Raven paradox

Raven paradox

The Raven paradox, also known as Hempel's paradox or Hempel's ravens is a paradox proposed by the German logician Carl Gustav Hempel in the 1940s to illustrate a problem where inductive logic violates intuition. It reveals the problem of induction.

The paradox

Hempel describes the paradox in terms of the hypothesis [Hempel, CG (1945) Studies in the Logic of Confirmation I. Mind Vol 54, No. 213 p.1 [http://www.jstor.org/sici?sici=0026-4423(194501)2%3A54%3A213%3C1%3ASITLOC%3E2.0.CO%3B2-0 JSTOR] ] [Hempel, CG (1945) Studies in the Logic of Confirmation II. Mind Vol 54, No. 214 p.97 [http://www.jstor.org/sici?sici=0026-4423(194504)2%3A54%3A214%3C97%3ASITLOC%3E2.0.CO%3B2-M JSTOR] ] : : (1) "All ravens are black".

In strict logical terms, via the Law of Implication, this statement is equivalent to:: (2) "Everything that is not black is not a raven."

It should be clear that in all circumstances where (2) is true, (1) is also true; and likewise, in all circumstances where (2) is false (i.e. if we imagine a world in which something that was not black, yet was a raven, existed), (1) is also false. This establishes logical equivalence.

Given a general statement such as "all ravens are black", we would generally consider a form of the same statement that refers to a specific observable instance of the general class to constitute evidence for that general statement. For example,: (3) "Nevermore, my pet raven, is black."is clearly evidence supporting the hypothesis that "all ravens are black".

The paradox arises when this same process is applied to statement (2). On sighting a green apple, we can observe:: (4) "This green (and thus not black) thing is an apple (and thus not a raven)."By the same reasoning, this statement is evidence that (2) "everything that is not black is not a raven." But since (as above) this statement is logically equivalent to (1) "all ravens are black", it follows that the sight of a green apple offers evidence that all ravens are black.

Proposed Resolutions

Two apparently reasonable premises:

: The Equivalence Condition (EC): If a proposition, X, provides evidence in favor of another proposition Y, then X also provides evidence in favor of any proposition which is logically equivalent to Y.

and

: Nicod's Criterion (NC): A proposition of the form "All P are Q" is supported by the observation of a particular P which is Q.

can be combined to reach the paradoxical conclusion:

: (PC): The observation of a green apple provides evidence that all ravens are black.

A resolution to the paradox must therefore either accept (PC) or reject(EC) or reject (NC). A satisfactory resolution should also explain"why" there naively appears to be a paradox. Solutions whichaccept the paradoxical conclusion can do this by presenting aproposition which we intuitively know to be false but whichis easily confused with (PC), while solutions which reject (EC)or (NC) should present a proposition which we intuitively knowto be true but which is easily confused with (EC) or (NC) [Maher, P(1999) Inductive Logic and the Ravens Paradox, Philosphoy of Science,66, p.50 [http://www.jstor.org/sici?sici=0031-8248(199903)66%3A1%3C50%3AILATRP%3E2.0.CO%3B2-9 JSTOR] ] .

Approaches which Accept the Paradoxical Conclusion

Hempel's Resolution

Hempel himself accepted the paradoxical conclusion, arguing thatthe reason the result appears paradoxical is because we possessprior information without which the observation of a non-blacknon-raven would indeed provide evidence that all ravens are black.

He illustrates this with the example of the generalization "All sodiumsalts burn yellow", and asks us to consider the observation which occurswhen somebody holds a piece of pure ice in a colorless flame which doesnot turn yellow.

:This result would confirm the assertion, "Whatever does not burn yellow is no sodium salt", and consequently, by virtue of the equivalence condition, it would confirm the original formulation. Why does this impress us as paradoxical? The reason becomes clear when we compare the previous situation with the case of an experiment where an object whose chemical constitution is as yet unknown to us is held into a flame and fails to turn it yellow, and where subsequent analysis reveals it to contain no sodium salt. This outcome, we should no doubt agree, is what was to be expected on the basis of the hypothesis ... thus the data here obtained constitute confirming evidence for the hypothesis.

: In the seemingly paradoxical cases of confirmation, we are often not actually judging the relation of the given evidence, E alone to the hypothesis H ... we tacitly introduce a comparison of H with a body of evidence which consists of E in conjunction with an additional amount of information which we happen to have at our disposal; in our illustration, this information includes the knowledge (1) that the substance used in the experiment is ice, and (2) that ice contains no sodium salt. If we assume this additional information as given, then, of course, the outcome of the experiment can add no strength to the hypothesis under consideration. But if we are careful to avoid this tacit reference to additional knowledge ... the paradoxes vanish. [Hempel, CG (1945) Studies in the Logic of Confirmation I. Mind Vol 54, No. 213 p.1 [http://www.jstor.org/sici?sici=0026-4423(194501)2%3A54%3A213%3C1%3ASITLOC%3E2.0.CO%3B2-0 JSTOR] ]

The Standard Bayesian Solution

One of the most popular proposed resolutions is to accept theconclusion that the observation of a green apple providesevidence that all ravens are black but to argue that theamount of confirmation provided is very small, due tothe large discrepancy between the number of ravens andthe number of non-black objects. According to this resolution,the conclusion appears paradoxical because we intuitively estimate theamount of evidence provided by the observation of a green appleto be zero, when it is in fact non-zero but very small.

