- War in the Age of Intelligent Machines
"War in the Age of Intelligent Machines" (1991) is a book by
Manuel de Landa that traces thehistory of warfare and of technology. It is influenced in part byMichel Foucault 's "Discipline and Punish " (1978), and also reinterprets the concepts ofwar machine s and themachinic phylum , introduced in Deleuze and Guattari's "A Thousand Plateaus " (1980). Deleuze & Guattari appreciated Foucault's definition of philosophy as a "tool box" that was to encourage thinking about new ideas. Thus, they themselves prepared the field for a reappropriation of their concepts, that is, a different use in another context of the "same" concept, which they also theorized under the name of "actualization ". Manuel de Landa wisely takes advantage of the liberty these authors offered to draw on their concepts in order to investigate his field of studies: the history of warfare and technologies.A social history of technology and of warfare
An
invention always needs to be inserted in social practices to become an effective technologicalinnovation . Deleuze and Guattari pointed out how thefeudal assemblage was composed of three heterogeneous components: thestirrup , thelance and theknight [http://courses.nus.edu.sg/course/elljwp/deleuzeandguattari.htm] . Technology is thus inserted in social practices, creating the specificwar machine of each social formation. "Tactical integration of new weapons has always been a lengthy process.Rifled firearms , for example, were available tohunters andduel ists for over a century before they found their way into the war machine. The tactics of most European armies were based on the volume of fire delivered rather than on the accuracy of individual shots." (p.170) Manuel de Landa thus describes how social and economic formations influence the war machine, i.e. the form of armies, according to each historical period. Quoting warfare historians, he thus shows, for example, how theRoman empire created a phalanx from a centralizedstate , a political form not characteristic of the Greek cities. Manuel de Landa draws onchaos theory to show how thebiosphere reaches singularities (or bifurcations) which markself-organization thresholds whereemergent properties are displayed, and claims that the "mecanosphere ", constituted by the machinic phylum, possesses similar qualities. Examples of such systems include theatmosphere , thesolar system ,plate tectonics ,turbulent fluids ,economics , andpopulation growth . QuotingFernand Braudel 's meteorological metaphor toMachiavelli 'sItaly as a "low pressure area ", de Landa shows for example how a certain level of population growth may induceinvasion s and others wars. Population thus reaches a specific point where it changes nature: just as asolid may be transformed into aliquid if it reaches a specific singularity, which had to be traced by endless trials in the early creation ofalloys — the point where two different metals, put together, become a new metal — this track has been refined by modernmilitary engineers , who are supported bythink tanks in their efforts.As a historian, Manuel de Landa is thus indebted to Fernand Braudel's "
Annales School " and the study of long-scale historical phenomena, as opposed to human-scale phenomena. However, both authors are far from any technologicaldeterminism , which would read history as the linear succession of technological progress. Like Foucault's "archeology", Manuel de Landa'sphilosophy of technology leaves openings for various causal series which interfers together. But as in "A Thousand Years of Nonlinear History " (1997), de Landa doesn't allow this perspective to justify anyanthropocentrism conception of history, which would be centered on teleological progress. Thus, instead of opposing theman to themachine as in classic philosophy, he plays on the interactions between the war machines and the machinic phylum. For example, he writes:"The machinic phylum, seen as technology's own internal dynamics and cutting edge, could still be seen shining through the brilliant civilian discoveries of the
transistor and theintegrated chip , which had liberated electronic circuit designs from the constraints on their possible complexity. But the military had already begun to tighten its grip on the evolution of the phylum, on the events happening at its cutting edge, channeling its forces but limiting its potential mutations" (p.153).The next threshold point, or singularity, to be reached, according to de Landa, is the point where man and machine cease to oppose themselves, becoming one single war machine, and when that war machine itself is crossed by the machinic phylum — this last condition might be compared to Deleuze's call for the desiring molecular machines to use the social machines, instead of being composed and manipulated in order to form a complex molar machines. The developments of
artificial intelligence , which will sooner or later lead to the creation of "predatory machines ", that is intelligent machines. Even if "the advent of [truly autonomous weapons] may be quite far in the future, the "will" to endow machines with predatory capabilities has been institutionalized in the [US] military" (p.128) warns de Landa. This disconnection of the war machines from the machinic phylum, of the military institution from the social formation, may result in erratic war machines that become nomads because of a lack of political control: if battles are notstrategically ordered following political objectives, then even their victories become meaningless. In this specific case, thepositive feedback between the war machine and the machinic phylum is broken. Such positive feedback may be illustrated by thevirtuous circle between the raising oftax es, which permits funding for the creation of professional armies, used in monarchs' wars with other heads of state, but also used to maintainpublic order , and thus favoritizeseconomic growth and supports the amelioration of current armies; a positive feedback seen by themercantilism movement). But an army that loses its political goals is doomed to permanently remain on the move, following rivers in order to be