Dynamics of the celestial spheres

Dynamics of the celestial spheres
 Ornate manuscript illumination showing celestial spheres, with angels turning cranks at the axis of the starry sphere
Fourteenth-century drawing of angels turning the celestial spheres

Ancient, medieval and Renaissance astronomers and philosophers developed many different theories about the dynamics of the celestial spheres. They explained the motions of the various nested spheres in terms of the materials of which they were made, external movers such as celestial intelligences, and internal movers such as motive souls or impressed forces. Most of these models were qualitative, although a few of them incorporated quantitative analyses that related speed, motive force and resistance.

Contents

The celestial material and its natural motions

In considering the physics of the celestial spheres, scholars followed two different views about the material composition of the celestial spheres. For Plato, the celestial regions were made “mostly out of fire”[1][2] on account of its mobility.[3] Later Platonists, such as Plotinus, maintained that although fire moves naturally upward in a straight line toward its natural place at the periphery of the universe, when it arrived there, it would either rest or move naturally in a circle.[4] An account which was compatible with Aristotle's meteorology[5] of a fiery region in the upper air, drug along underneath the circular motion of the lunar sphere.[6] However, the spheres themselves were made entirely of a special fifth element,[7] that took its name, Aether (Αἰθήρ), from the personification in mythology: the bright, untainted upper atmosphere in which the gods dwell, as distinct from the dense lower atmosphere, Aer (Ἀήρ).[8] Unlike the four terrestrial elements, earth, water, air and fire, that give rise to the generation and corruption of natural substances by their mutual transformations; aether was unchanging, moving always with a uniform circular motion that was uniquely suited to the celestial spheres, which were eternal.[9][10] Earth and water had a natural heaviness (gravitas), which they expressed by moving downward toward the center of the universe. Fire and air had a buoyant lightness (levitas), such that they moved upward, away from the center. Aether, being neither heavy nor light, moved naturally around the center.[11]

The causes of celestial motion

As early as Plato, philosophers considered the heavens to be moved by immaterial agents. Plato believed the cause to be a world-soul, created according to mathematical principles, which governed the daily motion of the heavens (the motion of the Same) and the opposed motions of the planets along the zodiac (the motion of the Different).[12] As a teleological cause, Aristotle proposed eternal unmoved movers, gods whom the spheres desired to mimic, as best they could, by uniform circular motion.[13][14] Aristotle determined that an individual unmoved mover would be required to insure each individual motion in the heavens. While stipulating that the number of spheres, and thus gods, is subject to revision by astronomers, he estimated the total was 47 or 55, depending on which of the two contemporary models one took into consideration.[15] In On the Heavens, Aristotle was content with the view of eternal circular motion as moving itself, in the manner of Plato's world-soul,[16] which lent support to three principles of celestial motion: an internal soul, an external unmoved mover, and the celestial material (aether).[17][18]

Later Greek interpreters

In his Planetary Hypotheses, Ptolemy (c.90–168) rejected the Aristotelian concept of an external prime mover, maintaining instead that the planets have souls and move themselves with a voluntary motion. Each planet sends out motive emissions that direct its own motion and the motions of the epicycle and deferent that make up its system, just as a bird sends out emissions to its nerves that direct the motions of its feet and wings.[19][20][21]

John Philoponus (490–570) considered that the heavens were made of fire, not of aether, yet maintained that circular motion is one of the two natural motions of fire.[22] In a theological work, On the Creation of the World (De opificio mundi), he denied that the heavens are moved by either a soul or by angels, proposing that "it is not impossible that God, who created all these things, imparted a motive force to the moon, the sun, and other stars — just as the inclination to heavy and light bodies, and the movements due to the internal soul to all living beings — in order that the angels do not move them by force."[23][24][25] This is interpreted as an application of the concept of impetus to the motion of the celestial spheres.[26][27][28] In his earlier commentary on Aristotle's Physics, Philoponus compared the innate power or nature that accounts for the rotation of the heavens to the innate power or nature that accounts for the fall of rocks.[29]