I J Good's presentation of thisargument in 1960 [ Good, IJ (1960) The Paradox of Confirmation, "The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science", Vol. 11, No. 42, 145-149 [http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0007-0882%28196008%2911%3A42%3C145%3ATPOC%3E2.0.CO%3B2-5 JSTOR] ] is perhaps the best known, and variations of the argument have been popular eversince [Fitelson, B and Hawthorne, J (2006) How Bayesian Confirmation Theory Handles the Paradox of the Ravens, in Probability in Science, Chicago: Open Court [http://fitelson.org/ravens.pdf Link] ] although it had been presented in 1958 [Alexander, HG (1958) The Paradoxes of Confirmation, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 9, No. 35, P. 227 [http://www.jstor.org/stable/685654?origin=JSTOR-pdf JSTOR] ] andearly forms of the argument appeared as early as 1940 [Hosaisson-Lindenbaum, J (1940) On Confirmation, The Journal of Symbolic Logic, Vol. 5, No. 4, p. 133 [http://www.jstor.org/action/showArticle?doi=10.2307/2268173 JSTOR] ] .

Good's argument involves calculating the weight of evidence provided by the observation of a black raven or a white shoe in favor of the hypothesis that all the ravens in a collection of objects are black. The weight of evidence is the logarithm of the Bayes factor, which in this case is simply the factor by which the odds of the hypothesis changes when the observation is made. The argument goes as follows:

Quote|... suppose that there are N objects that might be seen at any moment, of which r are ravens and b are black, and that the N objects each have probability 1/N of being seen. Let H_i be the hypothesis that there are i non-black ravens, and suppose that the hypotheses H_1, H_2, ... ,H_r are initially equiprobable. Then, if we happen to see a black raven, the Bayes factor in favour of H_0 is

:frac{r}{N} Bigg / average Bigg ( frac{r-1}{N},frac{r-2}{N}, ... ,frac{1}{N}Bigg ) = frac{2r}{r-1}

i.e. about 2 if the number of ravens in existence is known to be large. But the factor if we see a white shoe is only

:frac{N-b}{N} Bigg / average Bigg ( frac{N-b-1}{N},frac{N-b-2}{N}, ... ,max(0,frac{N-b-r}{N})Bigg )

: = frac{N-b}{max(N-b-r/2 -1/2 , (N-b-1)/2)}

:and this exceeds unity by only about r/(2N-2b) if N-b is large compared to r. Thus the weight of evidence provided by the sight of a white shoe is positive, but is small if the number of ravens is known to be small compared to the number of non-black objects. [Note: Good used "crow" instead of "raven", but "raven" has been used here throughout for consistency.]

Many of the proponents of this resolution and variants of it have been advocates of Bayesian probability, and it is now commonly called the Bayesian Solution, although, as Chihara [Chihara, (1981) Some Problems for Bayesian Confirmation Theory, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 38, No. 4 [http://bjps.oxfordjournals.org/cgi/reprint/38/4/551 LINK] ] observes, "there is no such thing as "the" Bayesian solution. Thereare many different `solutions' that Bayesians have put forwardusing Bayesian techniques." Noteworthy approaches using Bayesiantechniques include Earman, [Earman, 1992 Bayes or Bust? A Critical Examination of Bayesian Confirmation Theory, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.] , Eells [Eells, 1982 Rational Decision and Causality. New York: Cambridge University Press] , Gibson [Gibson, 1969 On Ravens and Relevance and a Likelihood Solution of the Paradox of Confirmation, [http://www.jstor.org/stable/686720 LINK] ] , Hosaisson-Lindenbaum [Hosaisson-Lindenbaum 1940] , Howson and Urbach [Howson, Urbach, 1993 Scientific Reasoning: The Bayesian Approach, Open Court Publishing Company] , Mackie [Mackie, 1963 The Paradox of Confirmation, Brit. J. Phil. Sci. Vol. 13, No. 52, p. 265 [http://bjps.oxfordjournals.org/cgi/content/citation/XIII/52/265 LINK] ] andHintikka [Hintikka, 1969] , who claims that his approach is "more Bayesian than the so-called `Bayesian solution' of the sameparadox." Bayesian approaches which make use of Carnap's theory of inductive inference includeHumburg [Humburg 1986, The solution of Hempel's raven paradox in Rudolf Carnap's system of inductive logic, Erkenntnis, Vol. 24, No. 1, pp] , Maher, [Maher 1999] and Fitelson et al. [Fitelson 2006] . Vranas [Vranas (2002) Hempel`s Raven Paradox: A Lacuna in the Standard Bayesian Solution [http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/archive/00000688/00/hempelacuna.doc LINK] ] introducedthe term "Standard Bayesian Solution" to avoid confusion.

