Principle of indifference

Principle of indifference

The principle of indifference (also called principle of insufficient reason) is a rule for assigning epistemic probabilities.Suppose that there are "n" > 1 mutually exclusive and collectively exhaustive possibilities.The principle of indifference states that if the "n" possibilities are indistinguishable except for their names,then each possibility should be assigned a probability equal to 1/"n".

The principle of indifference is meaningless under the frequency interpretation of probability, in which probabilities are relative frequencies rather than degrees of belief in uncertain propositions, conditional upon a state of information.

Examples

The textbook examples for the application of the principle of indifference are coins, dice, and cards.

The fundamental hypothesis of statistical physics, that any two configurations of atoms with the same total energy are equally probable at equilibrium,is essentially equivalent to the principle of indifference.From that hypothesis several important conclusions are reached, a few of the direct examples being the statistical ensembles.

In a macroscopic system, at least,it must be assumed that the physical laws which govern the system are not known well enough to predict the outcome.As observed some centuries ago by John Arbuthnot (in the preface of "Of the Laws of Chance", 1692),

:It is impossible for a Die, with such determin'd force and direction, not to fall on such determin'd side, only I don't know the force and direction which makes it fall on such determin'd side, and therefore I call it Chance, which is nothing but the want of art....

Given enough time and money,there is no fundamental reason to suppose that suitably precise measurements could not be made,which would enable the prediction of the outcome of coins, dice, and cards with high accuracy: Persi Diaconis's work with coin-flipping machines is a practical example of this.

Coins

A symmetric coin has two sides, arbitrarily labeled "heads" and "tails". Assuming that the coin must land on one side or the other,the outcomes of a coin toss are mutually exclusive, exhaustive, and interchangeable.According to the principle of indifference, we assign each of the possible outcomes a probability of 1/2.

It is implicit in this analysis that the forces acting on the coin are not known with any precision.If the momentum imparted to the coin as it is launched were known with sufficient accuracy,the flight of the coin could be predicted according to the laws of Lagrangian mechanics.Thus the uncertainty in the outcome of a coin toss is derived (for the most part) from the uncertainty with respect to initial conditions.This point is discussed at greater length in the article on coin flipping.

There is also a third possible outcome: the coin could land on its edge. However, the principle of indifference doesn't say anything about this outcome, as the labels "head", "tail", and "edge" are not interchangeable.One could argue, though, that "head" and "tail" remain interchangeable, and therefore Pr("head") and Pr("tail") are equal, and both are equal to 1/2 (1 - Pr("edge")).

Dice

A symmetric die has "n" faces, arbitrarily labeled from 1 to "n".Ordinary cubical dice have "n" = 6 faces,although symmetric dice with different numbers of faces can be constructed;see dice.We assume that the die must land on one face or another,and there are no other possible outcomes.Applying the principle of indifference, we assign each of the possible outcomes a probability of 1/"n".

As with coins,it is assumed that the initial conditions of throwing the dice are not knownwith enough precision to predict the outcome according to the laws of mechanics.Dice are typically thrown so as to bounce on a table or other surface.This interaction makes prediction of the outcome much more difficult.

Casino dice are manufactured to exacting specifications to ensure that they are very nearly symmetrical.Typically, casino dice are almost exactly cubic, with sharp edges; the pips (spots) are filled instead of hollow; and the dice are made of clear plastic so that the homogeneity of the dice can be verified.Also, in a casino, the manner of throwing the dice is specified: the dice must bounce on the table and then bounce off a wall which is studded with small square pyramids.The manufacture of the dice and the manner of throwing ensure that outcomes are, for the purposes of gambling, uniform over the possible outcomes and unpredictable.

Cards

A standard deck contains 52 cards, each given a unique label in an arbitrary fashion, i.e. arbitrarily ordered. We draw a card from the deck; applying the principle of indifference, we assign each of the possible outcomes a probability of 1/52.

This example, more than the others, shows the difficulty of actually applying the principle of indifference in real situations. What we really mean by the phrase "arbitrarily ordered" is simply that we don't have any information that would lead us to favor a particular card. In actual practice, this is rarely the case: a new deck of cards is certainly not in arbitrary order, and neither is a deck immediately after a hand of cards. In practice, we therefore shuffle the cards; this does not destroy the information we have, but instead (hopefully) renders our information practically unusable, although it is still usable in principle. In fact, some expert blackjack players can track aces through the deck; for them, the condition for applying the principle of indifference is not satisfied.

Application to continuous variables

It has been claimed that the principle of indifference cannot be applied to a continuous variable, as there is no unique definition of equiprobable elementary events. This ambiguity is at the heart of Bertrand's paradox. The difficulty can also be illustrated by the following example.

