- Quantum indeterminacy
Quantum indeterminacy is the apparent "necessary" incompleteness in the description of a
physical system , that has become one of the characteristics of the standard description ofquantum physics . Prior to quantum physics, it was thought that (a) a physical system had a determinate state which uniquely determined all the values of its measurable properties, and conversely (b) the values of its measurable properties uniquely determined the state.Albert Einstein may have been the first person to carefully point out the radical effect the new quantum physics would have on our notion of physical state. [ Christopher Fuchs , "Quantum mechanics as quantum information (and only a little more)", in A. Khrenikov (ed.) "Quantum Theory: Reconstruction of Foundations" (Växjö: Växjö University Press, 2002). Fuchs says:.. He was the first person to say in absolutely unambiguous terms why the quantum state should be viewed as information ..]Quantum indeterminacy can be quantitatively characterized by a
probability distribution on the set of outcomes of measurements of anobservable . The distribution is uniquely determined by the system state, and moreover quantum mechanics provides a recipe for calculating this probability distribution.Indeterminacy in measurement was not an innovation of quantum mechanics, since it had been established early on by experimentalists that errors in measurement may lead to indeterminate outcomes. However, by the later half of the
eighteenth century , measurement errors were well understood and it was known that they could either be reduced by better equipment or accounted for by statistical error models. In quantum mechanics, however, indeterminacy is of a much more fundamental nature, having nothing to do with errors or disturbance.Measurement
An adequate account of quantum indeterminacy requires a theory of measurement. Many theories have been proposed since the beginning of
quantum mechanics andquantum measurement continues to be an active research area in both theoretical and experimental physics [V. Braginski and F. Khalili, "Quantum Measurements", Cambridge University Press, 1992.] . Possibly the first systematic attempt at a mathematical theory was developed byJohn von Neumann . The kind of measurements he investigated are now called projective measurements. That theory was based in turn on the theory ofprojection-valued measure s forself-adjoint operator s which had been recently developed (by von Neumann and independently byMarshall Stone ) and the Hilbert space formulation of quantum mechanics (attributed by von Neumann toPaul Dirac ).In this formulation, the state of a physical system corresponds to a vector of length 1 in a
Hilbert space "H" over thecomplex number s. An observable is represented by a self-adjoint (i.e. Hermitian) operator "A" on "H". If "H" is finite dimensional, by thespectral theorem , "A" has anorthonormal basis ofeigenvector s. If the system is in state ψ, then immediately after measurement the system will occupy a state which is an eigenvector "e" of "A" and the observed value λ will be the corresponding eigenvalue of the equation "A" "e" = λ "e". It is immediate from this that measurement in general will be non-deterministic. Quantum mechanics, moreover, gives a recipe for computing a probability distribution Pr on the possible outcomes given the initial system state is ψ. The probability is:
where E(λ) is the projection onto the space of eigenvectors of "A" with eigenvalue λ.
Example
In this example, we consider a single spin 1/2 particle (such as an electron) in which we only consider the spin degree of freedom. The corresponding Hilbert space is the two-dimensional complex Hilbert space C2, with each quantum state corresponding to a unit vector in C2 (unique up to phase). In this case, the state space can be geometrically represented as the surface of a sphere, as shown in the figure on the right.
Bloch sphere showing eigenvectors for Pauli Spin matrices. The Bloch sphere is a two-dimensional surface the points of which correspond to the state space of a spin 1/2 particle. At the state ψ the values of σ1 are +1 whereas the values of σ2 and σ3 take the values +1, -1 with probability 1/2.The Pauli spin matrices:are
self-adjoint and correspond to spin-measurements along the 3 coordinate axes.The Pauli matrices all have the eigenvalues +1, −1.
* For σ1, these eigenvalues correspond to the eigenvectors::
* For σ3, they correspond to the eigenvectors::Thus in the state :σ1 has the determinate value +1, while measurement of σ3 can produce either +1, −1 each with probability 1/2. In fact, there is no state in which measurement of both σ1 and σ3 have determinate values.
There are various questions that can be asked about the above indeterminacy assertion.
# Can the indeterminacy be understood as similar to an error in measurement explainable by an error parameter? More precisely, is there a hidden parameter that could account for the statistical indeterminacy in a completely classical way?
