Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory

Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory

Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, with the axiom of choice, commonly abbreviated ZFC, is the standard form of axiomatic set theory and as such is the most common foundation of mathematics.

ZFC consists of a single primitive ontological notion, that of set, and a single ontological assumption, namely that all individuals in the universe of discourse (i.e., all mathematical objects) are sets. There is a single primitive binary relation, set membership; that set "a" is a member of set "b" is written a in b (usually read "a" is an element of "b" or "a" is in "b"). ZFC is a one-sorted first-order theory; hence the background logic is first-order logic. The axioms of ZFC govern how sets behave and interact.

History

In 1908, Ernst Zermelo proposed the first axiomatic set theory, Zermelo set theory. This axiomatic theory did not allow the construction of the ordinal numbers; while most of "ordinary mathematics" can be developed without ever using ordinals, ordinals are an essential tool in most set-theoretic investigations. Moreover, one of Zermelo's axioms invoked a concept, that of a "definite" property, whose operational meaning was not clear. In 1922, Abraham Fraenkel and Thoralf Skolem independently proposed operationalizing a "definite" property as one that could be formulated as a first order theory whose atomic formulas were limited to set membership and identity. They also independently proposed replacing the axiom schema of specification with the axiom schema of replacement. Appending this schema, as well as the axiom of regularity (proposed by Zermelo in 1930), to Zermelo set theory yields the theory denoted by ZF. Adding to ZF either the axiom of choice (AC) or a statement equivalent thereto, yields ZFC.

The axioms

There are many equivalent formulations of the ZFC axioms; for a rich but somewhat dated discussion of this fact, see Fraenkel "et al." (1973). The following particular axiom set is from Kunen (1980). The axioms per se are expressed in the symbolism of first order logic. The associated English prose is only intended to aid the intuition.

All formulations of ZFC imply that at least one set exists. Kunen includes an axiom, in addition to the following, which directly asserts the existence of a set. Many authors require a nonempty domain of discourse as part of the semantics of the first-order logic in which ZFC is formalized. The axiom of infinity (below) also asserts that at least one set exists, as it begins with an existential quantifier.

1. Axiom of extensionality: Two sets are equal (are the same set) if they have the same elements.:forall x forall y [ forall z (z in x Leftrightarrow z in y) Rightarrow x = y] .The converse of this axiom follows from the substitution property of equality. If the background logic does not include equality "=", "x"="y" may be defined as abbreviating ∀"z" ["z"∈"x"↔"z"∈"y"] ∧ ∀"z" ["x"∈"z"↔"y"∈"z"] , [Hatcher (1982), p. 138, Def. 1.] in which case this axiom can be reformulated as forall x forall y [ forall z (z in x Leftrightarrow z in y) Rightarrow forall z (x in z Leftrightarrow y in z) ] — if "x" and "y" have the same elements, then they belong to the same sets (Fraenkel "et al." 1973).

2. Axiom of regularity (also called the "Axiom of foundation"): Every non-empty set "x" contains a member "y" such that "x" and "y" are disjoint sets.:forall x [ exists y ( y in x) Rightarrow exists y ( y in x land lnot exists z (z in y land z in x))] .

3. Axiom schema of specification (also called the axiom schema of "separation" or of "restricted comprehension"): If "z" is a set, and phi! is any property which may characterize the elements "x" of "z", then there is a subset "y" of "z" containing those "x" in "z" which satisfy the property. The "restriction" to "z" is necessary to avoid Russell's paradox and its variants. More formally, let phi! be any formula in the language of ZFC with free variables among x,z,w_1,ldots,w_n!. So "y" is not free in phi!. Then::forall z forall w_1 ldots w_n exists y forall x [x in y Leftrightarrow ( x in z land phi )] .This axiom is part of Z, but can be redundant in ZF, in that it may follow from the axiom schema of replacement, with (as here) or without the axiom of the empty set. [See [http://us.metamath.org/mpegif/axsep.html here] for a Metamath derivation of a version of the separation schema from a version of the replacement schema.]