The Carnapian Approach

Maher [Maher, 1999] accepts the paradoxical conclusion, and refines it:

Quote|A non-raven (of whatever color) confirms that all ravens are black because

:(i) the information that this object is not a raven removes the possibility that this object is a counterexample to the generalization, and

:(ii) it reduces the probability that unobserved objects are ravens, thereby reducing the probability that they are counterexamples to the generalization.

In order to reach (ii), he appeals to Carnap's theory of inductiveprobability, which is (from the Bayesian point of view) a way of assigningprior probabilities which naturally implements induction. According toCarnap's theory, the posterior probability, P(Fa|E), that an object, a, will have a predicate, F, after the evidence E has been observed, is:

:P(Fa|E) = frac{n_F+lambda P(Fa)}{n+lambda}

where P(Fa) is the initial probability that a hasthe predicate F; n is the number of objects which have been examined (according to the available evidence E); n_F is the number of examined objects which turned out to have the predicate F, and lambda is a constant which measures resistance to generalization.

If lambda is close to zero, P(Fa|E) will be veryclose to one after a single observation of an object which turned out to have the predicate F,while if lambda is much larger than n, P(Fa|E) will be very close to P(Fa) regardless of the fraction of observedobjects which had the predicate F.

Using this Carnapian approach, Maher identifies a proposition which we intuitively (and correctly) know to be false, but which we easily confuse with the paradoxical conclusion. The proposition in questionis the proposition that observing non-ravens tells us about the color of ravens.While this is intuitively false and is also false according to Carnap's theoryof induction, observing non-ravens (according to that same theory) causes usto reduce our estimate of the total number of ravens, and thereby reducesthe estimated number of possible counterexamples to the rule that all ravensare black.

Hence, from the Bayesian-Carnapian point of view, the observation of a non-ravendoes not tell us anything about the color of ravens, but it tells us aboutthe prevalence of ravens, and supports "All ravens are black" by reducingour estimate of the number of ravens which might not be black.

The Role of Background Knowledge

Much of the discussion of the paradox in general and the Bayesian approachin particular has centred on the relevance of background knowledge.Surprisingly, Maher [ Maher, 1999] shows that, for a large class of possible configurations of background knowledge, the observation of a non-black non-raven provides "exactly the same" amount of confirmation as the observation of a black raven. The configurations of background knowledge which he considers are those which are provided by a "sample proposition", namely a proposition which is a conjunction of atomic propositions, each of which ascribes a single predicate to a single individual, with no two atomic propositions involving the same individual. Thus, a proposition of the form "A is a black raven and B is a white shoe" can be considered a sample proposition by taking "black raven" and "white shoe" to be predicates.

Maher's proof appears to contradict the result of the Bayesian argument, which was that the observation of a non-black non-raven provides much less evidence than the observation of a black raven. The reason is that the background knowledge which Good and others use can not be expressed in the form of a sample proposition - in particular, variants of the standard Bayesian approach often suppose (as Good did in the argument quoted above) that the total numbers of ravens, non-black objects and/or the total number of objects, are known quantities. Maher comments that, "The reason we think there are more non-black things than ravens is because that has been true of the things we have observed to date. Evidence of this kind can be represented by a sample proposition. But ... given any sample proposition as background evidence, a non-black non-raven confirms A just as strongly as a black raven does ... Thus my analysis suggests that this response to the paradox [i.e. the Standard Bayesian one] cannot be correct."

Fitelson et al. [ Fitelson, 2006] examined the conditions under which the observation of a non-black non-raven provides less evidence than the observationof a black raven. They show that, if a is an object selected at random, Ba is the proposition that the object is black, and Ra is the proposition that the object is a raven, then the condition:

:frac{P(overline{Ba}|overline{H})}{P(Ra|overline{H})} - P(overline{Ba}|Raoverline{H}) geq P(Ba|Raoverline{H}) frac{P(overline{Ba}|H)}{P(Ra|H)}

is sufficient for the observation of a non-black non-raven to provide lessevidence than the observation of a black raven. Here, a line over aproposition indicates the logical negation of that proposition.

This condition does not tell us "how large" the differencein the evidence provided is, but a later calculation in the same papershows that the weight of evidence provided by a black raven exceedsthat provided by a non-black non-raven by about -log P(Ba|Raoverline{H}). This is equal to the amount ofadditional information (in bits, if the base of the logarithm is 2) which is provided when a raven of unknown color is discovered to be black, given the hypothesis that not all ravens are black.

Fitelson et al. [ Fitelson, 2006] explain that:

:Under normal circumstances, p=P(Ba|Raoverline{H}) may be somewhere around 0.9 or 0.95; so 1/p is somewhere around 1.11 or 1.05. Thus, it may appear that a single instance of a black raven does not yield much more support than would a non-black non-raven. However, under plausible conditions it can be shown that a sequence of n instances (i.e. of n black ravens, as compared to n non-black non-ravens) yields a ratio of likelihood ratios on the order of (1/p)^n, which blows up significantly for large n.

The authors point out that their analysis is completelyconsistent with the supposition that a non-black non-ravenprovides an extremely small amount of evidence althoughthey do not attempt to prove it; they merely calculate the difference betweenthe amount of evidence that a black raven provides and the amount of evidence that a non-black non-raven provides.

