- Good and evil
In
religion ,ethics , andphilosophy , the phrase, good and evil refers to the location of objects, desires, andbehavior s on a two-wayspectrum , with one direction being morally positive ("good"), and the other morally negative ("evil"). "Good" is a broad concept and is difficult to define, but typically it deals with an association withlife ,continuity ,happiness , orhuman flourishing .Evil is more simply defined: the opposite of good. Depending on the context, good and evil may represent personal judgments, societal norms, or claims of absolute value related to human nature or to transcendent religious standards.There is no consensus over whether either good or evil are intrinsic to human
nature . The nature of "goodness" has been given many treatments; one is that the good is based on the naturallove , bonding, and affection that begins at the earliest stages of personal development; another is that goodness is a product of knowing truth. Differing views also exist as to why evil might arise. Many religious and philosophical traditions claim that evil behavior is an "aberration" that results from the imperfect human condition (eg. "The Fall of Man "). Sometimes, evil is attributed to the existence offree will and human agency. Some argue that evil itself is ultimately based in anignorance oftruth (i.e., human value,sanctity ,divinity ). A variety of Enlightenment thinkers have alleged the opposite, by suggesting that evil is learned as a consequence of tyrannicalsocial structure s. By anevolution ary perspective, humans are biologically adapted to carry out a variety ofgame theory strategies, some of which may promote individual utility at the expense of group utility, which, if the disparity is extreme enough, would be termed evil. Goodness in mathematics has also been related toentropy andinformation theory , as well as how well a statistical model will reflect a set of observations (known of asgoodness of fit ).Although goodness is generally not considered to be a real or well-established property under the laws of
physics , each person's highly individual concept of the perfect good has profound psychological significance. Agreement is divided over the extent to which this with the real world, but there is little disagreement that one's concept motivates one's actions in the real world."Theories of moral goodness" inquire into what sorts of things are good, and what the word "good" really means in the abstract. As a philosophical concept, goodness might represent a
hope that natural love be "continuous, expansive," and "all-inclusive". In a monotheistic religious context, it is by this "hope" that an important concept ofGod is derived —as aninfinite projection of love, manifest as goodness in the lives of people. In other contexts, the good is viewed to be whatever produces the best consequences upon the lives of people, especially with regard to their states of well being.Origin of the concept
While every language has a word expressing "good" in the sense of "having the right or desirable quality" (
ἀρετή ) and "bad" in the sense "undesirable", the notion of "good and evil" in an absolute moral or religious sense is not ancient, but emerges out of notions ofritual purity and impurity. The basic meanings of κακός and ἀγαθός are "bad, cowardly" and "good, brave, capable", and their absolute sense emerges only around 400 BC, withPre-Socratic philosophy , in particularDemocritus . [Charles H. Kahn, "Democritus and the Origins of Moral Psychology", The American Journal of Philology (1985)] Morality in this absolute sense solidifies in the dialogues ofPlato , together with the emergence ofmonotheistic thought (notably in "Euthyphro " which ponders the concept of piety () as a moral absolute). The idea is further developed inLate Antiquity , inNeoplatonism ,Gnosticism and by theChurch Fathers .This development from the relative or habitual to the absolute is also evident in the terms "
ethics " and "morality " both being derived from terms for "regional custom", Greek ήθος and Latin "mores", respectively (see also "").Descriptive, meta-ethical, and normative fields
It is possible to treat the essential theories of value by the use of a philosophical and academic approach. In properly analyzing theories of value, everyday beliefs are not only carefully "catalogued" and "described", but also rigorously "analyzed" and "judged".
There are at least two basic ways of presenting a theory of value, based on two different kinds of questions which people ask:
* What do people find good, and what do they despise?
