Evidentialism

Evidentialism

Evidentialism is a theory of justification according to which whether a belief is justified depends solely on what a person's evidence is. Technically, though belief is typically the primary object of concern, evidentialism can be applied to doxastic attitudes generally. Formulating evidentialism in terms of the doxastic attitude of belief its most-defended form comes from Conee and Feldman: Belief B toward proposition p is epistemically justified for S at t if and only if B fits the evidence S has at t.

Criticisms of evidentialism

Critics of evidentialism sometimes reject the claim that a belief is justified only if one's evidence supports that belief. A typical counterexample goes like this. Suppose, for example, that Babe Ruth approaches the batter's box believing that he will hit a home run despite his current drunkenness and overall decline in performance in recent games. He realizes that, however unlikely it is that his luck will change, it would increase his chances of hitting a home run if he maintains a confident attitude. In these circumstances, critics of evidentialism argue that his belief that "p = Babe Ruth will hit a home run" is justified, even though his evidence does not support this belief.

Evidentialists may respond to this criticism by forming a distinction between "pragmatic" or "prudential justification" and "epistemic justification". In Babe Ruth's case, it is pragmatically justified that he believe "p", but it is nevertheless epistemically unjustified: Though the belief may be justified for the purpose of promoting some other goal (a successful at bat, in Ruth's case), it is not justified relative to the purely epistemic goal of having beliefs that are most likely to be true.

A similar response follows the criticism that evidentialism implies all faith based beliefs are unjustified. For example, fideism claims that evidence is irrelevant to religious beliefs and that attempts to justify religious beliefs in such a way are misguided. Superficially, fideism and evidentialism have mutually exclusive takes on religious beliefs, but evidentialists use the term "justification" in a much weaker sense than the one in which fideists most likely use it. Evidentialism merely defines the epistemic condition of a belief, an issue towards which fideists would most likely be apathetic.

Likewise, some say that the human mind is not naturally inclined to form beliefs based on evidence, viz. cognitive dissonance. While this may be the case, evidentialists admit, evidentialism is only meant to separate justified beliefs from unjustified beliefs. One can believe that evidentialism is true yet still maintain that the human mind is not naturally inclined to form beliefs based on evidence. He would simply have to conclude that the mind is not naturally inclined to form justified beliefs.

The infinite regress argument

Evidentialism also faces a challenge from "the infinite regress argument". This argument begins with the observation that, normally, one's supporting evidence for a belief consists of other beliefs. But it seems that these other beliefs can do the job of justifying only if they themselves are already justified. And evidentialism demands that these supporting beliefs be justified by still further evidence if they are to be justified themselves. But this same reasoning would apply to the new, deeper level of supporting beliefs: they can only justify if they're themselves justified, and evidentialism therefore demands an even deeper level of supporting belief. And so on. According to this argument, a justified belief requires an endless supply of reasons. Most philosophers agree that this is an absurd conclusion.

In general, responses to this argument can be classified in the following ways:

"Foundationalism": There exist beliefs that are justified, but not because they are based on any other beliefs. These are called properly basic beliefs, and they are the foundation upon which all other justified beliefs ultimately rest.

"Coherentism": Justified beliefs are all evidentially supported by other beliefs, but an infinite set of beliefs is not generated, because the chains of evidential support among beliefs is allowed to move in a circle. On the resulting picture, a person's belief is justified when it fits together with the person's other beliefs in a coherent way in which the person's various beliefs mutually support one another.

"Conditional Theory of Justification": A belief is justified by a set of beliefs. However this justification operates conditionally, as it depends on the truth of the justifying beliefs. There is not a need for basic beliefs, but one should note that this type of justification is weaker.

"Skepticism": There cannot be any justified beliefs.

Aside from these responses, some philosophers have said that evidential chains terminate in beliefs that are not justified. Others have said that, indeed, there can exist infinite chains of reasons.

Of the main responses, coherentism and skepticism are clearly consistent with evidentialism. Coherentism allows evidential support for all of our justified beliefs in the face of the regress argument by allowing for circular chains of evidential support among beliefs. And the skeptic here is utilizing an evidentialist demand to arrive at her skeptical conclusion.

But because the resulting skepticism is so sweeping and devastating, and because so many reject the legitimacy of the circular reasoning embraced by the coherentist, foundationalism is the favored response of many philosophers to the regress argument. And foundationalism does not so clearly fit together with evidentialism. At first glance, at least, the "basic" beliefs of the foundationalist would appear to be counterexamples to the evidentialist's thesis, in that they are justified beliefs that are not rational because they are supported by deeper evidence.

Non-evidentialist theories of knowledge and justification

Many contemporary epistemologists reject the view that evidential support is the whole story about the justification of beliefs. While no sensible epistemologists generally urge people to disregard their evidence when forming beliefs, many believe that a more complete theory would introduce considerations about the processes that intitiate and sustain beliefs. An example of one such theory is "reliabilism". The most influential proponent of reliabilism is Alvin Goldman. According to a crude form of reliabilism, "S" is justified in believing "p" if and only if "S" 's belief in "p" is caused by a reliable process -- a process that generally leads to true beliefs. Some of these reliable processes may require the processing of evidence; many others won't. So evidentialism, on which the justification of a belief always turns completely on the issue of the belief's evidential support, is false. Likewise, evidentialism will be rejected by more sophisticated versions of reliabilism, some of which will allow evidence an important but limited role, as opposed to the all-encompassing role assigned to it by evidentialism.