Rejecting Nicod's Criterion

The Red Herring

Good [Good 1967, The White Shoe is a Red Herring, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 17, No. 4, p322 [http://www.jstor.org/stable/686774 JSTOR] ] gives an exampleof background knowledge with respect to which the observation of a black raven"decreases" the probability that all ravens are black:

:Suppose that we know we are in one or other of two worlds, and the hypothesis, H, under consideration is that all the ravens in our world are black. We know in advance that in one world there are a hundred black ravens, no non-black ravens, and a million other birds; and that in the other world there are a thousand black ravens, one white raven, and a million other birds. A bird is selected equiprobably at random from all the birds in our world. It turns out to be a black raven. This is strong evidence ... that we are in the second world, wherein not all ravens are black.

Good concludes that the white shoe is a "red herring": Sometimes even a black ravencan constitute evidence "against" the hypothesis that all ravens are black, sothe fact that the observation of a white shoe can support it is not surprising and not worth attention. Nicod's criterion is false, according to Good, and so theparadoxical conclusion does not follow.

Hempel rejected this as a solution to the paradox, insisting that the proposition 'c is a raven and is black' must be considered "by itself and without reference to any other information", and pointing out that it "... was emphasized in section 5.2(b) of my article in Mind ... that the very appearance of paradoxicality in cases like that of the white shoe results in part from a failure to observe this maxim." [Hempel 1967, The White Shoe - No Red Herring, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 18, No. 3, p. 239 [http://www.jstor.org/stable/686596 JSTOR] ]

The question which then arises is whether the paradox is to be understood in the context of absolutely no background information (as Hempel suggests), or in the context of the background information which we actually possess regarding ravens and black objects, or with regard to all possible configurations of background information. Good had shown that, for some configurations of background knowledge, Nicod's criterionis false (provided that we are willing to equate "inductively support" with "increase the probability of" - see below). The possibility remained that, withrespect to our actual configuration of knowledge, which is very different fromGood's example, Nicod's criterion might still be true and so we could stillreach the paradoxical conclusion. Hempel, on the other hand, insists thatit is our background knowledge itself which is the red herring, and thatwe should consider induction with respect to a condition of perfect ignorance.

Good's Baby

In his proposed resolution, Maher implicitly made use of the fact that the proposition "All ravens are black" is highly probable when it is highly probable that there are no ravens. Good had used this fact before to respondto Hempel's insistence that Nicod's criterion was to be understood to holdin the absence of background information [Good 1968, The White Shoe qua Red Herring is Pink, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 19, No. 2, p. 156 [http://www.jstor.org/stable/686795 JSTOR] ] :

:...imagine an infinitely intelligent newborn baby having built-in neural circuits enabling him to deal with formal logic, English syntax, and subjective probability. He might now argue, after defining a raven in detail, that it is extremely unlikely that there are any ravens, and therefore it is extremely likely that all ravens are black, that is, that H is true. 'On the other hand', he goes on to argue, 'if there are ravens, then there is a reasonable chance that they are of a variety of colours. Therefore, if I were to discover that even a black raven exists I would consider H to be less probable than it was initially.'

This, according to Good, is as close as one can reasonably expect to get to a condition of perfect ignorance, and it appears that Nicod's condition is still false. Maher made Good's argument more precise by using Carnap's theory of inductionto formalize the notion that if there is one raven, then it is likelythat there are many [Maher 2004, Probability Captures the Logic of Scientific Confirmation [http://patrick.maher1.net/pctl.pdf LINK] ] .

Maher's argument considers a universe of exactly two objects, each of whichis very unlikely to be a raven (a one in a thousand chance) and reasonably unlikely to be black (a one in ten chance). Using Carnap's formula for induction,he finds that the probability that all ravens are black decreases from 0.9985to 0.8995 when it is discovered that one of the two objects is a black raven.

Maher concludes that not only is the paradoxical conclusion true, butthat Nicod's criterion is false in the absence of background knowledge(except for the knowledge that the number of objects in the universeis two and that ravens are less likely than black things).

Distinguished Predicates

Quine [Quine, WV (1969) Natural Kinds, in Ontological Relativity and other Essays. New York:Columbia university Press, p.114] argued that the solution to the paradoxlies in the recognition that certain predicates, which hecalled natural kinds, have a distinguished status with respectto induction. This can be illustrated with Nelson Goodman'sexample of the predicate grue. An object is grueif it is blue before (say) 2010 and green afterwards. Clearly, weexpect objects which were blue before 2010 to remain blue afterwards,but we do not expect the objects which were found to be grue before 2010 to be grue afterwards. Quine's explanation is that "blue" isa natural kind; a privileged predicate which can be used for induction,while "grue" is not a natural kind and using induction with it leadsto error.

This suggests a resolution to the paradox - Nicod's criterion istrue for natural kinds, such as "blue" and "black", but is falsefor artificially contrived predicates, such as "grue" or "non-raven".The paradox arises, according to this resolution, because we implicitlyinterpret Nicod's criterion as applying to all predicates when in factit only applies to natural kinds.

