Hilbert-style deduction system

Hilbert-style deduction system

In logic, especially mathematical logic, a "Hilbert-style deduction system" is a type of system of "formal deduction" attributed to Gottlob FregeMáté & Ruzsa 1997:129] and David Hilbert. These deductive systems are most often studied for first-order logic, but are of interest for other logics as well.

Most variants of Hilbert-style deductions systems take a characteristic tack the way they balance a trade-off between logical axioms and rules of inference. Hilbert-style deduction systems can be characterized by the choice of a large number of schemes of logical axioms and a small set of rules of inference. The most commonly studied Hilbert-style deduction system has just one rule of inference – modus ponens – and several infinite axiom schemes.

A characteristic feature of the various variants of Hilbert-style deduction systems is that the "context" is not changed in any of their rules of inference, while both natural deduction and sequent calculus contain some context-changing rules. Thus, if we are interested only in the derivability of tautologies, no hypothetical judgments, then we can formalize the Hilbert-style deduction system in such a way that its rules of inference contain only judgments of a rather simple form. The same cannot be done with the other two deductions systems: as context is changed in some of their rules of inferences, they cannot be formalized so that hypothetical judgments could be avoided — not even if we want to use them just for proving derivability of tautologies.

Systems of natural deduction take the opposite tack, including many deduction rules but very few or no axiom schemes.

Formal deductions

In a Hilbert-style deduction system, a formal deduction is a finite sequence of formulas in which each formula is either an axiom or is obtained from previous formulas by a rule of inferences. These formal deductions are meant to mirror natural-language proofs, although they are far more detailed.

Suppose Gamma is a set of formulas, considered as hypotheses. For example Gamma could be a set of axioms for group theory or set theory. The notation Gamma vdash phi means that there is a deduction that ends with phi using as axioms only logical axioms and elements of Gamma. Thus, informally, Gamma vdash phi means that phi is provable assuming all the formulas in Gamma.

Hilbert-style deduction systems are characterized by the use of numerous schemes of logical axioms. An axiom scheme is an infinite set of axioms obtained by substituting all formulas of some form into a specific pattern. Not only are the axioms generated from this pattern, but also any generalization of one of these axioms, is included in the set of logical axioms. A generalization of a formula is obtained by prefixing zero or more universal quantifiers on the formula; thus:forall y ( forall x Pxy o Pty)is a generalization of forall x Pxt o Pty.

Logical axioms

A common Hilbert-style system has six infinite axiom schemes and one additional axiom. In order to reduce the number of axiom schemes, this system assumes all formulas have been rewritten to use only the connectives lnot and o and only the quantifier forall. As discussed below, it is possible to extend the system to include additional logical connectives, such as land and lor, without enlarging the class of deducible formulas.

The first three logical axiom schemes allow (together with modus ponens) for the manipulation of logical connectives.:1. phi o left( psi o phi ight) :2. left ( phi o ( psi ightarrow xi ight)) o left( left( phi o psi ight) o left( phi o xi ight) ight):3. left ( lnot phi o lnot psi ight) o left( psi o phi ight)

The fourth, fifth, and sixth logical axiom schemes provide ways to add, manipulate, and remove universal quantifiers.:4. forall x left( phi ight) o phi [x:=t] where "t" may be substituted for "x" in phi:5. forall x left( phi o psi ight) o left( forall x left( phi ight) o forall x left( psi ight) ight):6. phi o forall x left( phi ight) where "x" is not a free variable of phi.

The final axiom schemes are required to work with formulas involving the equality symbol.:7. x = x for every variable "x".:8. left( x = y ight) o left( phi [z:=x] o phi [z:=y] ight)

Conservative extensions

It is common to include in a Hilbert-style deduction system only axioms for implication and negation. Given these axioms, it is possible to form conservative extensions of the deduction theorem that permit the use of additional connectives. These extensions are called conservative because if a formula φ involving new connectives is rewritten as a logically equivalent formula θ involving only negation, implication, and universal quantification, then φ is derivable in the extended system if and only if θ is derivable in the original system. When fully extended, a Hilbert-style system will resemble more closely a system of natural deduction.

