- Gareth Evans (philosopher)
Gareth Evans (
12 May 1946 –10 August 1980 ) was a Britishphilosopher atOxford University during the 1970s.Life
Gareth Evans studied
Philosophy, Politics and Economics (PPE) at University College, Oxford (1964–67). His philosophy tutor wasPeter Strawson . He then became a senior scholar atChrist Church, Oxford (1967–68) and aKennedy Scholar atHarvard University andUniversity of California, Berkeley (1968–69). He died in 1980 of lung cancer at the age of 34, "a serious loss for British philosophy" according to the "Oxford Companion to Philosophy". His collected papers (1985) and a book, "The Varieties of Reference" (1982), edited by John McDowell, were published posthumously.Work
In his brief career Evans made substantial contributions to
logic ,metaphysics ,philosophy of language , andphilosophy of mind . Aside from Strawson,Michael Dummett andJohn McDowell were important influences on his work.Evans was one of many in the UK who took up the project of developing formal
semantics fornatural language s, instigated by Donald Davidson in the 1960s and 1970s. He co-edited "Truth and Meaning" (1976) withJohn McDowell on this subject. He also wrote a paper, "The Causal Theory of Names" (1973), which heavily criticized certain lines of the theory ofreference that derived fromKripke 's "Naming and Necessity " (1972/1980) and work byKeith Donnellan .A one-page paper in "Analysis", "Can There Be Vague Objects?" (1978), drew dozens of papers in response and is now considered a key work in metaphysics.
Varieties of Reference
Evans's book "The Varieties of Reference" (1982) was unfinished at the time of his death. It was edited for publication, and supplemented with appendices drawn from his notes, by McDowell, and has subsequently been influential in both philosophy of mind and philosophy of language.
Background
The theory of reference prior to the 1970s was dominated by the view that the meaning of an ordinary
name is a description of its object: so, for example, "Aristotle " means "the author of "De Caelo"." This was Russell's view, and was and is taken by many to be equivalent to Frege's view (where the "description" is what Frege calls a term's "sense"). Following Kripke's "Naming and Necessity" (1972/1980) lectures, the view came to prevail that names had no descriptive content, or sense: that the referent of a name was not what "fit" its meaning, but whichever object had been the initial cause of the name's being used.Evans's project
Evans concedes that names do not in general have descriptive meanings (although he contends that they could, in some cases), but argues that the proponents of the new theory had much too simplistic a view. He argues for what he calls "Russell's Principle": that a person cannot be thinking about an object unless he knows, in some non-trivial way, which object he is thinking about. In particular, Evans argues that a person must have a "discriminating conception" of the object (1982, p. 65).
From Russell's work, Evans also draws the point that some of the thoughts one has (thoughts about objects one is perceiving, for example) are such that if their object did not exist it would not be possible to think that thought at all. These he calls "Russellian thoughts".
He then claims that a certain version of the new theory, which he calls the "Photograph Model" of mental representation (1982, p. 78), violates Russell's Principle. According to the Photograph Model, "the causal antecedents of the information involved in a mental state... are claimed to be sufficient to determine which object the state concerns" (1982, p. 78). (The view is so named because it is similar to the view many people take on how a photography comes to be about something.) Thus, on the Photograph Model, contrary to Russell's Principle, one may have a thought about some object without discriminating knowledge of that object, just so long as the mental state is caused in the appropriate way (for example, perhaps by some sort of causal chain that originates with the object).
Evans argues that any causal theory, like that of the Photograph Model, must be restricted in certain ways: it is necessary to consider, one by one, the various kinds of Russellian thoughts people can have about objects, and to specify in each case what conditions must be met for them to meet Russell's Principle--only under those conditions can one have a thought about a specific object or objects (a "singular thought").
In particular, Evans discusses at length what he calls the "Generality Constraint". Evans states it thus:
...if a subject can be credited with the thought that "a" is "F", then he must have the conceptual resources for entertaining the thought that "a" is "G", for every property of being "G" of which he has a conception (1982, p. 104).
The Generality Constraint, according to Evans, is intended to capture the structure that there is in thought. As Evans puts it, "The thought that John is happy has something in common with the thought that Harry is happy, and the thought that John is happy has something in common with the thought that John is sad" (1982, p. 100). The Generality Constraint requires that if one is to have a thought (that John is happy, for example) about an object (John), then one must be able to conceive of the object (John) as having different properties (such as being sad).
