- Reliabilism
Reliabilism, a category of theories in the philosophical discipline of
epistemology , has been advanced both as a theory ofknowledge and of justified belief (as well as other varieties of so-calledpositive epistemic status ).Process reliabilism has been used as an argument againstphilosophical skepticism , [ [http://www.geocities.com/black_tim/Hill.pdf Microsoft Word - 3_Hill.doc ] ] like thebrain in a vat idea. [http://pantheon.yale.edu/~kd47/responding.htm Responding to Skepticism ] ] Process reliabilism is a form of epistemic externalism, and is quite popular.As a theory of knowledge, reliabilism can be roughly stated as follows:
One knows that "p" ("p" stands for any
proposition --e.g., that the sky is blue) if and only if "p" is true, one believes that "p" is true, and one has arrived at the belief that "p" through some "reliable process."As a theory of justified belief, reliabilism can be formulated roughly as follows:
One has a justified belief that "p" if, and only if, the belief is the result of a reliable process.
Moreover, a similar account can be given (and an elaborate version of this has been given by Alvin Plantinga) for such notions as 'warranted belief' or 'epistemically rational belief'.
Leading proponents of reliablist theories of knowledge and justification have included
Alvin Goldman ,Marshall Swain , and more recently,Alvin Plantinga . Goldman's article "A Causal Theory of Knowing" ("Journal of Philosophy", v. 64 (1967 ), pp. 357-372) is generally credited as being the first full treatment of the theory, thoughD. M. Armstrong is also regarded as an important source, and (according toHugh Mellor ) Frank Ramsey was the very first to state the theory, albeit in passing.On the classical or traditional analysis of 'knowledge', one must be justified in believing that "p" in order for that belief to constitute knowledge; the traditional analysis has it that knowledge is no more than "
justified true belief ". Reliabilist theories of knowledge are sometimes presented as an alternative to that theory: rather than justification, all that is required is that the belief be the product of a reliable process. But reliabilism need not be regarded as an alternative, but instead as a further explication of the traditional analysis. On this view, those who offer reliabilist theories of justification further analyze the 'justification' part of the traditional analysis of 'knowledge' in terms of reliable processes. Not all reliabilists agree with such accounts of justification, but some do.Objections to the Theory
Some find reliabilism of justification objectionable because it entails externalism, which is the view that one can have knowledge, or have a justified belief, despite not knowing (having "access" to) the evidence, or other circumstances, that make the belief justified. Most reliabilists maintain that a belief can be justified, or can constitute knowledge, "even if" the believer does not know about or understand the process that makes the belief reliable. In defending this view, reliabilists (and externalists generally) are apt to point to examples from simple acts of perception: if one sees a bird in the tree outside their window and thereby gains the belief that there is a bird in that tree, they might not at all understand the cognitive processes that account for their successful act of perception; nevertheless, it is the fact that the processes worked reliably that accounts for why their belief is justified. In short, they find they hold a belief about the bird, and that belief is justified if any is, but they are not acquainted at all with the processes that led to the belief and made them justified in having it. Of course, internalists do not let the debate rest there; see
externalism (epistemology) .Another of the most common objections to reliabilism, made first to Goldman's reliable process theory of knowledge and later to other reliabilist theories, is the so-called generality problem, as follows. For any given justified belief (or instance of knowledge), one can easily identify many different (concurrently operating) "processes" from which the belief results. My belief that there is a bird in the tree outside my window might be accorded a result of the process of forming beliefs on the basis of sense-perception, of visual sense-perception, of visual sense-perception through non-opaque surfaces in daylight, and so forth, down to a variety of different very specifically-described processes. Some of these processes might be statistically reliable, while others might not. It would no doubt be better to say, in any case, that we are choosing not which process to say resulted in the belief, but instead how to describe the process, out of the many different levels of generality on which it can be accurately described.
Another objection to reliabilism is called the New Evil Demon Problem. The evil demon problem originally motivated
skepticism , but can be resuited to object to reliabilist accounts as follows: If our experiences are controlled by an evil demon, it may be the case that we believe ourselves to be doing things that we are not doing. However, these beliefs are clearly justified.Robert Brandom has called for a clarification of the role ofbelief in reliabilist theories. Brandom is concerned that unless the role of belief is stressed, reliabilism may attribute knowledge to things that would otherwise be considered incapable of possessing it. Brandom gives the example of a parrot that has been trained to consistently respond to red visual stimuli by saying 'that's red'. The proposition is true, the mechanism that produced it is reliable, but Brandom is reluctant to say that the parrot "knows" it is seeing red because he thinks it cannot "believe" that it is. For Brandom, beliefs pertain to concepts: without the latter there can be no former. Concepts are products of the 'game of giving and asking for reasons'. Hence, only those entities capable of reasoning, through language in a social context, can for Brandom believe and thus have knowledge. Brandom may be regarded as hybridising externalist and internalist, allowing knowledge to be accounted for by reliable external process so long as a knower possess some internal understanding of why the belief is reliable.References
Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.