Islamic interpreters

The Persian philosophers, al-Farabi (c.872–c.950) and Avicenna (c.980–1037), following Plotinus, maintained that Aristotle's movers, called intelligences, came into being through a series of emanations beginning with God. A first intelligence emanated from God, and from the first intelligence emanated a sphere, its soul, and a second intelligence. The process continued down through the celestial spheres until the sphere of the moon, its soul, and a final intelligence. They considered that each sphere was moved continually by its soul, seeking to emulate the perfection of its intelligence.[30][31] Avicenna maintained that besides an intelligence and its soul, each sphere was also moved by a natural inclination (mayl).[32]

A Spanish Muslim interpreter of Aristotle, al-Bitruji (d. c.1024), proposed a radical transformation of astronomy that did away with epicycles and eccentrics, in which the celestial spheres were driven by a single unmoved mover at the periphery of the universe. The spheres thus moved with a "natural nonviolent motion."[33] but was a The mover's power diminished with increasing distance from the periphery so that the lower spheres lagged behind in their daily motion around the Earth; this power reached even as far as the sphere of water, producing the tides.[34][35]

More influential for later Christian thinkers were the teachings of Averroes (1126–1198), who agreed with Avicenna that the intelligences and souls combine to move the spheres but rejected his concept of emanation.[31][36] Considering how the soul acts, he maintained that the soul moves its sphere without effort, for the celestial material has no tendency to a contrary motion.[37]

Later in the century, a commentator on the Islamic theologian Adud al-Din al-Iji (1281–1355), under the influence of the Ash'ari doctrine of occasionalism, which maintained that all physical effects were caused directly by God's will rather than by natural causes, rejected non-religious science and astronomy,[38] and maintained that the celestial spheres were "imaginary things" and "more tenuous than a spider's web".[39]

Medieval Western Europe

In the Early Middle Ages, Plato's picture of the heavens was dominant among European philosophers, which led Christian thinkers to question the role and nature of the world-soul.[40] With the recovery of Aristotle's works in the twelfth and thirteenth centuries, Aristotle's views supplanted the earlier Platonism, and a new set of questions regarding the relationships of the unmoved movers to the spheres and to God emerged.[41]

In the early phases of the Western recovery of Aristotle, Robert Grosseteste (c.1175–1253), influenced by medieval Platonism and by the astronomy of al-Bitruji, rejected the idea that the heavens are moved by either souls or intelligences.[42] Adam Marsh's (c.1200–1259) treatise On the Ebb and Flow of the Sea, which was formerly attributed to Grosseteste, maintained al-Bitruji's opinion that the celestial spheres and the seas are moved by a peripheral mover whose motion weakens with distance.[43]

Thomas Aquinas (c.1225–1274), following Avicenna, interpreted Aristotle to mean that there were two immaterial substances responsible for the motion of each celestial sphere, a soul that was an integral part of its sphere, and an intelligence that was separate from its sphere. The soul shares the motion of its sphere and, through its love and desire for the unmoved separate intelligence, causes the sphere to move.[44][45] Avicenna, al-Ghazali, Moses Maimonides, and most Christian scholastic philosophers identified Aristotle's intelligences with the angels of revelation, thereby associating an angel with each of the spheres.[46] Moreover, Aquinas rejected the idea that celestial bodies are moved by an internal nature, similar to the heaviness and lightness that moves terrestrial bodies.[47] Attributing souls to the spheres was theologically controversial, as that could make them animals. After the Condemnations of 1277, most philosophers came to reject the idea that the celestial spheres had souls.[48]

In two slightly different discussions, John Buridan (c.1295–1358) suggested that when God created the celestial spheres, he began to move them, impressing in them a circular impetus that would be neither corrupted nor diminished, since there was neither an inclination to other movements nor any resistance in the celestial region. He noted that this would allow God to rest on the seventh day, but he left the matter to be resolved by the theologians.[49][50][51]

Nicole Oresme (c.1323-1382) explained the motion of the spheres in traditional terms of the action of intelligences, coupled with a consideration in terms of a power and resistance impressed in the spheres when God created the heavens.[52][53] In discussing the relation of the moving power of the intelligence, the resistance of the sphere, and the circular velocity, he said "this ratio ought not to be called a ratio of force to resistance except by analogy, because an intelligence moves by will alone ... and the heavens do not resist it."[54]

According to Grant, except for Oresme, scholastic thinkers did not consider the force-resistance model to be properly applicable to the motion of celestial bodies, although some, such as Bartholomew Amicus, thought analogically in terms of force and resistance.[55] By the end of the Middle Ages it was the common opinion among philosophers that the celestial bodies were moved by external intelligences, or angels, and not by some kind of an internal mover.[56]