Another approach which favours specific predicates over others was taken by Hintikka [Hintikka, 1969] . Hintikka was motivatedto find a Bayesian approach to the paradox which did not make useof knowledge about the relative frequencies of ravens and black things.Arguments concerning relative frequencies, he contends, cannot always account for the perceived irrelevance of evidence consisting ofobservations of objects of type A for the purposes of learningabout objects of type not-A.

His argument can be illustrated by rephrasing the paradox usingpredicates other than "raven" and "black". For example, "All menare tall" is equivalent to "All short people are women", and soobserving that a randomly selected person is a short woman shouldprovide evidence that all men are tall. Despite the fact thatwe lack background knowledge to indicate that there are dramaticallyfewer men than short people, we still find ourselves inclined toreject the conclusion. Hintikka's example is: "... a generalizationlike 'no material bodies are infinitely divisible' seems to be completelyunaffected by questions concerning immaterial entities, independentlyof what one thinks of the relative frequencies of material andimmaterial entities in one's universe of discourse."

His solution is to introduce an "order" into the set of predicates. When the logical system is equipped with this order,it is possible to restrict the "scope" of a generalization such as "All ravens are black" so that it applies to ravens only and not to non-black things, since the order privileges ravens over non-black things. As he puts it:

:If we are justified in assuming that the scope of the generalization 'All ravens are black' can be restricted to ravens, then this means that we have some outside information which we can rely on concerning the factual situation. The paradox arises from the fact that this information, which colors our spontaneous view of the situation, is not incorporated in the usual treatments of the inductive situation. [Hintakka J. 1969, Inductive Independence and the Paradoxes of Confirmation [http://books.google.com/books?id=pWtPcRwuacAC&pg=PA24&lpg=PA24&ots=-1PKZt0Jbz&lr=&sig=EK2qqOZ6-cZR1P1ZKIsndgxttMs LINK] ]

Proposed Resolutions which Reject the Equivalence Condition

elective Confirmation

Scheffler and Goodman [Scheffler I, Goodman NJ, Selective Confirmation and the Ravens, Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 69, No. 3, 1972 [http://www.jstor.org/stable/2024647 JSTOR] ] took an approach to the paradox which incorporates
Karl Popper's view that scientific hypotheses are never really confirmed,only falsified.

The approach begins by noting that the observation of a black raven does not prove that "All ravens are black" but it falsifies the contrary hypothesis, "No ravens are black". A non-black non-raven, on the other hand, is consistent with both "All ravens are black" and with "No ravens are black". As the authors put it:

:... the statement that all ravens are black is not merely "satisfied" by evidence of a black raven but is "favored" by such evidence, since a black raven disconfirms the contrary statement that all ravens are not black, i.e. satisfies its denial. A black raven, in other words, satisfies the hypothesis "that all ravens are black rather than not:" it thus selectively confirms "that all ravens are black".

Selective confirmation violates the equivalence condition sincea black raven selectively confirms "All ravens are black" butnot "All non-black things are non-ravens".

Probabilistic or Non-Probabilistic Induction

Scheffler and Goodman's concept of selective confirmation isan example of an interpretation of "provides evidence in favor of" which does not coincide with "increase the probability of". This must be a general feature of all resolutions which reject theequivalence condition, since logically equivalent propositions mustalways have the same probability.

It is impossible for the observation of a black raven to increase the probability of the proposition"All ravens are black" without causing exactly the samechange to the probability that "All non-black things are non-ravens".If an observation inductively supports the former but not thelatter, then "inductively support" must refer to something otherthan changes in the probabilities of propositions. A possible loopholeis to interpret "All" as "Nearly all" - "Nearly all ravens are black"is not equivalent to "Nearly all non-black things are non-ravens", andthese propositions can have very different probabilities [Gaifman, H (1979) Subjective Probability, Natural Predicates and Hempel's Ravens, Erkenntnis, Vol. 14, p. 105 [http://www.springerlink.com/content/vw370x1531q54422/ Springer] ] .

This raises the broader question of the relation of probabilitytheory to inductive reasoning. Karl Popper argued that probability theory alone cannot account for induction. His argument involves splitting a hypothesis,H, into a part which is deductively entailed by theevidence, E, and another part. This can be done in twoways.

First, consider the splitting [Popper, K. Realism and the Aim of Science, Routlege, 1992, p. 325] :

:H=A and B E=B and C

where A, B and C areprobabilistically independent: P(A and B)=P(A)P(B) andso on. The condition which is necessary for such a splittingof H and E to be possible is P(H|E)>P(H), that is,that H is probabilistically supported by E.

Popper's observation is that the part, B, of Hwhich receives support from E actually follows deductivelyfrom E, while the part of H which does notfollow deductively from E receives no support at all fromE - that is, P(A|E)=P(A).