* What really is good, and what really is bad?The two questions are subtly different. One may answer the first question by researching the world by use of social science, and examining the preferences that people assert. However, one may answer the second question by use of reasoning, introspection, prescription, and generalization. The former kind of method of analysis is called "
descriptive ", because it attempts to describe what people actually view as good or evil; while the latter is called "normative", because it tries to actively prohibit evils and cherish goods. These descriptive and normative approaches can be complementary. For example, tracking the decline of the popularity of slavery across cultures is the work of descriptive ethics, while advising that slavery be avoided is normative.Meta-ethics is the study of the fundamental questions concerning the nature and origins of the good and the vile, including inquiry into the nature of good and evil, as well as the meaning of evaluative language. In this respect, meta-ethics is not necessarily tied to investigations into how others see the good, or of asserting what is good.Theories of the intrinsically good
A satisfying formulation of goodness would be valuable because it might allow one to construct a good life or society by reliable processes of deduction, elaboration or prioritization. One could answer the ancient question, "How then should we live?", among many other important related questions. It has long been thought that this question can best be answered by examining what it is that necessarily makes a thing valuable, or what the source of value consists in.
Transcendental realism
One attempt to define goodness describes it as a property of the world. According to this claim, to talk about the good is to talk about something real within the object itself which exists independently of the perception of it.
Plato was one advocate of this view, in his expression that there is such a thing as an eternal realm offorms or ideas, and that the greatest of the ideas and the essence of being was goodness, or The good. The good was defined by many ancient Greeks and other ancient philosophers as a perfect and eternal idea, or blueprint. The good is the right relation between all that exists, and this exists in the mind of the Divine, or some heavenly realm. The good is theharmony of a just political community, love, friendship, the ordered human soul ofvirtues , and the right relation to the Divine and to Nature. The characters in Plato's dialogues mention the many virtues of a philosopher, or a lover of wisdom.Many people are theists, who support the idea that
god (s) created the universe. Such persons may, therefore, claim that the universe has a purpose and value according to the will of such a creator(s), and which lies partially beyond human understanding. For instance,Thomas Aquinas was a proponent of this view, and believed to have proven arguments for the existence of a god, and the right relations that humans ought to have to the divinefirst cause .Monotheists might also hope in the popular production of infinite universal love. Such hope is often translated as "
faith ", andwisdom itself is largely defined within religious doctrine as "a knowledge and understanding of innate goodness." The concepts ofinnocence , spiritualpurity , andsalvation are likewise related to a concept of being in, or returning to, a state of " goodness" —one which, according to various teachings of "enlightenment", approaches a state of "holiness" (or Godliness").Another spiritual, transcendental viewpoint is that of
Taoism , the ancient Chinese philosophy which advocated quietism and conformity to the Way, or Tao: "The Tao is the natural order of things. It is a force that flows through every living or sentient object, as well as through the entire universe".Some believe that good is anything that increases the probability of the universe eventually reaching the
Omega Point , and bad is anything that decreases that probability.Some say that good is neither good nor evil, but something altogether different--something of a third thing.
Perfectionism
It was the belief of
Aristotle that virtues consisted in the realization of potentials which were unique to humanity, such as the use of reason. This type of view, calledperfectionism , has been recently defended in modern form byThomas Hurka .An entirely different form of perfectionism has arisen in response to rapid technological change. Some
techno-optimist s, especially transhumanists, avow a form of perfectionism in which the capacity to determine good and trade off fundamental values, is expressed not by humans but by software,genetic engineering of humans,artificial intelligence . Skeptics assert that rather than perfect goodness, it would be only the appearance of perfect goodness, reinforced bypersuasion technology and probably brute force of violenttechnological escalation , which would cause people to accept such rulers or rules authored by them.Welfarist theories
Welfarist theories of value are those which say that that which is good, and hence valuable, are due to their effects on the well-being of persons.