The axiom of specification can be used to prove the existence of the empty set, denoted varnothing, once the existence of at least one set is established (see above). A common way to do this is to use an instance of specification for a property which all sets do not have. For example, if "w" is a set which already exists, the empty set can be constructed as:varnothing = {u in w mid (u in u) land lnot (u in u) }. If the background logic includes equality, it is also possible to define the empty set as :varnothing = {u in w mid lnot (u = u) }. Thus the axiom of the empty set is implied by the nine axioms presented here. The axiom of extensionality implies the empty set is unique, if it exists. It is common to make a definitional extension that adds the symbol varnothing to the language of ZFC.

4. Axiom of pairing: If "x" and "y" are sets, then there exists a set which contains "x" and "y" as elements.:forall x forall y exist z (x in z land y in z).This axiom is part of Z, but is redundant in ZF because it follows from the axiom schema of replacement applied to any two-member set. The existence of such a set is assured by either the axiom of infinity, or by the axiom of the power set applied twice to the empty set.

5. Axiom of union: For any set mathcal{F} there is a set "A" containing every set that is a member of some member of mathcal{F}.:forall mathcal{F} ,exists A , forall Y, forall x (x in Y land Y in mathcal{F} Rightarrow x in A).

6. Axiom schema of collection: Let phi ! be any formula in the language of ZFC whose free variables are among x,y,A,w_1,ldots,w_n !. So "B" is not free in phi !. exists ! y is a quantifier binding "y", meaning that exactly one y! exists, up to equality. Then::forall A,forall w_1,ldots,w_n [ ( forall x in A exists ! y phi ) Rightarrow exists B forall x in A exists y in B phi] .Less formally, this axiom states that if the domain of a function "f" is a set, and "f"("x") is a set for any "x" in that domain, then the range of "f" is a subclass of a set, subject to a restriction needed to avoid paradoxes.

7. Axiom of infinity: Let S(x)! abbreviate x cup {x} !, where x ! is some set. Then there exists a set "X" such that the empty set varnothing is a member of "X" and, whenever a set "y" is a member of "X", then S(y)! is also a member of "X". :exist X left [varnothing in X and forall y (y in X Rightarrow S(y) in X) ight ] .More colloquially, there exists a set "X" having infinitely many members. The minimal set "X" satisfying the axiom of infinity is the von Neumann ordinal ω.

8. Axiom of power set: Let z subseteq x abbreviate forall q (q in z Rightarrow q in x). For any set "x", there is a set "y" which is a superset of the power set of "x". The power set of "x" is the class whose members are every possible subset of "x".:forall x exists y forall z [z subseteq x Rightarrow z in y] .

Alternative forms of axioms 1–8 are often encountered, some of which are listed in Jech (2003). Some ZF axiomatizations include an axiom asserting that the empty set exists. The axioms of pairing, union, replacement, and power set are often stated so that the members of the set "x" whose existence is being asserted, are just those sets which the axiom asserts "x" must contain.

9. Well-ordering theorem: For any set "X", there is a binary relation "R" which well-orders "X". This means "R" is a linear order on "X" such that every nonempty subset of "X" has a member which is minimal under "R".:forall X exists R ( R ;mbox{well-orders}; X).

Given axioms 1-8, there are many statements provably equivalent to axiom 9, the best known of which is the axiom of choice (AC), which goes as follows. Let "X" be a set whose members are all non-empty. Then there exists a function "f", called a "choice function," whose domain is "X", and whose range is a set, called the "choice set," each member of which is a single member of each member of "X". Since the existence of a choice function when "X" is a finite set is easily proved from axioms 1-8, AC only matters for certain infinite sets. AC is characterized as nonconstructive because it asserts the existence of a choice set but says nothing about how the choice set is to be "constructed." Much research has sought to characterize the definability (or lack thereof) of certain sets whose existence AC asserts.