*Suppose there is a cube hidden in a box. A label on the box says the cube has a side length between 3 and 5 cm.
* We don't know the actual side length, but we might assume that all values are equally likely and simply pick the mid-value of 4 cm.
* The information on the label allows us to calculate that the surface area of the cube is between 54 and 150 cm². We don't know the actual surface area, but we might assume that all values are equally likely and simply pick the mid-value of 102 cm².
* The information on the label allows us to calculate that the volume of the cube is between 27 and 125 cm3. We don't know the actual volume, but we might assume that all values are equally likely and simply pick the mid-value of 76 cm3.
* However, we have now reached the impossible conclusion that the cube has a side length of 4 cm, a surface area of 102 cm², and a volume of 76 cm3!

In this example, mutually contradictory estimates of the length, surface area, and volume of the cube arise because we have assumed three mutually contradictory distributions for these parameters: a uniform distribution for any one of the variables implies a non-uniform distribution for the other two. In general, for continuous variables, the principle of indifference does not indicate which variable (e.g. in this case, length, surface area, or volume) is to have a uniform epistemic probability distribution.

History of the principle of indifference

The original writers on probability, primarily Jacob Bernoulli and Pierre Simon Laplace, considered the principle of indifference to be intuitively obvious and did not even bother to give it a name. Laplace wrote:

:The theory of chance consists in reducing all the events of the same kind to a certain number of cases equally possible, that is to say, to such as we may be equally undecided about in regard to their existence, and in determining the number of cases favorable to the event whose probability is sought. The ratio of this number to that of all the cases possible is the measure of this probability, which is thus simply a fraction whose numerator is the number of favorable cases and whose denominator is the number of all the cases possible.

These earlier writers, Laplace in particular, naively generalized the principle of indifference to the case of continuous parameters, giving the so-called "uniform prior probability distribution", a function which is constant over all real numbers. He used this function to express a complete lack of knowledge as to the value of a parameter.

The principle of insufficient reason was its first name, given to it by later writers, possibly as a play on Leibniz's principle of sufficient reason. These later writers (George Boole, John Venn, and others) objected to the use of the uniform prior for two reasons. The first reason is that the constant function is not normalizable, and thus is not a proper probability distribution. The second reason is its inapplicability to continuous variables, as described above.

The "Principle of insufficient reason" was renamed the "Principle of Indifference" by the economist John Maynard Keynes, who was careful to note that it applies only when there is no knowledge indicating unequal probabilities.

Attempts to put the notion on firmer philosophical ground have generally begun with the concept of equipossibility and progressed from it to equiprobability.

The principle of indifference can be given a deeper logical justification by noting that equivalent states of knowledge should be assigned equivalent epistemic probabilities. This argument was propounded by E.T. Jaynes: it leads to two generalizations, namely the principle of transformation groups and the principle of maximum entropy.

References

* Edwin Thompson Jaynes. "Probability Theory: The Logic of Science". Cambridge University Press, 2003. ISBN 0-521-59271-2.

* Persi Diaconis and Joseph B. Keller. "Fair Dice". "The American Mathematical Monthly", 96(4):337-339, 1989. "(Discussion of dice that are fair "by symmetry" and "by continuity".)"


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Поможем решить контрольную работу

Look at other dictionaries:

  • principle of indifference — indifference, principle of …   Philosophy dictionary

  • Principle of maximum entropy — This article is about the probability theoretic principle. For the classifier in machine learning, see maximum entropy classifier. For other uses, see maximum entropy (disambiguation). Bayesian statistics Theory Bayesian probability Probability… …   Wikipedia

  • Principle of material objectivity — is an obsolete term and should be replaced by principle of material frame indifference. ( I was responsible for introducing the obsolete term in 1958 and now regret that I misled a lot of people , Walter Noll). Here is a precise statement of the… …   Wikipedia

  • indifference — /in dif euhr euhns, dif reuhns/, n. 1. lack of interest or concern: We were shocked by their indifference toward poverty. 2. unimportance; little or no concern: Whether or not to attend the party is a matter of indifference to him. 3. the quality …   Universalium

  • indifference, principle of — The principle named (but rejected) by Keynes, whereby if there is no known reason for asserting one rather than another out of several alternatives, then relative to our knowledge they have an equal probability. Without restriction the principle… …   Philosophy dictionary

  • principle of insufficient reason — See indifference, principle of …   Philosophy dictionary

  • insufficient reason, principle of — See indifference, principle of …   Philosophy dictionary

  • reason, principle of insufficient — See indifference, principle of …   Philosophy dictionary

  • Doomsday argument — World population from 10,000 BC to AD 2000 The Doomsday argument (DA) is a probabilistic argument that claims to predict the number of future members of the human species given only an estimate of the total number of humans born so far. Simply… …   Wikipedia

  • List of philosophy topics (I-Q) — II and thou I Ching I Ching I proposition I Thou I Thou relationshipIaIamblichus (philosopher)IbYahya Ibn Adi Yahya Ibn Adi Ibn al Arabi Muhyi al Din Ibn al Arabi Abu Bakr Ibn Bajja Abu Bakr Ibn Bājja Abu Bakr Muhammad Ibn Yahya Ibn as Say igh… …   Wikipedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”