- Homunculus argument
The homunculus argument is a
fallacy arising most commonly in the theory of vision. One may explain (human) vision by noting thatlight from the outside world forms an image on theretina s in theeye s and something (or some'one') in thebrain looks at these images as if they are images on a movie screen (this theory of vision is sometimes termed the theory of theCartesian Theater : it is most associated, nowadays, with the psychologist David Marr). The question arises as to the nature of this internal viewer. The assumption here is that there is a 'little man' or 'homunculus ' inside the brain 'looking at' the movie.The reason why this is a fallacy may be understood by asking how the homunculus 'sees' the internal movie. The obvious answer is that there is another homunculus inside the first homunculus's 'head' or 'brain' looking at this 'movie'. But how does "this" homunculus see the 'outside world'? In order to answer this, we are forced to posit "another" homunculus inside this other homunculus's head and so forth. In other words, we are in a situation of
infinite regress : the argument has failed. The problem with thehomunculus argument is that it tries to account for a phenomenon in terms of the very phenomenon that it is supposed to explain--that is, homuncular arguments are fallacious for the same reason that a recipe for cake that had, as one of its ingredients, 'cake' is a problem recipe.Homunculus arguments in terms of Rules
Another example is with
cognitivist theories that argue that the human brain uses 'rules' to carry out operations (these rules often conceptualised as being like thealgorithms of acomputer program ). For example, in his work of the '50s, '60s and '70sNoam Chomsky argued that (in the words of one of his books) human beings use "Rules and Representations" (or to be more specific, rules acting on representations) in order to cognise (more recently Chomsky has abandoned this view: c.f. theMinimalist Program ).Now, in terms of (say) chess, the players are given 'rules' (i.e. the rules of chess) to follow. So: who "uses" these rules? The answer is self-evident: the players of the game (of chess) use the rules: it's not the case (obviously) that the rules "themselves" play chess. The rules themselves are merely inert marks on paper until a "human being" reads, understands and uses them. But what about the 'rules' that are, allegedly, inside our head (brain)? Who reads, understands and uses them? Again, the implicit answer is (and, some would argue, must be) a 'homunculus': a little man who reads the rules and then gives orders to the body to act on them. But again we are in a situation of
infinite regress , because this implies that the homunculus has cognitive process that are also rule bound, which presupposes another homunculus inside "its" head, and so on and so forth. Therefore, so the argument goes, theories of mind that imply or state explicitly that cognition isrule bound cannot be correct unless some way is found to 'ground' the regress.This is important because it is often assumed in
cognitive science that rules andalgorithms are essentially the same: in other words, the theory that cognition is rule bound is often believed to imply that thought (cognition ) is essentially, the manipulation of algorithms, and "this" is one of the key assumptions of some varieties ofartificial intelligence .Homunculus arguments are always fallacious unless some way can be found to 'ground' the regress (For example: a possible counter to this is that the brain as a whole "is" the homunculus, rather than thinking a specific part must be watching the movie). In
psychology andphilosophy of mind , 'homunculus arguments' (or the 'homunculus fallacies') are extremely useful for detecting where theories ofmind fail or are incomplete.The Homunculus fallacy is closely related to
Ryle's Regress .ee also
*
Cartesian theater
Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.