Metamathematics

The axiom schemata of replacement and separation each contain infinitely many instances. Montague (1961) included a result first proved in his 1957 Ph.D. thesis: if ZFC is consistent, it is impossible to axiomatize ZFC using only finitely many axioms. On the other hand, Von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel set theory (NBG) can be finitely axiomatized. The ontology of NBG includes proper classes as well as sets; a set is any class that can be a member of another class. NBG and ZFC are equivalent set theories in the sense that any theorem not mentioning classes and provable in one theory can be proved in the other.

Gödel's second incompleteness theorem says that no recursively axiomatizable system that can interpret Robinson arithmetic can prove its own consistency. Moreover, Robinson arithmetic can be interpreted in general set theory, a small fragment of ZFC. Hence the consistency of ZFC cannot be proved within ZFC itself (unless it is actually inconsistent). Thus, to the extent that ZFC is identified with ordinary mathematics, the consistency of ZFC cannot be demonstrated in ordinary mathematics. The consistency of ZFC does follow from the existence of a weakly inaccessible cardinal, which is unprovable in ZFC if ZFC is consistent. Nevertheless, it is unlikely that ZFC harbors an unsuspected contradiction; if ZFC were inconsistent, it is widely believed that that fact would have been uncovered by now. This much is certain — ZFC is immune to the classic paradoxes of naive set theory: Russell's paradox, the Burali-Forti paradox, and Cantor's paradox.

Abian and LaMacchia (1978), using simple models, prove consistent the theory including the axioms of extensionality, union, powerset, replacement, and choice. They then proved that each of the axioms of extensionality, replacement, and power set is independent of the four remaining axioms in this set. If this five axiom set is augmented with the axiom of infinity, each of the axioms of union, choice, and infinity is independent of the five remaining axioms. Because non-well-founded set theory is a model of ZFC without the axiom of regularity, that axiom is independent of the other ZFC axioms.

One piece of evidence bearing on ZFC as a foundation of mathematics is Metamath, an ongoing web-based project that seeks to derive much of contemporary mathematics from the ZFC axioms, first order logic, and a host of definitions, with all proofs verified by machine. As of early 2008, the Metamath database includes about 8000 proved theorems. This project can be seen as being in the same spirit as Bertrand Russell's "Principia Mathematica", except grounded in logical and nonlogical axioms that benefit from nearly a century of subsequent research.

ZFC does not prove the existence of the inaccessible cardinals required by category theory. Huge sets of this nature are possible if ZF is augmented with Tarski's axiom (Tarski 1939). Assuming that axiom turns the axioms of infinity and choice (7 and 9 above) into theorems. Tarski's axiom is not a trivial affair, as it contains 7 existential quantifiers and 23 atomic formulas. [ [http://us.metamath.org/mpegif/grothprim.html Metamath version] of Tarski's axiom, expressed using only the primitives membership and identity. With the help of 4 defined notions, this axiom can be recast [http://us.metamath.org/mpegif/axgroth2.html more concisely] so as to require merely 2 existential quantifiers and 10 atomic formulas.]

Independence in ZFC

Many important statements are independent of ZFC (see list of statements undecidable in ZFC). The independence is usually proved by forcing, whereby it is shown that every countable transitive model of ZFC (sometimes augmented with large cardinal axioms) can be expanded to satisfy the statement in question. The negation of the statement is then shown to satisfy a different expansion. An independence proof by forcing automatically proves independence from arithmetical statements, other concrete statements, and large cardinal axioms. Some statements independent of ZFC can be proven to hold in particular inner models, such as in the constructible universe. However, some statements that are true about constructible sets are not consistent with hypothesised large cardinal axioms.

Forcing proves that the following statements are independent of ZFC:
*Continuum hypothesis
*Diamond principle
*Suslin hypothesis
*Kurepa hypothesis
*Martin's axiom (which is not a ZFC axiom)
*Axiom of Constructibility (V=L) (which is also not a ZFC axiom).

Remarks:
*The consistency of V=L is provable by inner models but not forcing: every model of ZF can be trimmed to become a model of ZFC+V=L.
*The Diamond Principle implies the Continuum Hypothesis and the negation of the Suslin Hypothesis.
*Martin's axiom plus the negation of the Continuum Hypothesis implies the Suslin Hypothesis.
*The constructible universe satisfies the Generalized Continuum Hypothesis, the Diamond Principle, Martin's Axiom and the Kurepa Hypothesis.

