- Scott–Potter set theory
An approach to the
foundations of mathematics that is of relatively recent origin, Scott–Potter set theory is a collection of nested axiomatic set theories set out by thephilosopher Michael Potter, building on earlier work by themathematician Dana Scott and the philosopherGeorge Boolos .Potter (1990, 2004) clarified and simplified the approach of Scott (1974), and showed how the resulting
axiomatic set theory can do what is expected of such theory, namely grounding the cardinal andordinal number s, Peano arithmetic and the other usualnumber system s, and the theory ofrelation s.ZU etc.
Preliminaries
This section and the next follow Part I of Potter (2004) closely. The background logic is
first-order logic with identity. Theontology includesurelement s as well as sets, simply to allow the set theories described in this entry to have models that are not purely mathematical in nature. The urelements serve no essential mathematical purpose.Some terminology peculiar to Potter's set theory:
*"a" is a collection if "a"={"x" : "x"∈"a"}. All sets are collections, but not all collections are sets.
* The accumulation of "a", acc("a"), is the set {"x" : "x" is a urelement or ∃"b"∈"a" ("x"∈"b" or "x"⊂"b")}.
* If ∀"V"∈V("V" = acc(V∩"V")) then V is a history.
* A level is the accumulation of a history.
* An initial level has no other levels as members.
* A limit level is a level that is neither the initial level nor the level above any other level.
* The birthday of set "a", denoted "V"("a"), is the lowest level "V" such that "a"⊂"V".Axioms
The following three axioms define the theory ZU.
Creation: ∀"V"∃"V' "("V"∈"V' ").
"Remark": There is no highest level, hence there are infinitely many levels. This axiom establishes the
ontology of levels.Separation: An
axiom schema . For any first-order formula Φ("x") with (bound) variables ranging over the level "V", the collection {"x"∈"V" : Φ("x")} is also a set. (SeeAxiom schema of separation .)"Remark": Given the levels established by "Creation", this schema establishes the existence of sets and how to form them. It tells us that a level is a set, and all subsets, definable via
first-order logic , of levels are also sets. This schema can be seen as an extension of the background logic.Infinity: There exists at least one limit level. (See
Axiom of infinity .)"Remark": Among the sets "Separation" allows, at least one is
infinite . This axiom is primarilymathematical , as there is no need for theactual infinite in other human contexts, the human sensory order being necessarilyfinite . For mathematical purposes, the axiom "There exists an inductive set" would suffice.Further existence premises
The following statements, while in the nature of axioms, are not axioms of ZU. Instead, they assert the existence of sets satisfying a stated condition. As such, they are "existence premises," meaning the following. Let X denote any statement below. Any theorem whose proof requires X is then formulated conditionally as "If X holds, then..." Potter defines several systems using existence premises, including the following two:
* ZfU =df ZU + "Ordinals";
* ZFU =df "Separation" + "Reflection".Ordinals: For each (infinite) ordinal α, there exists a corresponding level "V"α.
"Remark": In words, "There exists a level corresponding to each infinite ordinal." "Ordinals" makes possible the conventional Von Neumann definition of ordinal numbers.
Let τ("x") be a first-order term.
Replacement: An
axiom scheme . For any collection "a", ∀"x"∈"a" [τ("x") is a set] → {τ("x") : "x"∈"a"} is a set."Remark": If the term τ("x") is a function (call it "f"("x")), and if the domain of "f" is a set, then the range of "f" is also a set.
Let Φ denote a first-order formula in which any number of
free variable s are present. Let Φ("V") denote Φ with these free variables all quantified, with the quantified variables restricted to the level "V".Reflection: An
axiom schema . If the free variables in any instance of ∃"V" [Φ→Φ("V")] are universally quantified, the result is an axiom."Remark": This schema asserts the existence of a "partial" universe, namely the level "V", in which all properties Φ holding when the quantified variables range over all levels, also hold when these variables range over "V" only. "Reflection" turns "Creation", "Infinity", "Ordinals", and "Replacement" into theorems (Potter 2004: §13.3).
Let "A" and "a" denote sequences of non
empty set s, each indexed by "n".Countable Choice: Given any sequence "A", there exists a sequence "a" such that::∀"n"∈ω ["a"n∈"A"n] .
"Remark". "Countable Choice" enables proving that any set must be one of finite or infinite.
Let "B" and "C" denote sets, and let "n" index the members of "B", each denoted "B""n".
Choice: Let the members of "B" be disjoint nonempty sets. Then::∃"C"∀"n" ["C"∩"B""n" is a
singleton ] .Discussion
In Boolos (1971), the "iterative conception of set" stratifies the universe of sets into a series of "levels," with sets at lower levels being logically prior to sets at higher levels. Moreover, the sets at a given level are the members of the sets making up the next higher level. Hence the levels form a nested and
well-ordered sequence, and would form a hierarchy if set membership weretransitive . Boolos's definite axiomatic treatment of these ideas is the set theory "S" in Boolos (1989), a two sorted first order theory involving sets and levels.The resulting hierarchy of levels and sets steers clear, in a well-motivated way, of the well-known
paradox es of Russell, Burali-Forti, and Cantor that result from the unrestricted use of the principle of comprehension thatnaive set theory allows. Collections such as "the class of all sets" or "the class of all ordinals" include sets from all levels of the hierarchy. Given the iterative conception, such collections cannot form sets at any given level of the hierarchy and thus cannot be sets at all. The iterative conception has gradually become more accepted over time, despite an imperfect understanding of its historical origins.cott's theory
Scott (1974) did not mention the "iterative conception of set," instead proposing his theory as a natural outgrowth of the simple theory of types. Nevertheless, Scott's theory can be seen as an unwitting axiomatization of the iterative conception and the associated iterative hierarchy.
