Hales–Jewett theorem

Hales–Jewett theorem

In mathematics, the Hales–Jewett theorem is a fundamental combinatorial result of Ramsey theory, concerning the degree to which high-dimensional objects must necessarily exhibit some combinatorial structure; it is impossible for such objects to be "completely random". [Alfred Hales, Robert Jewett, "Regularity and positional games", Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 106 (1963), 222--229.]

An informal geometric statement of the theorem is thatfor any positive integers "n" and "c" there is a number "H" such that if the cells of a "H"-dimensional "n"×"n"×"n"×...×"n" cube are colored with "c" colors, there must be one row, column, diagonal etc. of length "n" all of whose cells are the same color. In other words, the higher-dimensional, multi-player, "n"-in-a-row generalization of game of Tic-tac-toe cannot end in a draw, no matter how large "n" is, and no matter how many people "c" are playing, if it is played on a board of sufficiently high dimension "H". By a standard strategy stealing argument, one can thus conclude that the first player has a winning strategy when "H" is sufficiently large, though no constructive algorithm for obtaining this strategy is known.

More formally, let "W""n""H" be the set of words of length "H" over an alphabet with "n" letters; that is, the set of sequences of {1, 2, ..., "n"} of length "H". This set forms the hypercube that is the subject of the theorem. A "variable word" "w"("x") over "W""n""H" still has length "H" but includes the special element "x" in place of at least one of the letters. The words "w"(1), "w"(2), ..., "w"("n") obtained by replacing all instances of the special element "x" with 1, 2, ..., "n", form a "combinatorial line" in the space "W""n""H"; combinatorial lines correspond to rows, columns, and (some of the) diagonals of the hypercube. The Hales–Jewett theorem then states that for given positive integers "n" and "c", there exists a positive integer "H", depending on "n" and "c", such that for any partition of "W""n""H" into "c" parts, there is at least one part that contains an entire combinatorial line.

For example, take "n" = 3, "H" = 2, and "c" = 2. The hypercube "W""n""H" in this caseis just the standard tic-tac-toe board, with nine positions:

A typical combinatorialline would be the word 2x, which corresponds to the line 21, 22, 23; another combinatorial line is xx, which is the line11, 22, 33. (Note that the line 13, 22, 31, while a valid line for the game tic-tac-toe, is not considered a combinatorial line.) In this particular case, the Hales–Jewett theorem does not apply; it is possible to dividethe tic-tac-toe board into two sets, e.g. {11, 22, 23, 31} and {12, 13, 21, 32, 33}, neither of which containa combinatorial line (and would correspond to a draw in the game of tic-tac-toe). On the other hand, if we increase"H" to, say, 8 (so that the board is now eight-dimensional, with 38 = 6561 positions!), and partition this boardinto two sets (the "noughts" and "crosses"), then one of the two sets must contain a combinatorial line (i.e. no draw is possible in this variant of tic-tac-toe). For a proof, see below.

Proof of Hales–Jewett theorem (in a special case)

We now prove the Hales–Jewett theorem in the special case "n"=3, "c"=2, "H"=8 discussed above. The idea is toreduce this task to that of proving simpler versions of the Hales–Jewett theorem (in this particular case,to the cases "n"=2, "c"=2, "H"=2 and "n"=2, "c"=6, "H"=6). One can prove the general case ofthe Hales–Jewett theorem by similar methods, using mathematical induction.

Each element of the hypercube "W"38 is a string of eight numbers from 1 to 3, e.g. 13211321 is an element of the hypercube. We are assuming that this hypercube is completely filled with "noughts" and "crosses". We shall use a proof by contradiction and assume that neither the set of noughts nor the set of crosses contains a combinatorial line. If we fix the first six elements of such a string and let the last two vary, we obtain an ordinary tic-tac-toe board, for instance 132113?? gives such a board. For each such board abcdef??, we consider the positionsabcdef11, abcdef12, abcdef22. Each of these must be filled with either a nought or a cross, so by the
pigeonhole principle two of them must be filled with the same symbol. Since any two of these positions are part ofa combinatorial line, the third element of that line must be occupied by the opposite symbol (since we are assumingthat no combinatorial line has all three elements filled with the same symbol). In other words, for each choice of abcdef(which can be thought of as an element of the six-dimensional hypercube "W"36),there are six (overlapping) possibilities:

# abcdef11 and abcdef12 are noughts; abcdef13 is a cross.
# abcdef11 and abcdef22 are noughts; abcdef33 is a cross.
# abcdef12 and abcdef22 are noughts; abcdef31 is a cross.
# abcdef11 and abcdef12 are crosses; abcdef13 is a nought.
# abcdef11 and abcdef22 are crosses; abcdef33 is a nought.
# abcdef12 and abcdef22 are crosses; abcdef31 is a nought.

Thus we can partition the six-dimensional hypercube "W"36 into six classes, corresponding toeach of the above six possibilities. (If an element abcdef obeys multiple possibilities, we can choose one arbitrarily, e.g.by choosing the highest one on the above list).

Now consider the seven elements 111111, 111112, 111122, 111222, 112222, 122222, 222222 in "W"36.By the pigeonhole principle, two of these elements must fall into the same class. Suppose for instance111112 and 112222 fall into class (5), thus 11111211, 11111222, 11222211, 11222222 are crosses and 11111233, 11222233 arenoughts. But now consider the position 11333233, which must be filled with either a cross or a nought. If it is filledwith a cross, then the combinatorial line 11xxx2xx is filled entirely with crosses, contradicting our hypothesis. If insteadit is filled with a nought, then the combinatorial line 11xxx233 is filled entirely with noughts, again contradictingour hypothesis. Similarly if any other two of the above seven elements of "W"36 fall into the same class. Since we have a contradiction in all cases, the original hypothesis must be false; thus there must exist at leastone combinatorial line consisting entirely of noughts or entirely of crosses.