Second, the splitting [Popper K, Miller D, (1983) A Proof of the Impossibility of Inductive Probability, Nature, Vol. 302, p. 687 [http://www.nature.com/nature/journal/v302/n5910/abs/302687a0.html Link] ] :

:H=(H or E) and (H or overline{E})

separates H into (H or E), which asPopper says, "is the logically strongest part of H(or of the content of H) that follows [deductively] from E," and (H or overline{E}), which, he says, "contains all of H that goes beyond E."He continues:

:Does E, in this case, provide any support for the factor (H or overline{E}), which in the presence of E is alone needed to obtain H? The answer is: No. It never does. Indeed, E countersupports (H or overline{E}) unless either P(H|E)=1 or P(E)=1 (which are possibilities of no interest). ...

:This result is completely devastating to the inductive interpretation of the calculus of probability. All probabilistic support is purely deductive: that part of a hypothesis that is not deductively entailed by the evidence is always strongly countersupported by the evidence ... There is such a thing as probabilistic support; there might even be such a thing as inductive support (though we hardly think so). But the calculus of probability reveals that probabilistic support cannot be inductive support.

The Orthodox Approach

The orthodox Neyman-Pearson theoryof hypothesis testing considers how to decide whether to"accept" or "reject" a hypothesis, rather than whatprobability to assign to the hypothesis. From this point of view,the hypothesis that "All ravens are black" is not accepted"gradually", as its probability increases towards one when moreand more observations are made, but is accepted in a single action as the result of evaluating the data which has already been collected. As Neyman and Pearson put it:

:Without hoping to know whether each separate hypothesis is true or false, we may search for rules to govern our behaviour with regard to them, in following which we insure that, in the long run of experience, we shall not be too often wrong. [Neyman J, Pearson ES (1933) On the Problem of the Most Efficient Tests of Statistical Hypotheses, Phil. Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series A, Vol. 231, p289 [http://www.jstor.org/stable/91247 JSTOR] ]

According to this approach, it is not necessary to assign anyvalue to the probability of a "hypothesis", although one mustcertainly take into account the probability of the "data"given the hypothesis, or given a competing hypothesis, when decidingwhether to accept or to reject. The acceptance or rejection of a hypothesiscarries with it the risk of error.

This contrasts with the Bayesian approach, which requires that thehypothesis be assigned a prior probability, which is revised in the light of the observed data to obtain the final probability of thehypothesis. Within the Bayesian framework there is no risk of errorsince hypotheses are not accepted or rejected; instead they areassigned probabilities.

An analysis of the paradox from the orthodox point of view has beenperformed, and leads to, among other insights, a rejection of the equivalence condition:

:It seems obvious that one cannot both "accept" the hypothesis that all P's are Q and also reject the contrapositive, i.e. that all non-Q's are non-P. Yet it is easy to see that on the Neyman-Pearson theory of testing, a test of "All P's are Q" is "not" necessarily a test of "All non-Q's are non-P" or vice versa. A test of "All P's are Q" requires reference to some alternative statistical hypothesis of the form r of all P's are Q, 0, whereas a test of "All non-Q's are non-P" requires reference to some statistical alternative of the form r of all non-Q's are non-P, 0. But these two sets of possible alternatives are different ... Thus one could have a test of H without having a test of its contrapositive. [Giere, RN (1970) An Orthodox Statistical Resolution of the Paradox of Confirmation, Philosophy of Science, Vol. 37, No. 3, p.354 [http://www.jstor.org/stable/186464 JSTOR] ]

Rejecting Material Implication

The following propositions all imply one another: "Every object is either black ornot a raven", "Every Raven is black", and "Every non-black object is a non-raven."They are therefore, by definition, logically equivalent. However, the three propositions have different domains: the first proposition says something about "Every object", while the second says something about "Every raven".

The first proposition is the only one whose domain is unrestricted ("all objects"),so this is the only one which can be expressed in first order logic. It islogically equivalent to:

:forall x, Rx ightarrow Bx

and also to

::forall x, overline{Bx} ightarrow overline{Rx}

where ightarrow indicates the material conditional, accordingto which "If A then B" can be understood to mean "B or overline{A}".

It has been argued by several authors that material implication does not fullycapture the meaning of "If A then B" (see the paradoxes of material implication). "For every object, x, x is either black or not a raven" is "true" when there are no ravens. It is because of thisthat "All ravens are black" is regarded as true when there are no ravens. Furthermore, thearguments which Good and Maher used to criticize Nicod's criterion (see Good's Baby, above)relied on this fact - that "All ravens are black" is highly probable when it ishighly probable that there are no ravens.

Some approaches to the paradox have sought to find other ways of interpreting "If A then B" and "All A are B" which wouldeliminate the perceived equivalence between "All ravens are black" and "All non-blackthings are non-ravens."

One such approach involves introducing a many-valued logic according to which "If A then B" has the truth-value I, meaning "Indeterminate" or "Inappropriate" when A is false [Farrell RJ (1979) Material Implication, Confirmation and Counterfactuals [http://projecteuclid.org/DPubS/Repository/1.0/Disseminate?view=body&id=pdf_1&handle=euclid.ndjfl/1093882546 LINK] ] . In such a system, contraposition is not automatically allowed: "If A then B" is not equivalent to "If overline{B} then overline{A}". Consequently, "All ravens are black" is not equivalent to "All non-black things are non-ravens".