# Can the indeterminacy be understood as a disturbance of the system being measured?Von Neumann formulated the question 1) and provided an argument why the answer had to be no, "if" one accepted the formalism he was proposing, although according to Bell, von Neumann's formal proof did not justify his informal conclusion [ J.S. Bell, "Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics", Cambridge University Press, 2004, pg. 5.] . The definitive negative answer to 1) has been established by experiment thatBell's inequalities are violated, on the assumption that hidden variables must be "local" (seeBell test experiments ). The answer to 2) depends on how disturbance is understood (particularly since measurement is disturbance), but in the most natural interpretation the answer is also no. To see this, consider two sequences of measurements: (A) which measures exclusively σ1 and (B) which measures only σ3 of a spin system in the state ψ. The measurement outcomes of (A) are all +1, while the statistical distribution of the measurements (B) is still divided between +1, −1 with probability 1/2.Other examples of indeterminacy
Quantum indeterminacy can also be illustrated in terms of a particle with a definitely measured momentum for which there must be a fundamental limit to how precisely its location can be specified. This quantum uncertainty principle can be expressed in terms of other variables, for example, a particle with a definitely measured energy has a fundamental limit to how precisely one can specify how long it will have that energy.The units involved in quantum uncertainty are on the order of
Planck's constant (found experimentally to be 6.6 x 10-34 J·s).Indeterminacy and incompleteness
Quantum indeterminacy is the assertion that the state of a system does not determine a unique collection of values for all its measurable properties. Indeed, according to the
Kochen-Specker theorem , in the quantum mechanical formalism it is impossible that, for a given quantum state, each one of these measurable properties (observables) has a determinate (sharp) value. The values of an observable will be obtained non-deterministically in accordance with a probability distribution which is uniquely determined by the system state. Note that the state is destroyed by measurement, so when we refer to a collection of values, each measured value in this collection must be obtained using a freshly prepared state.This indeterminacy might be regarded as a kind of essential incompleteness in our description of a physical system. Notice however, that the indeterminacy as stated above only applies to values of measurements not to the quantum state. For example, in the spin 1/2 example discussed above, the system can be prepared in the state ψ by using measurement of σ1 as a "filter" which retains only those particles such that σ1 yields +1. By the von Neumann (so-called) postulates, immediately after the measurement the system is assuredly in the state ψ.
However, Einstein did believe that quantum state cannot be a complete description of a physical system and, it is commonly thought, never came to terms with quantum mechanics. In fact, Einstein,
Boris Podolsky andNathan Rosen did show that if quantum mechanics is correct, then the classical view of how the real world works (at least after special relativity) is no longer tenable. This view included the following two ideas:
# A measurable property of a physical system whose value can be predicted with certainty is actually an element of reality (this was the terminology used by EPR).
# Effects of local actions have a finite propagation speed. This failure of the classical view was one of the conclusions of the EPR thought experiment in which two remotely located observers, now commonly referred to asAlice and Bob , perform independent measurements of spin on a pair of electrons, prepared at a source in a special state called aspin singlet state. It was a conclusion of EPR, using the formal apparatus of quantum theory, that once Alice measured spin in the "x" direction, Bob's measurement in the "x" direction was determined with certainty, whereas immediately before Alice's measurement Bob's outcome was only statistically determined. From this it follows that either value of spin in the "x" direction is not an element of reality or that the effect of Alice's measurement has infinite speed of propagation.Indeterminacy for mixed states
We have described indeterminacy for a quantum system which is in a
pure state .Mixed state s are a more general kind of state obtained by a statistical mixture of pure states. For mixed statesthe "quantum recipe" for determining the probability distribution of a measurement is determined as follows:Let "A" be an observable of a quantum mechanical system. "A" is given by a denselydefined self-adjoint operator on "H". The
spectral measure of "A" is a projection-valued measure defined by the condition:for every Borel subset "U" of R. Given a mixed state "S", we introduce the "distribution" of "A" under "S" as follows:: This is a probability measure defined on the Borel subsets of Rwhich is the probability distribution obtained by measuring "A" in"S".See also
*
Quantum mechanics
*Quantum entanglement
*Complementarity (physics)
*Interpretation of quantum mechanics
*Quantum measurement
*Counterfactual definiteness
*EPR paradox Notes and references
Other references
* A. Aspect, "Bell's inequality test: more ideal than ever", Nature 398 189 (1999). [http://www-ece.rice.edu/~kono/ELEC565/Aspect_Nature.pdf]
*G. Bergmann, "The Logic of Quanta", American Journal of Physics, 1947. Reprinted in Readings in the Philosophy of Science, Ed. H. Feigl and M. Brodbeck, Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1953. Discusses measurement, accuracy and determinism.
* J.S. Bell, "On the Einstein-Poldolsky-Rosen paradox", Physics 1 195 (1964).
* A. Einstein, B. Podolsky, and N. Rosen, [http://www.drchinese.com/David/EPR.pdf "Can quantum-mechanical description of physical reality be considered complete?"] Phys. Rev. 47 777 (1935). [http://prola.aps.org/abstract/PR/v47/i10/p777_1]
* G. Mackey, "Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics", W. A. Benjamin, 1963 (paperback reprint by Dover 2004).
* J. von Neumann, "Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics", Princeton University Press, 1955. Reprinted in paperback form. Originally published in German in 1932.
* R. Omnès, "Understanding Quantum Mechanics", Princeton University Press, 1999.External links
* [http://www.oberlin.edu/physics/dstyer/TeachQM/misconnzz.pdf Common Misconceptions Regarding Quantum Mechanics] See especially part III "Misconceptions regarding measurement".
Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.