The movers and Copernicanism

Although Nicolaus Copernicus (1473–1543) transformed Ptolemaic astronomy and Aristotelian cosmology by moving the Earth from the center of the universe, he retained both the traditional model of the celestial spheres and the medieval Aristotelian views of the causes of its motion. Copernicus follows Aristotle to maintain that circular motion is natural to the form of a sphere. However, he also appears to have accepted the traditional philosophical belief that the spheres are moved by an external mover.[57]

Although Johannes Kepler's (1571–1630) cosmology eliminated the celestial spheres, he held that the planets were moved both by an external motive power, which he located in the Sun, and a motive soul associated with each planet. In an early manuscript discussing the motion of Mars, Kepler considered the Sun to cause the circular motion of the planet. He then attributed the inward and outward motion of the planet, which transforms its overall motion from circular to oval, to a moving soul in the planet since the motion is "not a natural motion, but more of an animate one".[58] In various writings, Kepler often attributed a kind of intelligence to the inborn motive faculties associated with the stars.[59]

In the aftermath of Copernicanism the planets came to be seen as bodies moving freely through a very subtle aethereal medium. Although many scholastics continued to maintain that intelligences were the celestial movers, they now associated the intelligences with the planets themselves, rather than with the celestial spheres.[60]

Notes

  1. ^ Plato, Timaeus 40a2–4
  2. ^ Cornford 1957, p. 118.
  3. ^ Plato, Timaeus, 55d-56a.
  4. ^ Merlan, Philip (1943). "Plotinus Enneads 2.2". Transactions and Proceedings of the American Philological Association 74: 179–191. doi:10.2307/283597. JSTOR 283597, pp. 186-7. 
  5. ^ Aristotle; Webster, E.W. (2006). Meteorology. Digireads.com. p. 7. ISBN 9781420927481. http://books.google.com/books?id=etvHt-bBafMC&lpg=PA7&pg=PA7. 
  6. ^ Sorabji, R. (2005). The Philosophy of the Commentators, 200-600 AD: Physics. G - Reference, Information and Interdisciplinary Subjects Series. Cornell University Press. p. 352. ISBN 9780801489884. LCCN 2004063547. http://books.google.com/books?id=0QpQw8JDgQcC&lpg=PA352&pg=PA352. 
  7. ^ Grant 1994, p. 189.
  8. ^ Hesiod. Theogony. lines 104, 929j. http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/text?doc=Perseus%3Atext%3A1999.01.0130%3Acard%3D104#note2. 
  9. ^ Lloyd 1968, pp. 134-9.
  10. ^ "by simple bodies I mean those which possess a principle of movement in their own nature, such as fire and earth and their kinds.... there must necessarily be some simple body which revolves naturally and by virtue of its own nature with a circular movement." Aristotle, On the heavens, 268b28-269a8.
  11. ^ Grant 1994, pp. 196-7.
  12. ^ Cornford 1957, pp. 57-93.
  13. ^ Lloyd 1968, pp. 139-147.
  14. ^ Grant 1994, p. 515.
  15. ^ Lloyd 1968, pp. 147-53.
  16. ^ Cleary, J.J. (1995). Aristotle and Mathematics: Aporetic Method in Cosmology and Metaphysics. Philosophia Antiqua. E.J. Brill. p. 390–393. ISBN 9789004101593. LCCN lc95001398. http://books.google.com/books?id=kD7Rmkw_8AwC&lpg=PA390&pg=PA390. 
  17. ^ Merlan, Philip (1943). "Plotinus Enneads 2.2". Transactions and Proceedings of the American Philological Association 74: 179–191. doi:10.2307/283597. JSTOR 283597, p. 180. 
  18. ^ Sorabji 1988, pp. 224-6.
  19. ^ Murschel, Andrea (1995). "The Structure and Function of Ptolemy's Physical Hypotheses of Planetary Motion". Journal for the History of Astronomy 26: 33–61. Bibcode 1995JHA....26...33M, pp. 38-40. 
