- Pathological (mathematics)
In
mathematics , a pathological phenomenon is one whose properties are considered atypically bad or counterintuitive.Often, when the usefulness of a theorem is challenged by
counterexamples , defenders of the theorem argue that the exceptions are pathological. A famous case is theAlexander horned sphere , a counterexample showing that topologically embedding the sphere S2 in R3 may fail to "separate the space cleanly", unless an extra condition of "tameness" is used to suppress possible "wild" behaviour. SeeJordan-Schönflies theorem .One can therefore say that (particularly in
mathematical analysis andset theory ) those searching for the "pathological" are likeexperimentalist s, interested in knocking down potentialtheorems , in contrast to finding general statements widely applicable. Each activity has its role within mathematics.Pathological functions
A classic example is the
Weierstrass function , which is continuous everywhere but differentiable nowhere. Obviously, the sum of a differentiable function and the Weierstrass function is again continuous but nowhere differentiable; so there are at least as many such functions as differentiable functions. In fact, by theBaire category theorem one can show that continuous functions are typically or "generically" nowhere differentiable.In layman's terms, this is because of the vast infinity of possible functions, relatively few will ever be studied by mathematicians, and those that do come to their attention as being interesting or useful will tend to be well-behaved. To quote
Henri Poincaré :cquote|Logic sometimes makes monsters. For half a century we have seen a mass of bizarre functions which appear to be forced to resemble as little as possible honest functions which serve some purpose. More of continuity, or less of continuity, more derivatives, and so forth. Indeed, from the point of view of logic, these strange functions are the most general; on the other hand those which one meets without searching for them, and which follow simple laws appear as a particular case which does not amount to more than a small corner.
In former times when one invented a new function it was for a practical purpose; today one invents them purposely to show up defects in the reasoning of our fathers and one will deduce from them only that.
If logic were the sole guide of the teacher, it would be necessary to begin with the most general functions, that is to say with the most bizarre. It is the beginner that would have to be set grappling with this teratologic museum.|20px|20px|
Henri Poincaré |1899This highlights the fact that the term "pathological" is subjective or at least context-dependent, and its meaning in any particular case resides in the community of mathematicians, not necessarily within the subject matter of mathematics itself.
Pathological examples
Pathological examples often have some undesirable or unusual properties that make it difficult to contain or explain within a theory. Such pathological behaviour often prompts new investigation which leads to new theory and more general results. For example, three important historical examples of this are the following:
*The discovery of
irrational number s by the school ofPythagoras in ancient Greece; the first example of an irrational number they found was the length of the diagonal of aunit square , that is
*The discovery ofnumber field s whose rings of integers do not form aunique factorization domain , for example the field .
*The discovery offractal s and other "rough" geometric objects (seeHausdorff dimension ).At the time of their discovery, each of these were considered highly pathological; today, each has been assimilated, which is to say, explained by an extensive general theory.
Again, to reiterate, it should be pointed out that such judgments about what is or is not pathological are inherently subjective or at least vary with context and depend on both training and experience — what is pathological to one researcher may very well be standard behaviour to another.
Pathological examples can show the importance of the assumptions in a theorem. For example, in
statistics , theCauchy distribution does not satisfy thecentral limit theorem , even though its symmetric bell-shape appears similar to many distributions which do; it fails the requirement to have a mean and standard deviation which exist and are finite.The best-known
paradox es such as theBanach–Tarski paradox andHausdorff paradox are based on the existence ofnon-measurable set s. Mathematicians, unless they take the minority position of denying theaxiom of choice , are in general resigned to living with such sets.Other examples include the Peano
space-filling curve which maps the unit interval [0, 1] continuously onto [0, 1] × [0, 1] , and theCantor set which is a subset of the interval [0, 1] and has the pathological property that it isuncountable , yet its measure is zero.Computer science
In
computer science , "pathological" has a slightly different sense with regard to the study ofalgorithm s. Here, an input (or set of inputs) is said to be "pathological" if it causes atypical behavior from the algorithm, such as a violation of its average case complexity, or even its correctness. For example,hash table s generally have pathological inputs: sets of keys that collide on hash values.Quicksort normally has O(n log n) time complexity, but deteriorates to O(n2) when given input that is sorted. The term is often used pejoratively, as a way of dismissing such inputs as being specially designed to break a routine that is otherwise sound in practice. Compare "Byzantine".ee also
*
Well-behaved External links
* [http://www.mountainman.com.au/fractal_00.htm Pathological Structures & Fractals] - Extract of an article by
Freeman Dyson , "Characterising Irregularity", Science, May 1978
Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.