Other non-evidentialist theories include: the "Causal Theory", according to which "S" knows "p" if and only if "S" 's belief in "p" is causally connected in an appropriate way with "S" 's believing "p"; and Robert Nozick's "Truth Tracking Theory", according to which "S" knows "p" if and only if (i) "p" is true, (ii) "S" believes "p", (iii) "S" 's attitude toward "p" tracks the truth value of "p" in that, when "p" is not true, "S" does not believe "p" and when "p" is true, "S" does believe "p".

Another alternative perspective, promoted by David Hume's 18th Century opponent, Presbyterian philosopher Thomas Reid, and perhaps hinted at by Hume himself, at least in some moods (though this is a very controversial issue in interpreting Hume), has it that some of our "natural" beliefs -- beliefs we are led to form by natural features of the human constitution -- have what can be called an "innocent-until-proven-guilty" status. Contrary to evidentialism, they can be justified in the absence of any effective evidence that supports them. They are justified just so long as one doesn't have good reason to think them false.

A very important and provocative new account of the extent of our evidence is Timothy Williamson's claim that E=K: One's evidence is what one knows. (See Williamson's book, "Knowledge and Its Limits" (Oxford UP, 2000).) Going by the "letter of the law," Williamson's resulting theory is not contrary to, but is rather an instance of, evidentialism. By allowing our evidence to encompass everything we know, Williamson is able to give thoroughly evidentialist accounts of many important epistemological concepts. But, traditionally, evidentialists have presupposed much more restrictive accounts of what our evidence is. Thus, Williamson's theory is opposed to the spirit of much traditional evidentialism. However, Williamson's work may point to a quite general way to modify traditional evidentialism to make it better able to meet the challenges it faces: Whether or not one goes so far as to accept that E=K, broadening one's view of what comprises our evidence may provide a way to address many of the objections to evidentialism, especially to those disinclined to swallow skeptical consequences of a view.

References

*Conee and Feldman 2004. "Evidentialism" (Oxford University Press).

External links

* [http://www.iep.utm.edu/e/evidenti.htm Article from Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy by Dan Mittag of the University of Rochester]
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/epistemology/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy article on epistemology by Mathias Steup.]


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Нужна курсовая?

Look at other dictionaries:

  • evidentialism —    Evidentialism is the epistemological theory that the epistemic justification of a belief depends on the evi dence one has for it. John Locke developed an influential version of the theory with his claim that belief should always be proportioned …   Christian Philosophy

  • Will to believe doctrine — The Will to Believe is the title of William James s classic lecture (published in 1897) defending the adoption of beliefs as hypotheses and self fulfilling prophecies even without prior evidence of their truth. James idea that people have a right …   Wikipedia

  • Evidential apologetics — or evidentialism (not to be confused with epistemological evidentialism) is an approach to Christian apologetics emphasizing the use of evidence to demonstrate that God probably exists. The evidence is supposed to be evidence both the believer… …   Wikipedia

  • Evident — Dieser Artikel wurde in der Qualitätssicherung Philosophie eingetragen. Dabei werden Artikel gelöscht, die nach Fristablauf sich als nicht relevant herausstellen oder kein akzeptables Niveau erreicht haben. Bitte hilf mit, die inhaltlichen Mängel …   Deutsch Wikipedia

  • Evidenz — (vom lateinischen ex „aus“ und videre „sehen“ das Herausscheinende) bezeichnet das dem Augenschein nach Unbezweifelbare, das durch unmittelbare Anschauung oder Einsicht Erkennbare. Evident ist ein Sachverhalt, der unmittelbar ohne besondere… …   Deutsch Wikipedia

  • Evidenz (Philosophie) — Dieser Artikel wurde in der Qualitätssicherung Philosophie eingetragen. Dabei werden Artikel gelöscht, die nach Fristablauf sich als nicht relevant herausstellen oder kein akzeptables Niveau erreicht haben. Bitte hilf mit, die inhaltlichen Mängel …   Deutsch Wikipedia

  • Francis Schaeffer — Infobox Person name= Francis Schaeffer caption= Founder of L Abri community birth date= 1912 01 30 birth place= dead=dead death date= 1984 05 15 death place= occupation= Christian Philosopher Church Leader spouse= Edith Seville Francis August… …   Wikipedia

  • Freethought — is a philosophical viewpoint that holds that beliefs should be formed on the basis of science and logic and should not be influenced by emotion, authority, tradition, or any dogma. The cognitive application of freethought is known as freethinking …   Wikipedia

  • Christian apologetics — Part of a series on Christianity   …   Wikipedia

  • List of Christian apologetic works — This list contains works related to Christian apologetics. See also List of apologetic works.References* Bush, L. Russ. 1983. Classical Readings in Christian Apologetics AD. 100 1800 .Zondervan, Grand Rapids, Michigan. * Geisler, Norman L. 1999.… …   Wikipedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”