He also defends a reading of Frege, derived in part from
Michael Dummett 's work, according to which Frege's notion of sense is not equivalent to a description, and indeed remains essential to a theory of reference that abandoned descriptivism (1982, §1.3).Kinds of reference
The bulk of the text considers three kinds of reference to objects, and argues for a number of conditions that must obtain for reference to occur.
He considers first
demonstrative reference, where one speaks or thinks about an object visible in one's vicinity. He argues that these presuppose, among other things: having a correct conception of the kind of object that it is; the ability to conceive of it and oneself as located in an objective space, and to orient oneself within that space; that one must move smoothly through time and space and be able to track the object's movements continuously in perception.He next considers reference to oneself and then reference by way of a capacity for recognition: one's ability to (re-)identify an object when presented with it, even if it is not available at present. Evans famously considers the phenomenon of "Immunity to Error Through Misidentification"--a phenomenon of certain types of judgment in which one cannot be wrong about which object the judgment is about by misidentifying it (see his 1982, especially §6.6 & §7.2). This phenomenon may be exemplified by the incoherence of the following judgment (upon feeling pain): "Someone seems to be feeling pain, but is it "I" who is feeling the pain?". While this phenomenon has been noticed by philosophers before, Evans argues that they have tended to think that it only applies to judgments concerning oneself and one's conscious experiences, and so they have failed to recognize that it is a more general phenomenon that can occur in any sort of demonstrative judgment. Furthermore, philosophers such as
Ludwig Wittgenstein (in his "Blue and Brown Books" [1958] ) andElizabeth Anscombe (in her "The First Person" [1975] ) have wrongly concluded that such cases show that the first-person pronoun "I" does not refer to anything.Language issues
In the last third of the book Evans turns to problems with reference to objects that actively depend on the use of language. Here he treats the use of proper names, which do not seem to presuppose as much knowledge on the part of the speaker as demonstrative or recognition-based identification. One can refer to an object one has never encountered using a name if the name was received in the right sort of linguistic (social) practice--even, apparently, if one has no true beliefs about the object. He also considers problems of reference to objects in fictions and hallucinations, and to the meaning of saying that something exists which doesn't. (Here he draws explicitly on Kripke's never-published
John Locke lectures , "Reference and Existence".)Selected Publications
* 1973, "The Causal Theory of Names," "Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume" xlvii, pp. 187-208.
* 1975, "Identity and Predication," "Journal of Philosophy" lxxii, pp. 343-363.
* 1976(a), "Truth and Meaning: Essays in Semantics" (co-edited with John McDowell), Oxford: Oxford University Press.
* 1976(b), "Semantic Structure and Logical Form," in Evans and McDowell (eds.) 1976(a), pp. 199-222.
* 1977, "Pronouns, Quantifiers, and Relative Clauses" (I), "Canadian Journal of Philosophy" vii, pp. 467-536.
* 1978, "Can There Be Vague Objects?" "Analysis" Vol. 38, No. 4, p. 208.
* 1979, "Reference and Contingency," "The Monist" lxii, pp. 161-189.
* 1980, "Pronouns," "Linguistic Inquiry" xi, pp. 337-362.
* 1980, "Things Without the Mind," in Zak van Staaten (ed.) "Philosophical Subjects: Essays Presented to P.F. Strawson", Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 76-116.
* 1981, "Understanding Demonstratives," in Herman Parret and Jacques Bouveresse (eds.) "Meaning and Understanding", Berlin and New York: De Gruyter, pp. 280-303.
* 1982, "The Varieties of Reference" (published posthumously, edited by John McDowell), Oxford: Oxford University Press.
* 1985, "Collected Papers", Oxford: Oxford University Press.References and Further Reading
* Davies, Martin, [http://philrsss.anu.edu.au/~mdavies/papers/evans.pdf Gareth Evans (12 May 1946 – 10 August 1980)] . In Donald M. Borchert (editor), "The Encyclopedia of Philosophy", 2nd edition. Macmillan Reference, USA.
* Evans, Gareth (1982), "The Varieties of Reference", edited by John McDowell, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
* Kripke, Saul (1972), "Naming and Necessity", in "Semantics of Natural Language", edited by D. Davidson and G. Harman. Dordrecht; Boston: Reidel. (Published on its own as a book in 1980.)Resources
* Rick Grush's [http://mind.ucsd.edu/misc/resources/evans/evansindex.html Guide to Gareth Evans's "Varieties of Reference"] .
Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.