  20. ^ Neugebauer, Otto (1975). A History of Ancient Mathematical Astronomy. 2. Berlin: Springer. p. 923. ISBN 3-540-06995-X. 
  21. ^ Taub, Liba Chaia (1993). Ptolemy's Universe: The Natural Philosophical and Ethical Foundations of Ptolemy's Astronomy. Chicago: Open Court. pp. 117–121. ISBN 0-8126-9228-4. 
  22. ^ Wildberg 1988, p. 239.
  23. ^ Wildberg 1988, p. 243.
  24. ^ Wolfson 1962, p. 70.
  25. ^ Sorabji 1988, p. 232.
  26. ^ Sorabji 1988, pp. 231-7.
  27. ^ Wildberg 1988, pp. 243-6.
  28. ^ Sorabji 1988, pp. 232.
  29. ^ Sorabji 1988, p. 234.
  30. ^ Davidson, Herbert A. (1992). Alfarabi, Avicenna, and Averroes, on Intellect: Their Cosmologies, Theories of the Active Intellect, and Theories of Human Intellect. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 44–48, 74–77. ISBN 0-19-507423-8. 
  31. ^ a b Wolfson 1958, pp. 243-4.
  32. ^ Wolfson 1962, pp. 82-3.
  33. ^ al-Biţrūjī. (1971) On the Principles of Astronomy, 1.60-62, trans. Bernard R. Goldstein, vol. 1, pp. 78-9. New Haven: Yale Univ. Pr. ISBN 0-300-01387-6
  34. ^ Dales 1980, pp. 538-9.
  35. ^ Weisheipl 1961, p. 297.
  36. ^ Wolfson 1962, p. 85.
  37. ^ Grant 1994, pp. 539-40.
  38. ^ Huff, Toby (2003). The Rise of Early Modern Science: Islam, China, and the West. Cambridge University Press. p. 175. ISBN 0521529948. 
  39. ^ pp. 55–57 of Ragep, F. Jamil; Al-Qushji, Ali (2001). "Freeing Astronomy from Philosophy: An Aspect of Islamic Influence on Science". Osiris. 2nd Series 16 (Science in Theistic Contexts: Cognitive Dimensions): 49–71. doi:10.1086/649338. ISSN 0369-7827. JSTOR 301979. 
  40. ^ Marenbon, John (2002). "Platonism – A Doxographic Approach: The Early Middle Ages". In Gersh, Stephen; Hoenen, M. J. F. M.. The Platonic tradition in the Middle Ages: a doxographic approach. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter. pp. 80–82. ISBN 3-11-016844-8. 
  41. ^ Grant 1994, pp. 707-717.
  42. ^ Dales 1980, pp. 540-3.
  43. ^ Dales 1980, p. 540.
  44. ^ Wolfson 1962, 87-90
  45. ^ Grant 1994, pp. 516-17.
  46. ^ Grant 1994, p. 525.
  47. ^ Weisheipl 1961, p. 322.
  48. ^ Grant 1994, pp. 546-7.
  49. ^ Dales 1980, pp. 547-8.
  50. ^ John Buridan (1959). "Questions on the Eight Books of the Physics of Aristotle". In Marshall Clagett. The Science of Mechanics in the Middle Ages. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press. p. 536. 
  51. ^ John Buridan (1959). "Questions on the Four Books on the Heavens and the World of Aristotle". In Marshall Clagett. The Science of Mechanics in the Middle Ages. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press. p. 561. 
  52. ^ Dales 1980, pp. 548-9.
  53. ^ Nicole Oresme (1968). A. D. Menut and A. J. Denomy. ed. Le Livre du ciel et du monde. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press. pp. 286–9. 
  54. ^ Nicole Oresme (1966). Edward Grant. ed. De proportionibus proportionum and Ad pauca respicientes. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press. p. 293. 
  55. ^ Grant 1994, pp. 502-3, 541-2.
  56. ^ Grant 1994, pp. 527.
  57. ^ Jardine, Nicholas (1982). "The Significance of the Copernican Orbs". Journal for the History of Astronomy 13: 168–194. Bibcode 1982JHA....13..168J, pp. 178-183. 
  58. ^ Donahue, W. H. (1993). "Kepler's First Thoughts on Oval Orbits: Text, Translation, and Commentary". Journal for the History of Astronomy 24: 71–100. Bibcode 1993JHA....24...71D, pp. 75-76, 85-88. 
  59. ^ Wolfson 1962, pp. 90-93.
  60. ^ Grant 1994, pp. 544-5.