The above argument was somewhat wasteful; in fact the same theorem holds for "H"=4. [ Neil Hindman, Eric Tressler, [http://www.math.ucsd.edu/~etressle/research/hj32.pdf "The first nontrivial Hales-Jewett number is four"] , submitted.] If one extends the above argument to general values of "n" and "c", then "H" will grow very fast; even when "c"=2 (which corresponds to two-player tic-tac-toe) the "H" given by the above argument grows as fast as the Ackermann function. The first primitive recursive bound is due to Saharon Shelah, [ Saharon Shelah, "Primitive recursive bounds for van der Waerden numbers", J. Amer. Math. Soc. 1 (1988), 683--697.] and is still the best known bound in general for the "Hales–Jewett number" "H"="H"("n,c").

Connections with other theorems

Observe that the above argument also gives the following corollary: if we let "A" be the set of alleight-digit numbers whose digits are all either 1, 2, 3 (thus "A" contains numbers such as 11333233),and we color "A" into two colors, then "A" contains at least one arithmetic progression of length three,all of whose elements are the same color. This is simply because all of the combinatorial lines appearing in theabove proof of the Hales–Jewett theorem, also form arithmetic progressions in decimal notation. A more generalformulation of this argument can be used to show that the Hales–Jewett theorem generalizes van der Waerden's theorem. Indeed the Hales–Jewett theorem is substantially a stronger theorem.

Just as van der Waerden's theorem has a stronger "density version" in Szemerédi's theorem, the Hales–Jewett theorem also has a density version. [Hillel Furstenberg, Yitzhak Katznelson, "A density version of the Hales–Jewett theorem", J. d'Analyse Math. 57 (1991), 64--119.] In this strengthened version of the Hales–Jewett theorem, instead of coloring the entire hypercube "W""n""H" into "c" colors, one is given an arbitrary subset "A" of the hypercube "W""n""H" with some given density 0 < &delta; < 1. Then if "H" is sufficiently large depending in "n" and &delta;, then this set "A" must necessarily contain an entire combinatorial line.

See also

* Bartel Leendert van der Waerden

References

External links

* [http://www.math.uga.edu/~lyall/REU/ramsey.pdf A detailed proof of Hales-Jewett theorem]


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Поможем написать курсовую

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Van der Waerden's theorem — is a theorem of the branch of mathematics called Ramsey theory. The theorem is about the basic structure of the integers. It is named for Dutch mathematician B. L. van der Waerden. [B.L. van der Waerden, Beweis einer Baudetschen Vermutung , Nieuw …   Wikipedia

  • Ramsey theory — This article provides an introduction. For a more detailed and technical article, see Ramsey s theorem. Ramsey theory, named for Frank P. Ramsey, is a branch of mathematics that studies the conditions under which order must appear. Problems in… …   Wikipedia

  • Théorie de Ramsey — La théorie de Ramsey, qui porte le nom de Frank Ramsey, pose typiquement une question de la forme : combien d éléments d une certaine structure doivent être considérés pour qu une propriété particulière se vérifie ? Un adage souvent… …   Wikipédia en Français

  • List of theorems — This is a list of theorems, by Wikipedia page. See also *list of fundamental theorems *list of lemmas *list of conjectures *list of inequalities *list of mathematical proofs *list of misnamed theorems *Existence theorem *Classification of finite… …   Wikipedia

  • List of mathematics articles (H) — NOTOC H H cobordism H derivative H index H infinity methods in control theory H relation H space H theorem H tree Haag s theorem Haagerup property Haaland equation Haar measure Haar wavelet Haboush s theorem Hackenbush Hadamard code Hadamard… …   Wikipedia

  • List of combinatorics topics — This is a list of combinatorics topics.A few decades ago it might have been said that combinatorics is little more than a way to classify poorly understood problems, and some standard remedies. Great progress has been made since 1960.This page is …   Wikipedia

  • Outline of combinatorics — See also: Index of combinatorics articles The following outline is presented as an overview of and topical guide to combinatorics: Combinatorics – branch of mathematics concerning the study of finite or countable discrete structures. Contents 1… …   Wikipedia

  • Noga Alon — 2008 Noga Alon (hebräisch ‏נוגה אלון‎; Pseudonym Alon Nilli; * 1956) ist ein israelischer Mathematiker (Kombinatorik) und Informatiker. Alon promovierte 1983 an der Hebräischen Universität Jerusalem bei Micha Perle …   Deutsch Wikipedia

  • Theorie de Ramsey — Théorie de Ramsey La théorie de Ramsey, qui porte le nom de Frank P. Ramsey, pose typiquement une question de la forme : combien d éléments d une certaine structure doivent être considérés pour qu une propriété particulière se vérifie ? …   Wikipédia en Français

  • Théorie de ramsey — La théorie de Ramsey, qui porte le nom de Frank P. Ramsey, pose typiquement une question de la forme : combien d éléments d une certaine structure doivent être considérés pour qu une propriété particulière se vérifie ? Un adage souvent… …   Wikipédia en Français

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”