- Complex argument (continued fraction)
In analysis, the complex argument "θ" = arg("z") is commonly defined as an angle, often in terms of the inverse tangent function, or the inverse cosine. In a purely formal and perfectly rigorous treatment of the complex numbers, such reliance on geometric intuition should be avoided. [(Whittaker and Watson, 1927, "Appendix"). W. and W. provide a purely analytical approach to this problem, but instead of dealing directly with the natural logarithm, their analysis begins with Euler's formula for the exponential function.] Here is one way the complex argument "θ", −"π" < "θ" ≤ "π", can be defined without reference to any geometrical or trigonometric construction.
Formal definition of arg("z")
By convention, arg(0) is undefined, since there is no complex number "z" for which "e""z" = 0. [See
Picard theorem .] We define arg("z") = "π" for real "z" < 0. When "z" is not a real number ≤ 0, we define:
now completes the formal definition of arg("z") without reference to any geometrical construction.
Historical context
Euler's formula connecting this continued fraction with an infinite logarithmic series was first published in 1748. Euler was not particularly concerned with procedural niceties, and mathematicians today generally regard his work as original, and very useful, but not entirely rigorous. [(Euler, 1748; cited in Wall, 1948).]
Gauss found another way to derive this continued fraction from the
hypergeometric series in 1813. Gauss proved a general formula, but he did not have the analytical tools necessary to verify the uniform convergence of this particular continued fraction. [(Gauss, 1813; cited in Wall, 1948).]Up through the time of Gauss, mathematicians generally did not draw a sharp distinction between geometrical and analytical concepts, and used these frameworks almost interchangeably. This practice continues in many modern presentations of mathematical ideas – charts and graphs are freely used to illustrate the concepts of analysis.
In the mid-19th century mathematicians like
Cauchy and Weierstrass began insisting on more rigorous proofs. This emphasis on rigor eventually led to Hilbert's program of formalism in mathematics, and that stimulated a desire to state the concepts ofmathematical analysis and the concepts ofgeometry without mixing them together.See also
*
Complex logarithm
*Complex number
*Complex plane
*Euler's continued fraction formula
*Generalized continued fraction
*Atan2 Notes
References
*
Leonhard Euler , "Introductio in analysin infinitorum", Vol. I, Chapter 18 (1748).
*Karl Friedrich Gauss , "Werke", Vol. 3, pp. 134-138 (1813).
*H. S. Wall, "Analytic Theory of Continued Fractions", D. Van Nostrand Company, Inc., 1948; reprinted (1973) by Chelsea Publishing Company ISBN 0-8284-0207-8.
*E. T. Whittaker andG. N. Watson , "A Course in Modern Analysis", fourth edition, Cambridge University Press, 1927.
Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.