Converse (logic)

Converse (logic)

In logic, the converse of a categorical or implicational statement is the result of reversing its two parts. For the implication PQ, the converse is QP. For the categorical proposition All S is P, the converse is All P is S. In neither case does the converse necessarily follow from the original statement.[1] The categorical converse of a statement is contrasted with the contrapositive and the obverse.

Contents

Implicational converse

If S is a statement of the form P implies Q (PQ), then the converse of S is the statement Q implies P (QP). In general, the verity of S says nothing about the verity of its converse, unless the antecedent P and the consequent Q are logically equivalent.

For example, consider the true statement "If I am a human, then I am mortal." The converse of that statement is "If I am mortal, then I am a human," which is not necessarily true.

On the other hand, the converse of a statement with mutually inclusive terms remains true, given the truth of the original proposition. Thus, the statement "If I am a bachelor, then I am unmarried" is logically equivalent to "If I am unmarried, then I am a bachelor."

A truth table makes it clear that S and the converse of S are not logically equivalent unless both terms imply each other:

P Q PQ QP (converse)
T T T T
T F F T
F T T F
F F T T

Going from a statement to its converse is the fallacy of affirming the consequent. However, if the statement S and its converse are equivalent (i.e. if P is true if and only if Q is also true), then affirming the consequent will be valid.

Converse of a theorem

In mathematics, the converse of a theorem of the form PQ will be QP. The converse may or may not be true. If true, the proof may be difficult. For example, the Four-vertex theorem was proved in 1912, but its converse only in 1998.

In practice, when determining the converse of a mathematical theorem, aspects of the antecedent may be taken as establishing context. That is, the converse of Given P, if Q then R will be Given P, if R then Q. For example, the Pythagorean theorem can be stated as:

Given a triangle with sides of length a, b, and c, if the angle opposite the side of length c is a right angle, then a2 + b2 = c2.

The converse, which also appears in Euclid's Elements (Book I, Proposition 48), can be stated as:

Given a triangle with sides of length a, b, and c, if a2 + b2 = c2, then the angle opposite the side of length c is a right angle.

Categorical converse

In traditional logic, the process of going from All S is P to its converse All P is S is called conversion. In the words of Asa Mahan, "The original proposition is called the exposita; when converted, it is denominated the converse. Conversion is valid when, and only when, nothing is asserted in the converse which is not affirmed or implied in the exposita."[2] The "exposita" is more usually called the "convertend." In its simple form, conversion is valid only for E and I propositions:[3]

Type Convertend Simple converse Converse per accidens
A All S is P not valid Some P is S
E No S is P No P is S Some P is not S
I Some S is P Some P is S
O Some S is not P not valid

The validity of simple conversion only for E and I propositions can be expressed by the restriction that "No term must be distributed in the converse which is not distributed in the convertend."[4] For E propositions, both subject and predicate are distributed, while for I propositions, neither is.

For A propositions, the subject is distributed while the predicate is not, and so the inference from an A statement to its converse is not valid. As an example, for the A proposition "All cats are mammals," the converse "All mammals are cats" is obviously false. However, the weaker statement "Some mammals are cats" is true. Logicians define conversion per accidens to be the process of producing this weaker statement. Inference from a statement to its converse per accidens is generally valid. However, as with syllogisms, this switch from the universal to the particular causes problems with empty categories: "All unicorns are mammals" is often taken as true, while the converse per accidens "Some mammals are unicorns" is clearly false.

In first-order predicate calculus, All S is P can be represented as \forall x. S(x) \to P(x).[5] It is therefore clear that the categorical converse is closely related to the implicational converse, and that S and P cannot be swapped in All S is P.

See also

References

  1. ^ Robert Audi, ed. (1999), The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, 2nd ed., Cambridge University Press: "converse".
  2. ^ Asa Mahan (1857), The Science of Logic: or, An Analysis of the Laws of Thought, p. 82.
  3. ^ William Thomas Parry and Edward A. Hacker (1991), Aristotelian Logic, SUNY Press, p. 207.
  4. ^ James Hervey Hyslop (1892), The Elements of Logic, C. Scribner's sons, p. 156.
  5. ^ Gordon Hunnings (1988), The World and Language in Wittgenstein's Philosophy, SUNY Press, p. 42.

Further reading

  • Aristotle. Organon.
  • Copi, Irving. Introduction to Logic. MacMillan, 1953.
  • Copi, Irving. Symbolic Logic. MacMillan, 1979, fifth edition.
  • Stebbing, Susan. A Modern Introduction to Logic. Cromwell Company, 1931.

Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Поможем решить контрольную работу

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Converse — may refer to: Converse accident, a type of logical fallacy Conversion (linguistics), a kind of word formation Converse (logic), a concept in logic Religious conversion, the adaption of a new religious belief Converse (shoe company), an American… …   Wikipedia

  • Converse implication — is the converse of implication. That is to say; that for any two propositions P and Q, if Q implies P, then P is the converse implication of Q. It may take the following forms: p⊂q, Bpq, or p←q Contents 1 Definition 1.1 Truth table 1.2 …   Wikipedia

  • Converse — Con verse, n. 1. (Logic) A proposition which arises from interchanging the terms of another, as by putting the predicate for the subject, and the subject for the predicate; as, no virtue is vice, no vice is virtue. [1913 Webster] Note: It should… …   The Collaborative International Dictionary of English

  • converse — converse1 [kən vʉrs′; ] for n. [ kän′vʉrs΄] vi. conversed, conversing [ME conversen < OFr converser < L conversari, to live with, keep company with, freq. of convertere: see CONVERT] 1. to hold a conversation; talk 2. Obs. to consort;… …   English World dictionary

  • Converse nonimplication — In logic, converse nonimplication is a logical connective which is the negation of the converse of implication. Contents 1 Definition 1.1 Truth table 1.2 Venn diagram …   Wikipedia

  • logic — logicless, adj. /loj ik/, n. 1. the science that investigates the principles governing correct or reliable inference. 2. a particular method of reasoning or argumentation: We were unable to follow his logic. 3. the system or principles of… …   Universalium

  • converse — converse1 converser, n. v. /keuhn verrs /; n. /kon verrs/, v., conversed, conversing, n. v.i. 1. to talk informally with another or others; exchange views, opinions, etc., by talking. 2. Archaic. to maintain a familiar association (usually fol.… …   Universalium

  • Converse — /kon verrs/, n. Frederick Shepherd /shep euhrd/, 1871 1940, U.S. composer. * * * ▪ logic       in logic, the proposition resulting from an interchange of subject and predicate with each other. Thus, the converse of “No man is a pencil” is “No… …   Universalium

  • Logic — For other uses, see Logic (disambiguation). Philosophy …   Wikipedia

  • converse — I. verb (i) /kənˈvɜs / (say kuhn vers) (conversed, conversing) 1. (sometimes followed by with) to talk informally with another; interchange thought by speech. –noun /ˈkɒnvɜs / (say konvers) 2. familiar discourse or talk; conversation. {Middle… …  

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”