Scott began with an axiom he declined to name: the
atomic formula "x"∈"y" implies that "y" is a set. In symbols::∀"x","y"∃"a" ["x"∈"y"→"y"="a"] .His axiom of "Extensionality" andaxiom schema of "Comprehension" (Separation) are strictly analogous to theirZF counterparts and so do not mention levels. He then invoked two axioms that do mention levels:
* "Accumulation". A given level "accumulates" all members and subsets of all earlier levels. See the above definition of "accumulation".
* "Restriction". All collections belong to some level."Restriction" also implies the existence of at least one level and assures that all sets are well-founded.Scott's final axiom, the "Reflection" schema, is identical to the above existence premise bearing the same name, and likewise does duty for
ZF 's "Infinity" and "Replacement". Scott's system has the same strength asZF .Potter's theory
Potter (1990, 2004) introduced the idiosyncratic terminology described earlier in this entry, and discarded or replaced all of Scott's axioms except "Reflection"; the result is ZU. Russell's paradox is Potter's (2004) first theorem;
Russell's paradox reproduces his very easy proof thereof, one requiring no set theory axioms. Thus Potter establishes from the very outset the need for a more restricted kind of collection, namely sets, that steers clear of Russell's paradox.ZU, like
ZF , cannot be finitely axiomatized. ZU differs fromZFC in that it:
* Includes noaxiom of extensionality because the usual extensionality principle follows from the definition of collection and an easy lemma;
* Admits nonwellfounded sets. However Potter (2004) never invokes such sets, and no theorem in Potter would be overturned were Foundation or its equivalent added to ZU;
*Includes no equivalents of Choice or the axiom schema of Replacement.Hence ZU is equivalent to theZermelo set theory of 1908, namelyZFC minus Choice, Replacement, and Foundation. The remaining differences between ZU and ZFC are mainly expositional.What is the strength of ZfU, and ZFU relative to Z, ZF, and
ZFC ?The
natural number s are not defined as a particular set within the iterative hierarchy, but as models of a "pure" Dedekind algebra. "Dedekind algebra" is Potter's name for a set closed under an unaryinjective operation, successor, whose domain contains a unique element, zero, absent from its range. Because all Dedekind algebras with the lowest possible birthdays arecategorical (all models areisomorphic ), any such algebra can proxy for the natural numbers.The Frege–Russell definitions of the cardinal and ordinal numbers work in Scott-Potter set theory, because the
equivalence class es these definitions require are indeed sets. Thus in ZU an equivalence class of:
*Equinumerous sets from a common level is acardinal number ;
*Isomorphic well-ordering s, also from a common level, is anordinal number .InZFC , defining the cardinals and ordinals in this fashion gives rise to the Cantor andBurali-Forti paradox , respectively.Although Potter (2004) devotes an entire appendix to
proper class es, the strength and merits of Scott-Potter set theory relative to the well-known rivals toZFC that admit proper classes, namely NBG andMorse–Kelley set theory , have yet to be explored.Scott-Potter set theory resembles NFU in that the latter is a recently devised
axiomatic set theory admitting bothurelement s and sets that are not well-founded. But the urelements of NFU, unlike those of ZU, play an essential role; they and the resulting restrictions on Extensionality make possible a proof of NFU'sconsistency relative toPeano arithmetic . But nothing is known about the strength of NFU relative to "Creation"+"Separation", NFU+"Infinity" relative to ZU, and of NFU+"Infinity"+"Countable Choice" relative to ZU+"Countable Choice".Unlike nearly all writing on set theory in recent decades, Potter (2004) mentions mereological fusions. His "collections" are also synonymous with the "virtual sets" of
Willard Quine andRichard Milton Martin : entities arising from the free use of the principle of comprehension that can never be admitted to theuniverse of discourse .ee also
*
Foundation of mathematics
*Hierarchy (mathematics)
*List of set theory topics
*Philosophy of mathematics
*Von Neumann universe
*Zermelo set theory
*ZFC References
*
George Boolos , 1971, "The iterative conception of set," "Journal of Philosophy 68": 215–31. Reprinted in Boolos 1999. "Logic, Logic, and Logic". Harvard Univ. Press: 13-29.
*--------, 1989, "Iteration Again," "Philosophical Topics 42": 5-21. Reprinted in Boolos 1999. "Logic, Logic, and Logic". Harvard Univ. Press: 88-104.
*Potter, Michael, 1990. "Sets: An Introduction". Oxford Univ. Press.
*------, 2004. "Set Theory and its Philosophy". Oxford Univ. Press.
*Dana Scott , 1974, "Axiomatizing set theory" in Jech, Thomas, J., ed., "Axiomatic Set Theory II", Proceedings of Symposia in Pure Mathematics 13. American Mathematical Society: 207–14.External links
Reviews of Potter (2004):
* Bays, Timothy, 2005, " [http://ndpr.nd.edu/review.cfm?id=2141 Review,] " "Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews".
*Uzquiano, Gabriel, 2005, " [http://philmat.oxfordjournals.org/cgi/content/full/13/3/308 Review,] " "Philosophia Mathematica 13": 308-46.
Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.