In this system, when contraposition occurs, the modality of the conditional involvedchanges from the indicative ("If that piece of butter "has been" heated to 32 C then it "has" melted") to the counterfactual ("If that piece of butter "had been" heated to 32 C then it "would have" melted"). According to this argument,this removes the alleged equivalence which is necessary to conclude that yellow cows can inform us about ravens:

:In proper grammatical usage, a contrapositive argument ought not to be stated entirely in the indicative. Thus:

::From the fact that if this match is scratched it will light, it follows that if it does not light it was not scratched.

:is awkward. We should say:

::From the fact that if this match is scratched it will light, it follows that if it "were" not to light it "would" not have been scratched. ...

:One might wonder what effect this interpretation of the Law of Contraposition has on Hempel's paradox of confirmation. "If a is a raven then a is black" is equivalent to "If a were not black then a would not be a raven". Therefore whatever confirms the latter should also, by the Equivalence Condition, confirm the former. True, but yellow cows still cannot figure into the confirmation of "All ravens are black" because, in science, confirmation is accomplished by prediction, and predictions are properly stated in the indicative mood. It is senseless to ask what confirms a counterfactual. [Farrell (1979)]

Differing Results of Accepting the Hypotheses

Several commentators have observed that the propositions "All ravens are black" and "All non-black things are non-ravens" suggest different procedures for testing the hypotheses. E.g. Good writes [Good (1960)] :

:As propositions the two statements are logically equivalent. But they have a different psychological effect on the experimenter. If he is asked to test whether all ravens are black he will look for a raven and then decide whether it is black. But if he is asked to test whether all non-black things are non-ravens he may look for a non-black object and then decide whether it is a raven.

More recently, it has been suggested that "All ravens are black" and "All non-black things are non-ravens" can have different effects when "accepted" [O'Flanagan (2008) Judgment [http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/archive/00003932/01/judgment6.pdf LINK] ] . The argument considers situations in which the total numbers or prevalences of ravens and black objects are unknown, but estimated. When the hypothesis "All ravens are black" is accepted,according to the argument, the estimated number of black objects increases, while theestimated number of ravens does not change.

It can be illustrated by considering the situation of two people who have identical information regarding ravens and black objects, and who have identical estimates of thenumbers of ravens and black objects. For concreteness, suppose that there are 100 objectsoverall, and, according to the information available to the people involved, each object is just as likely to be a non-raven as it is to be a raven, and just as likely to be black as it is to be non-black:

:P(Ra)=frac{1}{2} P(Ba)=frac{1}{2}

and the propositions Ra, Rb are independent for differentobjects a, b and so on. Then the estimated numberof ravens is 50; the estimated number of black things is 50; the estimatednumber of black ravens is 25, and the estimated number of non-black ravens(counterexamples to the hypotheses) is 25.

One of the people performs a statistical test (e.g. a Neyman-Pearson test or the comparison of the accumulated weight of evidence to a threshold) of the hypothesis that "All ravens are black", while the other tests the hypothesis that "All non-black objects are non-ravens". For simplicity, suppose that the evidence used for the test has nothing to do with the collection of 100 objects dealt with here. If the first person accepts the hypothesis that "All ravens are black" then, according to the argument, about 50 objects whose colors were previously in doubt (the ravens) are now thought to be black, while nothing different is thought about the remaining objects (the non-ravens). Consequently, he should estimate the number of black ravens at 50, the number of black non-ravens at 25 and the number of non-black non-ravens at 25. By specifying these changes, this argument "explicitly" restricts the domain of "All ravens are black" to ravens.

On the other hand, if the second person accepts the hypothesis that "All non-black objects are non-ravens", then the approximately 50 non-black objects about which it was uncertain whether each was a raven, will be thought to be non-ravens. At the same time, nothing different will be thought about the approximately 50 remaining objects (the black objects). Consequently, he should estimate the number of black ravens at 25, the number of black non-ravens at 25 and the number of non-black non-ravens at 50. According to this argument, since the two people disagree about their estimates after they have accepted the different hypotheses, accepting "All ravens are black" is not equivalent to accepting "All non-black things are non-ravens"; accepting the former means estimating more things to be black, while accepting the latter involves estimating more things to be non-ravens. Correspondingly, the argument goes, the former requires as evidence ravens which turn out to be black and the latter requires non-black things which turn out to be non-ravens [O'Flanagan (2008)] .

Existential Presuppositions

A number of authors have argued that propositions of the form "All A are B" presuppose that there are objects which are A [Strawson PF (1952) Introduction to Logical Theory, methuan & Co. London, John Wiley & Sons, New York] . This analysis has been applied to the raven paradox [Cohen Y (1987) Ravens and Relevance, Erkenntnis [http://www.springerlink.com/content/hnn2lutn1066xw47/fulltext.pdf LINK] ] :

:... H_1: "All ravens are black" and H_2: "All nonblack things are nonravens" are not "strictly equivalent" ... due to their different existential presuppositions. Moreover, although H_1 and H_2 describe the same regularity - the nonexistence of nonblack ravens - they have different logical forms. The two hypotheses have different senses and incorporate different procedures for testing the regularity they describe.