A variation on the method of forcing can also be used to demonstrate the consistency and unprovability of the axiom of choice, i.e., that the axiom of choice is independent of ZF. The consistency of choice can be (relatively) easily verified by proving that the inner model L satisfies choice. (Thus every model of ZF contains a submodel of ZFC, so that Con(ZF) implies Con(ZFC).) Since forcing preserves choice, we cannot directly produce a model contradicting choice from a model satisfying choice. However, we can use forcing to create a model which contains a suitable submodel, namely one satisfying ZF but not C.

Another method of proving independence results, one owing nothing to forcing, is based on Gödel's second incompleteness theorem. This approach employs the statement whose independence is being examined, to prove the existence of a set model of ZFC, in which case Con(ZFC) is true. Since ZFC satisfies the conditions of Gödel's second theorem, the consistency of ZFC is unprovable in ZFC. Hence no statement allowing such a proof can be proved in ZFC. This method can prove that the existence of large cardinals is not provable in ZFC, but cannot prove that assuming such cardinals, given ZFC, is free of contradiction.

Criticisms

:"For criticism of set theory in general, see Objections to set theory"

ZFC has been criticized both for being excessively strong and for being excessively weak, as well as for its failure to capture objects such as proper classes and the universal set.

Many mathematical theorems can be proven in much weaker systems than ZFC, such as Peano arithmetic and second order arithmetic (as explored by the program of reverse mathematics). Saunders Mac Lane and Solomon Feferman have both made this point. Some of "mainstream mathematics" (mathematics not directly connected with axiomatic set theory) is beyond Peano arithmetic and second order arithmetic, but still, all such mathematics can be carried out ZC (Zermelo set theory with choice), another theory weaker than ZFC. Much of the power of ZFC, including the axiom of regularity and the axiom schema of replacement, is included primarily to facilitate the study of the set theory itself.

On the other hand, among axiomatic set theories, ZFC is comparatively weak. Unlike New Foundations, ZFC does not admit the existence of a universal set. Hence the universe of sets under ZFC is not closed under the elementary operations of the algebra of sets. Unlike von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel set theory and Morse–Kelley set theory (MK), ZFC does not admit the existence of proper classes. These ontological restrictions are required for ZFC to avoid Russell's paradox, but critics argue these restrictions make the ZFC axioms fail to capture the informal concept of "set". A further comparative weakness of ZFC is that the axiom of choice included in ZFC is weaker than the axiom of global choice included in MK.

There are numerous mathematical statements undecidable in ZFC. These include the continuum hypothesis, the Whitehead problem, and the Normal Moore space conjecture. Some of these conjectures are provable with the addition of axioms such as Martin's axiom, large cardinal axioms, or the axiom of determinacy to ZFC. The Mizar system has adopted Tarski-Grothendieck set theory instead of ZFC so that proofs involving Grothendieck universes (encountered in category theory and algebraic geometry) can be formalized.

See also

* Axiomatic set theory
* List of statements undecidable in ZFC
* Metamath
* Non-well-founded set theory
* "Principia Mathematica"
* Set theory
* Von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel set theory
* Z notation
* Zermelo set theory