References

Primary sources

Secondary sources

  • Cornford, Francis MacDonald (1957?) [1937]. Plato's Cosmology: The Timaeus of Plato translated, with a running commentary. Indianapolis: Bobbs Merrill Co. 
  • Dales, Richard C. (1980). "The De-Animation of the Heavens in the Middle Ages". Journal of the History of Ideas 41 (4): 531–550. doi:10.2307/2709273. JSTOR 2709273. 
  • Grant, Edward (1994). Planets, Stars and Orbs: The Medieval Cosmos, 1200-1687. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-56509-X. 
  • Lloyd, G. E. R. (1968). Aristotle: The Growth and Structure of His Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-09456-9. 
  • Sorabji, Richard (1988). Matter, Space and Motion: Theories in Antiquity and Their Sequel. London: Duckworth. pp. 224–6. ISBN 0-7156-2205-6. 
  • Weisheipl, James A. (1961). "The Celestial Movers in Medieval Physics". Thomist 24: 286–326. 
  • Wildberg, Christian (1988). John Philoponus’ criticism of Aristotle’s theory of aether. Peripatoi. 16. Berlin: W. de Gruyter. ISBN 3-11-010446-6. 
  • Wolfson, Harry A. (1958). "The Plurality of Immovable Movers in Aristotle and Averroës". Harvard Studies in Classical Philology 63: 233–253. doi:10.2307/310858. JSTOR 310858. 
  • Wolfson, Harry A. (1962). "The Problem of the Souls of the Spheres from the Byzantine Commentaries on Aristotle Through the Arabs and St. Thomas to Kepler". Dumbarton Oaks Papers 16: 65–93. doi:10.2307/1291158. JSTOR 1291158. 

Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Нужен реферат?

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Celestial spheres — Not to be confused with celestial sphere. For other uses, see Celestial (disambiguation). Geocentric celestial spheres; Peter Apian s Cosmographia (Antwerp, 1539) …   Wikipedia

  • Celestial mechanics — is the branch of astrophysics that deals with the motions of celestial objects. The field applies principles of physics, historically classical mechanics, to astronomical objects such as stars and planets to produce ephemeris data. Orbital… …   Wikipedia

  • The Book of Healing — (Arabic: الشفاء Al Shefa , Latin: Sanatio ) is a scientific and philosophical encyclopedia written by the great Islamic polymath Abū Alī ibn Sīnā (Avicenna) from Asfahana, near Bukhara in Greater Persia (now Uzbekistan). Despite its English title …   Wikipedia

  • Ionians (The) — The Ionians Malcolm Schofield THALES AND OTHERS The Greeks agreed that philosophy had begun with Thales. However they did not know much about his views.1 What survives is mostly a potent legend. Herodotus tells stories of his practical ingenuity …   History of philosophy

  • Christian angelic hierarchy — The Assumption of the Virgin by Francesco Botticini at the National Gallery London, shows three hierarchies and nine orders of angels, each with different characteristics …   Wikipedia

  • Theory of impetus — The theory of impetus was an antiquated auxiliary or secondary theory of Aristotelian dynamics, put forth initially to explain projectile motion against gravity. It was first introduced by Hipparchus in antiquity, and subsequently further… …   Wikipedia

  • Islamic Golden Age — The Islamic Golden Age, also sometimes known as the Islamic Renaissance, [Joel L. Kraemer (1992), Humanism in the Renaissance of Islam , p. 1 148, Brill Publishers, ISBN 9004072594.] was traditionally dated from the 8th century to the 13th… …   Wikipedia

  • History of physics — The modern discipline of physics emerged in the 17th century following in traditions of inquiry established by Galileo Galilei, René Descartes, Isaac Newton, and other natural philosophers.Fact|date=September 2008 Prior to this time, a unified… …   Wikipedia

  • Astral body — The Astral Sleep by Jeroen van Valkenburg The astral body is a subtle body posited by many religious philosophers, intermediate between the intelligent soul and the physical body, composed of a subtle material.[1] The concept ultimately derives… …   Wikipedia

  • History of Physics —     History of Physics     † Catholic Encyclopedia ► History of Physics     The subject will be treated under the following heads: I. A Glance at Ancient Physics; II. Science and Early Christian Scholars; III. A Glance at Arabian Physics; IV.… …   Catholic encyclopedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”