able to survive off the territory it occupies: its sheer size forces it tonomadism . In this sense, nomadism may be considered as the failure of the war machine, which has become its own end in itself, disconnected from any social needs and energies. However, de Landa's warning against a certain military conception of technology and of warfare is not presented at all as aprophecy that describes the future withfatalism . Like some other critical theorists, Manuel de Landa avoids the trap that would force one to choose between plain simple unilateral technological oreconomic determinism (as invulgar Marxism ) and liberalindividualism , which denies the existence ofideology (a denegation that Althusser has demonstrated was itself ideologically founded).Science fiction may refer to this previsioned radical shift toautonomous warfare as atechnological singularity , although de Landa would probably argue that this singularity or bifurcation is yet another emergent property of the biosphere, which has led to the creation of a "mecanosphere" centered on the machinic phylum. In yet another passage, Manuel de Landa writes:"I defined the machinic phylum as the set of all the singularities at the onset of processes of self-organization — the critical points in the flow of matter and energy, points at which these flows spontaneously acquire a new form or pattern. All these processes, involving elements as different as molecules, cells or termites, may be represented by a few mathematical models. Thus, because one and the same singularity may be said to trigger two very different self-organizing effects, the singularity is said to be 'mechanism independent' " (p.132)
If "a same singularity may be said to trigger two very different self-organizing effects", neither
technophobia , as presented by Virilio's work, ortechnophilia are justified in themselves. Manuel de Landa demonstrates that de-centering history from a human perspective is not necessarily denying human freedom, opposing himself to those who would argue, for example, thatLouis Althusser 's explicit "antihumanism " and insistence on Ideological State Apparatuses (I.S.A.) instead of on the universal and individual subject would be a form ofMarxism opposed to the Enlightenment's ideals.Centralization and decentralization
According to de Landa, centralization and decentralization are two trends in the "war machine": either military commanders try to centralize command and control of each event on the battlefield, and get "human will out of the decision-making loop" or, to the contrary, they delegate responsibility to
individual soldiers (e.g.platoons or the Germanmission-type tactics ) in order to avoid "friction". "Friction", according to de Landa, is like "noise " — too much undispersed friction blocks the war machine, which destroys itself. Thus, rather than waiting for friction to accumulate at the head of the control, command and communication center (C3), which is the case in centralized armies, decentralized war machines allow it to disperse itself at each level of the machine.The 1805
Jacquard loom , which used the holes punched in pasteboardpunch cards to control the weaving of patterns in fabric, is the first example of a "migration" of human control to machines control, and marks the invention ofsoftware according to de Landa. Command and control techniques adapted by the German were then introduced in armyarsenal s by Frederick Taylor and extended to civilian society: "the imposition of military production methods into the civilian society was accompanied by the transfer of a whole command and control grid." (p.153) The system ofNumerical control — and then theCNC — which was developed by funds from the US Air Force, "withdraws all control from workers in the area of weapons production and centralizes it at the top. But if the NC (and related methods) effectively shortened the chain of command be getting humans out of the decision-making loop, it also weakened the civilian sector of the economy by its adverse effects on workers' productivity," (p.154) argues Manuel de Landa. He thus underlines that the US has become a net importer ofmachine tools for the first time since the 19th century, and points out that while in 1975 all major manufacturers ofintegrated chips were American, in 1986 only two were notJapan ese. In 1982, the Japanese MITI had launched theFifth Generation Computer Systems project (FGCS) initiative to create computers supposed to perform much calculation utilizingmassive parallelism .According to Manuel de Landa, the Prussian army was thus Jominian, that it favored centralized command of the battlefield and the conduct of military affairs over diplomacy and politics. He opposes
Clausewitz 's classic theory exposed in "On War " (1832) of the preeminence of politics over warfare (if strategy is the art of assembling battles, politics is the art of making sense of victories). Although Manuel de Landa doesn't quoteSun Tzu , his use of Clausewitz recalls the Chinese's councils on the way to avoid wars as being the most effective warfare: one may be sure he won the war when actually the war didn't happen. Manuel de Landa claims that this Jominian theory influenced Prussianmilitarism and, later, theRAND Corporation and current Pentagon policies concerningresearch and development . This centralization always aims at taking out humans from the decision-making loop, and is therefore closely linked to the evolution of technology — although a major thesis of Manuel de Landa's book is that evolution of technology in itself is not either good or bad, astechnophiles andtechnophobes hope or fear. It may be used to keep the human will out of the loop, or, on the other hand, to prioritize cooperative behavior and decentralization: the classic example used is the hackers' reappropriation of the militaryARPANET in the early ages of theInternet .Thus, the
