- Strict conditional
In
logic , a strict conditional is amaterial conditional that is acted upon by the necessity operator frommodal logic . For any two propositions and , the formula says that materially implies while says that strictly implies . Strict conditionals are the result ofClarence Irving Lewis 's attempt to find a conditional for logic that can adequately expressindicative conditional s. Such a conditional would, for example, avoid theparadoxes of material implication . The following statement, for example, is not correctly formalized by material implication.: If Bill Gates had graduated in Medicine, then Elvis never died.
This condition is clearly false: the degree of Bill Gates has nothing to do with whether Elvis is still alive. However, the direct encoding of this formula in
classical logic using material implication lead to:: Bill Gates graduated in Medicine Elvis never died.
This formula is true because a formula is true whenever the antecedent is false. Hence, this formula is not an adequate translation of the original sentence. Strict conditions are encodings of implications in modal logic attempting A different encoding is:
: (Bill Gates graduated in Medicine Elvis never died.)
In modal logic, this formula means (roughly) that, in every possible world in which Bill Gates graduated in Medicine, Elvis never died. Since one can easily imagine a world where Bill Gates is a Medicine graduate and Elvis is dead, this formula is false. Hence, this formula seems a correct translation of the original sentence.
Although the strict conditional is much closer to being able to express natural language conditionals than the material conditional, it has its own problems. The following sentence, for example, is not correctly formalized by a strict conditional:
: If Bill Gates graduated in Medicine, then 2 + 2 = 4.
Using strict conditionals, this sentence is expressed as:
: (Bill Gates graduated in Medicine 2 + 2 = 4)
In modal logic, this formula means that, in every possible world where Bill Gates graduated in medicine, it holds that 2 + 2 = 4. Since 2 + 2 is equal to 4 in all possible worlds, this formula is true. While it is clearly not the case that 2 + 2 = 4 if Bill Gates graduated in medicine, the corresponding strict material statement is true.
To avoid the paradoxes of strict implication, some logicians have created
counterfactual conditionals . Others, such asPaul Grice , have usedconversational implicature to argue that, despite apparent difficulties, the material conditional is just fine as a translation for the natural language 'if...then...'. Others still have turned torelevant logic to supply a connection between the antecedent and consequent of provable conditionals.In
logic , the corresponding conditional of anargument (or derivation) is alogical implication whose antecedent is the conjunction of the argument's (or derivation's)premise s and whoseconsequent is the argument'sconclusion . An argument isvalid if and only if its corresponding conditional is a necessary truth. It follows that an argument is valid if and only if the negation of its corresponding conditional is acontradiction .Example
Consider the following argument,
# Socrates is alive (A) or dead (D).
# Socrates is not alive (not A).
# Therefore, Socrates is dead (D).This argument's corresponding conditional may be stated as a conjunction of the premises that implies the conclusion,
:
External links
* [http://www.swif.uniba.it/lei/foldop/foldoc.cgi?corresponding+conditional Corresponding conditional from the Free On-line Dictionary of Computing]
ee also
*
Counterfactual conditional
*Indicative conditional
*Material conditional
*Logical implication References
*Edgington, Dorothy, 2001, "Conditionals," in Goble, Lou, ed., "The Blackwell Guide to Philosophical Logic". Blackwell.For an introduction to non-classical logic as an attempt to find a better translation of the conditional, see:
*Priest, Graham, 2001. "An Introduction to Non-Classical Logic". Cambridge Univ. Press.For an extended philosophical discussion of the issues mentioned in this article, see:
*Mark Sainsbury , 2001. "Logical Forms". Blackwell Publishers.
*Jonathan Bennett, 2003. "A Philosophical Guide to Conditionals". Oxford Univ. Press.
Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.