ubjective theories of wellbeing
It is difficult to figure out where an immaterial trait such as "goodness" could reside in the world. A counterproposal is to locate values inside people. Some philosophers go so far as to say that if some
state of affairs does not tend to arouse a desirable subjective state in self-aware beings, then it cannot be good.Most philosophers that think goods have to create desirable mental states also say that goods are experiences of self-aware beings. These philosophers often distinguish the experience, which they call an intrinsic good, from the things that seem to cause the experience, which they call "inherent" goods. Failing to distinguish the two leads to a
subject-object problem in which it is not clear who is evaluating what object.In some theories there is no higher collective value than that of maximizing "pleasure" for individual(s). Some have even defined goodness and that which is intrinsically valuable as the experience of pleasure, and the bad as the experience of pain. This view is called
Hedonism , a "monistic theory of value". It has two main varieties: simple, and Epicurean."Simple hedonism" is the view that physical pleasure is the ultimate good. However, the ancient philosopher
Epicurus used the word 'pleasure' in a more general sense which encompassed a range of states from bliss to contentment to relief. Contrary to popular caricature, he valued pleasures of the mind to bodily pleasures, and advocated moderation as the surest path to happiness.Jeremy Bentham 's book "The Principles of Morals and Legislation " prioritized goods by considering pleasure, pain and consequences. This theory had a wide effect on public affairs, up to and including the present day. A similar system was later namedUtilitarianism byJohn Stuart Mill . More broadly, utilitarian theories are examples of Consequentialism. All utilitarian theories are based upon the "maxim of utility", which states that that which is good is that which provides "the greatest happiness for the greatest number". It follows from this principle that that which brings happiness to the greatest number of people, is a good.One of the benefits of tracing good to pleasure and pain is that both things seem to be easily understandable, both in oneself and to an extent in others. For the hedonist, the explanation for helping behavior may come in the form of "empathy"—the ability of a being to "feel" another's pain. People tend to value the lives of gorillas more than those of mosquitoes because the gorilla lives and feels, making it easier to empathize with them. This idea is carried forward in the
ethical relationship view and has given rise to theanimal rights movement and parts of thepeace movement . The impact of sympathy on human behavior is compatible with Enlightenment views, includingDavid Hume 's stances that the idea of a self with unique identity is illusory, and that morality ultimately comes down to sympathy and fellow feeling for others, or the exercise of approval underlying moral judgements.A view adopted by
James Griffin (philosopher) attempts to find a subjective alternative to hedonism as an intrinsic value. He argues that it is the satisfaction of one's informed desires which constitutes wellbeing, and not necessarily whether or not said desires actually cause the agent to experience happiness. Moreover, these preferences must be life-relevant, that is, contributing to the success of a person's life overall.Desire satisfaction may occur without the agent's awareness of the satisfaction of the desire. For example, if a man wishes for his legal will to be enacted after his death, and it is, then his desire has been satisfied despite the fact that he will never experience or know of it.
Objective theories of wellbeing
The idea that the ultimate good exists and is not orderable but is globally measurable is reflected in various ways in
classical economics ,green economics ,welfare economics and theGross National Happiness andmeasuring well-being theories, all of which focus on various ways of assessing progress towards that goal, a so-calledGenuine Progress Indicator . Modern economics thus reflects very ancient philosophy, but a calculation or quantitative or other process based on cardinality andstatistics replaces the simple ordering of values.For example, in both economics and in folk wisdom, the value of a thing seems to rise so long as it is relatively scarce. However, if it becomes too scarce, it leads often to a conflict, and can reduce collective value. "See the separate analysis of
wealth ."In the classical
political economy ofAdam Smith andDavid Ricardo , and in its critique byKarl Marx , "human labor" is seen as the ultimate source of all new economic value. This is an "objective" theory of value (seevalue theory which attributes value to real production-costs, and ultimately expenditures of human labor-time (see alsolaw of value . It contrasts withmarginal utility theory, which argues that the value of labor depends on subjective preferences by consumers, which may however also be objectively studied.The economic value of labor may be assessed technically in terms of its