Existential quantification

* Introduction
* Elimination

Conjunction and disjunction

* Conjunction introduction and elimination
* Disjunction introduction and elimination

Metatheorems

Because Hilbert-style systems have very few deduction rules, it is common to prove metatheorems that show that additional deduction rules add no deductive power, in the sense that a deduction using the new deduction rules can be converted into a deduction using only the original deduction rules.

Some common metatheorems of this form are:
* The deduction theorem: Gamma;phi vdash psi if and only if Gamma vdash phi o psi.
* Gamma vdash phi leftrightarrow psi if and only if Gamma vdash phi o psi and Gamma vdash psi o phi.
* Contraposition: If Gamma;phi vdash psi then Gamma;lnot psi vdash lnot phi.
* Generalization: If Gamma vdash phi and "x" does not occur free in any formula of Gamma then Gamma vdash forall x phi.

Further connections

Axiom 1, 2 together with deduction rule modus ponens, corresponds to combinatory logic base combinators K, S together with the notion of application. See also Curry-Howard correspondence.

Notes

References

* cite book
last = Curry
first = Haskell B.
coauthors = Robert Feys
title = Combinatory Logic Vol. I
volume = 1
year = 1958
publisher = North Holland
location = Amsterdam

*
*
* It is a Hungarian translation of Alfred Tarski's selected papers on semantic theory of truth.

External links

cite web |last=Farmer |first=W. M |title=Propositional logic |url=http://www.cas.mcmaster.ca/~wmfarmer/SE-2F03-05/slides/02-prop-logic.pdf |format=pdf It describes (among others) a part of the Hilbert-style deduction system (restricted to propositional calculus).


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Нужна курсовая?

Look at other dictionaries:

  • David Hilbert — Hilbert redirects here. For other uses, see Hilbert (disambiguation). David Hilbert David Hilbert (1912) Born …   Wikipedia

  • Axiomatic system — In mathematics, an axiomatic system is any set of axioms from which some or all axioms can be used in conjunction to logically derive theorems. A mathematical theory consists of an axiomatic system and all its derived theorems. An axiomatic… …   Wikipedia

  • Curry–Howard correspondence — A proof written as a functional program: the proof of commutativity of addition on natural numbers in the proof assistant Coq. nat ind stands for mathematical induction, eq ind for substitution of equals and f equal for taking the same function… …   Wikipedia

  • Natural deduction — In logic and proof theory, natural deduction is a kind of proof calculus in which logical reasoning is expressed by inference rules closely related to the natural way of reasoning. This contrasts with the axiomatic systems which instead use… …   Wikipedia

  • Curry-Howard correspondence — The Curry Howard correspondence is the direct relationship between computer programs and mathematical proofs. Also known as Curry Howard isomorphism, proofs as programs correspondence and formulae as types correspondence, it refers to the… …   Wikipedia

  • Propositional calculus — In mathematical logic, a propositional calculus or logic (also called sentential calculus or sentential logic) is a formal system in which formulas of a formal language may be interpreted as representing propositions. A system of inference rules… …   Wikipedia

  • Judgment (mathematical logic) — In mathematical logic, a judgment can be for example an assertion about occurrence of a free variable in an expression of the object language, or about provability of a proposition (either as a tautology or from a given context); but judgments… …   Wikipedia

  • List of mathematics articles (H) — NOTOC H H cobordism H derivative H index H infinity methods in control theory H relation H space H theorem H tree Haag s theorem Haagerup property Haaland equation Haar measure Haar wavelet Haboush s theorem Hackenbush Hadamard code Hadamard… …   Wikipedia

  • Boolean algebra (introduction) — Boolean algebra, developed in 1854 by George Boole in his book An Investigation of the Laws of Thought , is a variant of ordinary algebra as taught in high school. Boolean algebra differs from ordinary algebra in three ways: in the values that… …   Wikipedia

  • Plankalkül — Infobox programming language name = Plankalkül paradigm = procedural year = concept first published in 1948 designer = Konrad Zuse latest release version = C99 latest release date = March 2000 implementations = Plankalkül Compiler by the FU… …   Wikipedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”