Schlieffen Plan , formulated by theGerman general staff after the 1870-71Franco-Prussian war , is a good example of centralized war planning and of Jominian theory: everything was so rigidly planned that there was almost zero ability to adapt for sudden changes. WhenWorld War I started in August 1914, the military told the emperor that they could do nothing but invade France, although the emperor changed his mind, hoping that if he didn't invade France,Great Britain wouldn't enter the war (in virtue of the 1904 "Entente cordiale " agreement). But the plan was too rigid and didn't allow for modification, thus potentially becoming one of the indirect causes of the war (although it surely wasn't the only one: de Landa, who begins his book quotingFernand Braudel , doesn't believe inunicausality ordeterminism ).Wargaming and Game Theory
Manuel de Landa also shows how
wargaming , invented in the early 19th century byPrussia ns under the name of "Kriegspiel ", has been used since that time formodelization of future battles, in particular by thegeneral staff , which may be considered the "institution alized brain" of thearmed forces — until their substitution bythink tank s, the first one being theRAND Corporation , charged with the elaboration ofscience policy in the frame of themilitary-industrial complex .Frederick the Great was fascinated withautomaton s, as Foucault has shown, and with miniature wargames. 19th century wargaming modelization, which benefited from thecartography progress, was dependent ondice s at the beginning to represent the effects ofchaos . Eventually, these irrational conditions were taken out of the loop, as well as human will: current military wargames oppose computers, and not human beings. It was shown during the nuclear arms race that human beings refused in game modelizations to cross the threshold and press the red button, which convinced military programers to take out human players.De Landa distinguishes various "ages" of war machines (although they probably don't succeed each other in a simple way; Foucault and Deleuze likewise cast in doubt such historical linear succession); he also defines various "levels" of war machines (tactics, strategy and
logistics , which necessarily involvepolitics ).Henceforth, describing the passage from the "
clockwork paradigm" to the "motor paradigm", he quotesMichel Serres 's studies to demonstrate how this new paradigm led to the creation of an "abstract motor" composed of three components: a reservoir (steam in the case of thesteam engine ), a form of exploitable difference (heat/cold difference) and a "diagram" or "program" for the exploitation of (thermal) differences. Michel Serres thus mentioned Darwin, Marx and Freud as examples in the area of scientificdiscourse :"reservoirs of population, of capital or of unconscious desires, put to work by the use of differences of fitness, class or sex, each following a procedure directing the circulation of naturally selected species, or commodities and labor, or symptoms and fantasies..." (p.141)
Thus,
Napoleon 's armies, born from the 1789French Revolution , marked a new threshold of the machinic phylum, or singularities or bifurcation:emergent properties are displayed in this "evolution" from the "clockwork paradigm" to the "motor paradigm". This evolution is not merely technological; it is not so much the invention of the steam engine itself — the first type of motor — that determines this "evolution". Indeed, the first steam engine was invented throughtinkering , and can thus not be said to be the consequences of a "paradigm shift " asThomas Kuhn would conceive it. There is no necessary preeminence of science over technology (nor the reverse). Manuel de Landa thus explains that the "abstract motor" is more important than the "concrete motor" itself, taking as his example the dazzling victories during theNapoleonic Wars :"Napoleon himself did not incorporate the motor as a "technical" object into his war machine (as mentioned, he explicitly rejected the use of
steamboats ), but the abstract motor did affect the mode of assemblage of the Napoleonic armies: "motorized" armies were the first to make use of a reservoir of loyal human bodies, to insert these bodies into a flexiblecalculus (nonlinear tactics), and to exploit the friend/foe difference to take warfare from clockwork dynastic duels to massive confrontations betweennations ." (p.141)Thus, Napoleon's true innovation is not in the implementation of the motor invention — he rejected the use of steamboats — but his use of the pool of energy formed by
patriotism , itself fuelled by theFrench Revolution . This highmorale madeconscription possible; it also allowed more local initiative by and decentralization of the army, since French commanders didn't dread, as did their counterparts, endless cases ofdesertions if they allowed small groups of soldiers to take over specific missions.De Landa also notes how von Neumann was hired by the RAND Corporation to improve
war exercises , which he did by devisinggame theory , which helpedThe Pentagon theorizenuclear strategy . In particular, game theory was used to represent theCold War dualism conflict as an instantiation of thePrisoner's dilemma , azero-sum game . Since thezero-sum fallacy wasn't yet theorized, this led tosystemic bias in favor of conflict againstcooperative game s, according to de Landa. Thus, themassive retaliation nuclear strategy was chosen, althoughnuclear disarmament would have been, in a more realisticwin-win game , the best solution. TheTuring machines were also perfect "abstract machines" which would be implemented in concrete machines only later.See also
*
Artificial intelligence andRevolution in Military Affairs (RMA)
*Charles Babbage (1791-1871)
*ENIAC andColossus computer , the first "universal machines" or "trueTuring machines ", invented duringWorld War II
* DARPA created in 1958 following the 1957 launching ofSputnik , which developed theARPANET
*Maurice of Nassau
*Self-organization
*History of technology
*History of warfare
*Vannevar Bush (1890-1974), who directed theOffice of Scientific Research and Development responsible of theManhattan Project
*Technological singularity
*Wilhelm Stieber Source
*
Manuel de Landa , "War in the Age of Intelligent Machines", New York: Zone Books, 1991, 280 pages, Hardcover, ISBN 0-942299-76-0; Paperback, ISBN 0-942299-75-2.
Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.