two thesis:
*adherence to the Normative Principle
*adherence to the Projective PrincipleAdvocates of the former, the Normative Principle, argue that attributions of intentional idioms to physical systems should be the propositional attitudes that the physical system ought to have in those circumstances (Dennett 1987, 342). However, exponents of this view are still further divided into those who make an Assumption of Rationality and those who adhere to the Principle of Charity. Dennett (1969, 1971, 1975), Cherniak (1981, 1986), and the late Putnam (1983) recommend the Assumption of Rationality, which unsurprisingly assumes that the physical system in question is rational.
Donald Davidson (1967, 1973, 1974, 1985) and Lewis (1974) defend the Principle of Charity.The latter is advocated by Grandy (1973) and Stich (1980, 1981, 1983, 1984), who maintain that attributions of intentional idioms to any physical system (e.g. humans, artifacts, non-human animals, etc.) should be the propositional attitude (e.g. "belief", "desire", etc.) that one would suppose one would have in the same circumstances (Dennett 1987, 343).
Basic kinds of intentionality in Le Morvan
Working on the intentionality of vision, belief, and knowledge, Pierre Le Morvan (2005) has distinguished between three basic kinds of intentionality that he dubs "transparent," "translucent," and "opaque" respectively. The three-fold distinction may be explained as follows. Let's call the "intendum" what an intentional state is about, and the "intender" the subject who is in the intentional state. An intentional state is transparent if it satisfies the following two conditions: (i) it is genuinely relational in that it entails the existence of not just the intender but the intendum as well, and (ii) substitutivity of identicals applies to the intendum (i.e. if the intentional state is about a, and a = b, then the intentional state is about b as well). An intentional state is translucent if it satisfies (i) but not (ii). An intentional state is opaque if it satisfies neither (i) nor (ii).
Intentionality vs. intensionality
Intentionality should not be confused with
intension ality, a concept fromsemantics though it is related to the modern understanding ofintention .ee also
*
Alexius Meinong
*A J Ayer
*consciousness
*superintelligence
*Daniel Dennett
*Edmund Husserl
*Gilbert Ryle
*Intention
*Jean-Paul Sartre
* Antonio Millan-Puelles
*John Searle
*Martin Heidegger
*mind-body problem
*Roderick Chisholm
*Thomas Nagel
*Wilfrid Sellars
*Ruth Millikan References
* Chisholm, Roderick M. "Intentionality" in "The Encyclopedia of Philosophy". MacMillan, N.Y., 1967.
* Chisholm, Roderick M. "Notes on the Logic of Believing". "Philosophy and Phenomenological Research". Vol. 24: 195-201, 1963.
* Chisholm, Roderick M. "Perceiving: A Philosophical Study". Ithaca, N.Y., 1957.
* Dennett, Daniel C. "The Intentional Stance". Massachusetts: Cambridge, 1987.
* Husserl, Edmund. "Ideas: General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology."
* Husserl, Edmund. "Logical Investigations."
* Le Morvan, Pierre. "Intentionality: Transparent, Translucent, and Opaque". "The Journal of Philosophical Research," 30, pp. 283-302. 2005.
* Malle, B. F., Moses, L. J., & Baldwin, D. A. (Eds.). "Intentions and intentionality: Foundations of social cognition." Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, ISBN 0-262-13386-5.
* Mohanty, Jitendra Nath. "The Concept of Intentionality: A Critical Study". St. Louis, MO: Warren H. Green, 1972.
*Quine, W.V. "Word and Object". Massachusetts: Cambridge, 1960.Notes
Further reading
* Davidson, Donald. "Truth and Meaning". Synthese, XVII, pp. 304-23. 1967.
* Fodor, J. "The Language of Thought". Hassocks, Sussex: Harvester Press; Scranton, PA: Crowell, 1975.
* Sajama, Seppo & Kamppinen, Matti. "Historical Introduction to Phenomenology". New York, NY: Croom Helm, 1987.
* Stich, Stephen. "Relativism, Rationality, and the Limits of Intentional Description". Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 65, pp.211-35. 1984.External links
*Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy:
** [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/intentionality/ Intentionality]
** [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/consciousness-intentionality/ Consciousness and Intentionality]
** [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/intentionality-ancient/ Ancient Theories of Intentionality]
Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.