Notes

References

*Alexander Abian, 1965. "The Theory of Sets and Transfinite Arithmetic". W B Saunders.
*-------- and LaMacchia, Samuel, 1978, " [http://projecteuclid.org/DPubS/Repository/1.0/Disseminate?view=body&id=pdf_1&handle=euclid.ndjfl/1093888220 On the Consistency and Independence of Some Set-Theoretical Axioms,] " "Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic" 19: 155-58.
*Keith Devlin, 1996 (1984). "The Joy of Sets". Springer.
*Abraham Fraenkel, Yehoshua Bar-Hillel, and Azriel Levy, 1973 (1958). "Foundations of Set Theory". North Holland. Fraenkel's final word on ZF and ZFC.
*Hatcher, William, 1982 (1968). "The Logical Foundations of Mathematics". Pergamon.
*Thomas Jech, 2003. "Set Theory: The Third Millennium Edition, Revised and Expanded". Springer. ISBN 3-540-44085-2.
*Kenneth Kunen, 1980. "Set Theory: An Introduction to Independence Proofs". Elsevier. ISBN 0-444-86839-9.
*Richard Montague, 1961, "Semantic closure and non-finite axiomatizability" in "Infinistic Methods". London: Pergamon: 45-69.
*Patrick Suppes, 1972 (1960). "Axiomatic Set Theory". Dover reprint. Includes many theorems.
*Gaisi Takeuti and Zaring, W M, 1971. "Introduction to Axiomatic Set Theory". Springer Verlag.
*Alfred Tarski, 1939, "On well-ordered subsets of any set,", "Fundamenta Mathematicae" 32: 176-83.
*Tiles, Mary, 2004 (1989). "The Philosophy of Set Theory". Dover reprint. Weak on metatheory; the author is not a mathematician.
*Tourlakis, George, 2003. "Lectures in Logic and Set Theory, Vol. 2". Cambridge Univ. Press.
*Jean van Heijenoort, 1967. "From Frege to Godel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879-1931". Harvard Univ. Press. Includes annotated English translations of the classic articles by Zermelo, Fraenkel, and Skolem bearing on ZFC.

External links

* Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy articles by Thomas Jech:
** [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/set-theory/ Set Theory] ;
** [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/set-theory/ZF.html Axioms of Zermelo-Fraenkel Set Theory] .
* [http://us.metamath.org/mpegif/mmset.html#staxioms Metamath version of the ZFC axioms] — A concise and nonredundant axiomatization. The background first order logic is defined especially to facilitate machine verification of proofs.
*


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Поможем сделать НИР

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory — The first rigorous axiomatization of set theory was presented by Ernst Zermelo (1871–1953) in 1908, and its development by A. A. Fraenkel (1891–1965), adding the axiom of replacement, is known as ZF. If the axiom of choice is added it is known as …   Philosophy dictionary

  • Zermelo set theory — Zermelo set theory, as set out in an important paper in 1908 by Ernst Zermelo, is the ancestor of modern set theory. It bears certain differences from its descendants, which are not always understood, and are frequently misquoted. This article… …   Wikipedia

  • Set theory — This article is about the branch of mathematics. For musical set theory, see Set theory (music). A Venn diagram illustrating the intersection of two sets. Set theory is the branch of mathematics that studies sets, which are collections of objects …   Wikipedia

  • set theory — the branch of mathematics that deals with relations between sets. [1940 45] * * * Branch of mathematics that deals with the properties of sets. It is most valuable as applied to other areas of mathematics, which borrow from and adapt its… …   Universalium

  • Morse–Kelley set theory — In the foundation of mathematics, Morse–Kelley set theory (MK) or Kelley–Morse set theory (KM) is a first order axiomatic set theory that is closely related to von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel set theory (NBG). While von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel set theory …   Wikipedia

  • Constructive set theory — is an approach to mathematical constructivism following the program of axiomatic set theory. That is, it uses the usual first order language of classical set theory, and although of course the logic is constructive, there is no explicit use of… …   Wikipedia

  • List of set theory topics — Logic portal Set theory portal …   Wikipedia

  • Naive set theory — This article is about the mathematical topic. For the book of the same name, see Naive Set Theory (book). Naive set theory is one of several theories of sets used in the discussion of the foundations of mathematics.[1] The informal content of… …   Wikipedia

  • Quasi-set theory — is a formal mathematical theory of collections of indistinguishable objects, mainly motivated by the assumption that certain objects treated in quantum physics are indistinguishable. Quasi set theory is closely related to, yet distinct from,… …   Wikipedia

  • Naive Set Theory (book) — See also naive set theory for the mathematical topic. Naive Set Theory is a mathematics textbook by Paul Halmos originally published in 1960. This book is an undergraduate introduction to not very naive set theory. It is still considered by many… …   Wikipedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”