- Infinitesimal
Infinitesimals (from a 17th century
Modern Latin coinage "infinitesimus", originally referring to the "infinite -th " member of a series) have been used to express the idea of objects so small that there is no way to see them or to measure them. For everyday life, an infinitesimal object is an object which is smaller than any possible measure. When used as an adjective in the vernacular, "infinitesimal" means extremely small, but not necessarily "infinitely small".Before the nineteenth century none of the mathematical concepts relating to infinitesimals as we know them today were formally defined, but many of these concepts were already there. The founders of calculus, Leibniz, Newton, Euler, Lagrange, the Bernoullis and many others, used infinitesimals in the way shown below and achieved essentially correct results even though no formal definition was available (similarly, there was no formal definition of real numbers at the time).
History of the infinitesimal
The first
mathematician to make use of infinitesimals wasArchimedes (c. 250 BC) [Archimedes, "The Method of Mechanical Theorems"; seeArchimedes Palimpsest ] . TheArchimedean property is the property of having no nonzero infinitesimals in an orderedalgebraic structure .In
India from the 12th century until the 16th century, infinitesimals were discovered for use withdifferential calculus by Indian mathematicianBhaskara and variousKeralese mathematicians .When Newton and Leibniz developed
calculus , they made use of infinitesimals. A typical argument might go:::To find the
derivative "f′"("x") of the function "f"("x") = "x"2, let d"x" be an infinitesimal. Then,:::
::since d"x" is infinitely small.
This argument, while intuitively appealing, and producing the correct result, is not mathematically rigorous. The use of infinitesimals was attacked as incorrect by Bishop Berkeley in his work "
The Analyst ". [George Berkeley, "The Analyst; or a discourse addressed to an infidel mathematician"] The fundamental problem is that d"x" is first treated as non-zero (because we divide by it), but later discarded as if it were zero.The naive definition of an infinitesimal is this: a number whose
absolute value is less than any non-zero positive number. From this definition, it can be shown than there are no non-zero real infinitesimals, using the property of theleast upper bound . Considering just the positive numbers, the only way for a number to be less than all numbers would be to be the least positive number. If "h" is such a number, then what is "h"/2? Or if "h" is indivisible, is it still a number? Also, intuitively, one would require that the reciprocal of an infinitesimal is infinitely large (in modulus) or unlimited, but this would make it the greatest number when clearly, there is no "last" biggest number.Despite this, the real numbers can in fact be extended and modified to include infinitesimals, forming such systems as the
dual numbers or thehyperreals , but this can only be done if certain properties of the real numbers are removed.It was not until the second half of the nineteenth century that the calculus was given a formal mathematical foundation by
Karl Weierstrass and others using the notion of a limit. In the 20th century, it was found that infinitesimals could after all be treated rigorously. Neither formulation is wrong, and both give the same results if used correctly.Modern uses of infinitesimals
Infinitesimal is necessarily a relative concept. If epsilon is infinitesimal with respect to a class of numbers it means that epsilon cannot belong to that class. This is the crucial point: infinitesimal must necessarily mean infinitesimal "with respect" to some other type of numbers.
The path to formalisation
Proving or disproving the existence of infinitesimals of the kind used in nonstandard analysis depends on the model and which collection of
axiom s are used. We consider here systems where infinitesimals can be shown to exist.In 1936
Maltsev proved thecompactness theorem . This theorem is fundamental for the existence of infinitesimals as it proves that it is possible to formalise them. A consequence of this theorem is that if there is a number system in which it is true that for any positive integer "n" there is a positive number "x" such that 0 < "x" < 1/"n", then there exists an extension of that number system in which it is true that there exists a positive number "x" such that for any positive integer "n" we have 0 < "x" < 1/"n". The possibility to switch "for any" and "there exists" is crucial. The first statement is true in the real numbers as given inZFC set theory : for any positive integer "n" it is possible to find a real number between 1/"n" and zero, but this real number will depend on "n". Here, one chooses "n" first, then one finds the corresponding "x". In the second expression, the statement says that there is an "x" (at least one), chosen first, which is between 0 and 1/"n" for any "n". In this case "x" is infinitesimal. This is not true in the real numbers (R) given by ZFC. Nonetheless, the theorem proves that there is a model (a number system) in which this will be true. The question is: what is this model? What are its properties? Is there only one such model? There are in fact many ways to construct such a one-dimensional linearly ordered set of numbers, but fundamentally, there are two different approaches:: 1) Extend the number system so that it contains more numbers than the real numbers.
: 2) Extend the axioms (or extend the language) so that the distinction between the infinitesimals and non-infinitesimals can be made in the real numbers.
In 1960,
Abraham Robinson provided an answer following the first approach. The extended set is called the hyperreals and contains numbers less in absolute value than any positive real number. The method may be considered relatively complex but it does prove that infinitesimals exist in the universe of ZFC set theory. The real numbers are called standard numbers and the new non-real hyperreals are called nonstandard.In 1977
Edward Nelson provided an answer following the second approach. The extended axioms are IST, which stands either for Internal Set Theory or for the initials of the three extra axioms: Idealization, Standardization, Transfer. In this system we consider that the language is extended in such a way that we can express facts about infinitesimals. The real numbers are either standard or nonstandard. An infinitesimal is a nonstandard real number which is less, in absolute value, than any positive standard real number.In 2006 [http://math.sci.ccny.cuny.edu/people?name=Karel_Hrbacek Karel Hrbacek] developed an extension of Nelson's approach in which the real numbers are stratified in (infinitely) many levels i.e, in the coarsest level there are no infinitesimals nor unlimited numbers. Infinitesimals are in a finer level and there are also infinitesimals with respect to this new level and so on.
All of these approaches are mathematically rigorous.
This allows for a definition of infinitesimals which refers to these approaches:
A definition
:An infinitesimal number is a nonstandard number whose modulus is less than any nonzero positive standard number.
What standard and nonstandard refer to depends on the chosen context.
Alternatively, we can have
synthetic differential geometry orsmooth infinitesimal analysis with its roots incategory theory . This approach departs dramatically from the classical logic used in conventional mathematics by denying thelaw of excluded middle --i.e., "not" ("a" ≠ "b") does not have to mean "a" = "b". A "nilsquare" or "nilpotent " infinitesimal can then be defined. This is a number "x" where "x"2 = 0 is true, but "x" = 0 need not be true at the same time. With an infinitesimal such as this, algebraic proofs using infinitesimals are quite rigorous, including the one given above.ee also
*
Hyperreal number
*Infinitesimal calculus
*Non-standard calculus
*Nonstandard analysis
*Surreal number
*Differential (mathematics)
*Dual number
*Model theory Notes
References
* J. Keisler "Elementary Calculus" (2000) University of Wisconsin [http://www.math.wisc.edu/~keisler/calc.html]
* K. Stroyan "Foundations of Infinitesimal Calculus" (1993) [http://www.math.uiowa.edu/%7Estroyan/InfsmlCalculus/InfsmlCalc.htm]
* Robert Goldblatt (1998) "Lectures on the hyperreals" Springer. [http://www.springer.com/west/home/generic/order?SGWID=4-40110-22-1590889-0]
* "Nonstandard Methods and Applications in Mathematics" (2007) Lecture Notes in Logic 25, Association for Symbolic Logic. [http://www.aslonline.org/books-lnl_25.html]
* "The Strength of Nonstandard Analysis" (2007) Springer. [http://www.springer.com/west/home/springerwiennewyork/mathematics?SGWID=4-40638-22-173705722-0]
Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.