A modified logic can take account of existential presuppositions using the presuppositional operator, `*'. For example,

::forall x, *Rx ightarrow Bx

can denote "All ravens are black" while indicating that it is ravens and not non-black objects which are presupposed to exist in this example.

:... the logical form of each hypothesis distinguishes it with respect to its recommended type of supporting evidence: the possibly true substitution instances of each hypothesis relate to different types of objects. The fact that the two hypotheses incorporate different kinds of testing procedures is expressed in the formal language by prefixing the operator `*' to a different predicate. The presuppositional operator thus serves as a relevance operator as well. It is prefixed to the predicate `x is a raven' in H_1 because the objects relevant to the testing procedure incorporated in "All raven are black" include only ravens; it is prefixed to the predicate `x is nonblack', in H_2, because the objects relevant to the testing procedure incorporated in "All nonblack things are nonravens" include only nonblack things. ... Using Fregean terms: whenever their presuppositions hold, the two hypotheses have the same referent (truth-value), but different senses; that is, they express two different ways to determine that truth-value [Cohen (1987)]

=Notes=

References

* Franceschi, P. " [http://www.univ-corse.fr/~franceschi/HP(GB).html The Doomsday Argument and Hempel's Problem] ", English translation of a paper initially published in French in the Canadian Journal of Philosophy 29, 139-156, 1999, under the title "Comment l'Urne de Carter et Leslie se Déverse dans celle de Hempel"
* Hempel, C. G. "A Purely Syntactical Definition of Confirmation." J. Symb. Logic 8, 122-143, 1943.
* Hempel, C. G. "Studies in Logic and Confirmation." Mind 54, 1-26, 1945.
* Hempel, C. G. "Studies in Logic and Confirmation. II." Mind 54, 97-121, 1945.
* Hempel, C. G. "Studies in the Logic of Confirmation." In Marguerite H. Foster and [http://www.bu.edu/philo/faculty/martin.html Michael L. Martin] , eds. "Probability, Confirmation, and Simplicity". New York: Odyssey Press, 1966. 145-183.
* Whiteley, C. H. "Hempel's Paradoxes of Confirmation." Mind 55, 156-158, 1945.

External links

* [http://www.mathacademy.com/pr/prime/articles/paradox_raven/index.asp PRIME Encyclopedia]
* [http://www.logicalparadoxes.info/hempelsravens.html Hempel's Ravens, at Logical Paradoxes.Info]


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Поможем сделать НИР

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Raven (disambiguation) — Raven may refer to:Birds*Raven, a large black bird in the crow family ( Corvidae ) *Raven, often used in the Northern Hemisphere as a synonym for the Common Raven ( Corvus corax ) *Raven (mythology), a bird in mythology *Cultural depictions of… …   Wikipedia

  • Common Raven — For the German band named after this bird, see Corvus Corax (band). For the butterfly, see Papilio castor. Common Raven At Bodega Head State Park, USA …   Wikipedia

  • List of paradoxes — This is a list of paradoxes, grouped thematically. Note that many of the listed paradoxes have a clear resolution see Quine s Classification of Paradoxes.Logical, non mathematical* Paradox of entailment: Inconsistent premises always make an… …   Wikipedia

  • List of philosophy topics (R-Z) — RRaRabad Rabbinic law Rabbinic theology Francois Rabelais François Rabelais race racetrack paradox racism Gustav Radbruch Janet Radcliffe Richards Sarvepalli Radhakrishnan radical Aristotelianism radical behaviourism radical feminism radical… …   Wikipedia

  • Carl Gustav Hempel — Infobox Philosopher region = Western Philosophy era = 20th century philosophy color = #B0C4DE name = Carl Gustav Hempel birth = birth date|1905|01|08 Oranienburg, Germany death = death date|1997|11|09 Princeton, New Jersey school tradition =… …   Wikipedia

  • List of mathematics articles (R) — NOTOC R R. A. Fisher Lectureship Rabdology Rabin automaton Rabin signature algorithm Rabinovich Fabrikant equations Rabinowitsch trick Racah polynomials Racah W coefficient Racetrack (game) Racks and quandles Radar chart Rademacher complexity… …   Wikipedia

  • Парадокс воронов — (англ. Raven paradox), известный также как парадокс Гемпеля (нем. Hempels paradox) или вороны Гемпеля  логический парадокс, сформулированный немецким математиком Карлом Густавом Гемпелем в 1940 х годах, для иллюстрации того, что… …   Википедия

  • David Stove — Full name David Stove Born September 15, 1927(1927 09 15) Died June 2, 1994(1994 06 02) (aged 66) Era 20th century philosophy Region …   Wikipedia

  • Bayes' theorem — In probability theory, Bayes theorem (often called Bayes law after Thomas Bayes) relates the conditional and marginal probabilities of two random events. It is often used to compute posterior probabilities given observations. For example, a… …   Wikipedia

  • Bayesian inference — is statistical inference in which evidence or observations are used to update or to newly infer the probability that a hypothesis may be true. The name Bayesian comes from the frequent use of Bayes theorem in the inference process. Bayes theorem… …   Wikipedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”