use-value orutility or commercially in terms of itsexchange-value ,price or production cost (see alsolabor power . But its value may also be socially assessed in terms of its contribution to thewealth andwell-being of a society.In non-market societies, labor may be valued primarily in terms of skill, time, and output, as well as moral or social criteria and legal obligations. In market societies, labor is valued economically primarily through the
labor market . The price of labor may then be set by supply and demand, bystrike action or legislation, or by legal or professional entry-requirements into occupations.Mid-range theories
"
Conceptual metaphor theories" argue against both subjective and objective conceptions of value and meaning, and focus on the relationships between body and other essential elements of human life. In effect, conceptual metaphor theories treat ethics as anontology problem and the issue of how to work-out values as a negotiation of these metaphors, not the application of someabstraction or a strict standoff between parties who have no way to understand each other's views.Goodness and agency
Agent-centered theories
One more recent philosophical proposal has defined good as "That which increases the quality and quantity of choices available overall." These approaches have been called "choice optimization theories". This maxim might be countered by the phenomenon of
opportunity cost s observed by social scientists. Opportunity cost is when people who are confronted with a greater number of choices also experience greater dismay at their choices after the fact, because of the missed opportunities.In his "
Development as Freedom ",Amartya Sen assertedfree time as the most fundamental good and systems of organizing which enabled it as the most fundamental value in civilization. He refuted the common claim that Asian value theorists had devalued freedom and was clear that a marketplace (creating unity via pricing) valuing free time could be created.Marilyn Waring took a similar view from afeminist perspective, arguing women's time was undervalued and especially the free time they used to raise and teach children. Waring also strongly denied that military hardware or activities were of any value, and attempted to reconcilepeace or welfare views of good with the ecological values.Virtue theories
John Rawls 's book "A Theory of Justice " prioritized social arrangements and goods based on their contribution tojustice . Rawls defined justice as "fairness", especially in distributing social goods, defined fairness in terms of procedures, and attempted to prove that just institutions and lives are good, if rational individuals' goods are considered fairly. Rawls's crucial invention was theoriginal position , a procedure in which one tries to make objective moral decisions by refusing to let personal facts about oneself enter one's moral calculations.One problem with the approaches of Rawls is that it is overly procedural. Procedurally fair processes of the type used by Rawls may not leave enough room for judgment, and therefore, reduce the totality of goodness. For example, if two people are found to own an orange, the standard fair procedure is to cut it in two and give half to each. However, if one wants to eat it while the other wants the rind to flavor a cake, cutting it in two is clearly less good than giving the peel to the baker and feeding the core to the eater.
Applying procedural fairness to an entire society therefore seems certain to create recognizable inefficiencies, and therefore be unfair, and (by the equivalence of justice with fairness) unjust.
However, procedural processes are not always necessarily damning in this way. Kant, a great influence for Rawls, similarly applies a lot of procedural practice within the practical application of "The Categorical Imperative", however, this is indeed not based solely on 'fairness'. Even though an example like the one above regarding the orange would not be something that required the practical application of "The Categorical Imperative", it is important to draw distinction between Kant and Rawls, and note that Kant's Theory would not necessarily lead to the same problems Rawls' does - i.e., the cutting in half of the orange. Kant's Theory promotes acting out of Duty - acting for the Summum Bonum for him, "The Good Will" - and in fact encourages Judgement, too. What this would mean is that the outcome of the Orange's distribution would not be such a simple process for Kant as the reason why it would be wanted by both parties would necessarily have to be a part of the Judgement process, thus eliminating the problem that Rawls' account suffers here.
Agent-external theories
ociety, life and ecology
Many views value "unity" as a good: to go beyond
eudaimonia by saying that an individual person's flourishing is valuable only as a means to the flourishing of society as a whole. In other words, a single person's life is, ultimately, not important or worthwhile in itself, but is good only as a means to the success of society as a whole. Some elements ofConfucianism are an example of this, encouraging the view that people ought to conform as individuals to demands of a peaceful and ordered society.According to the naturalistic view, the flourishing of society is not, or not the only, intrinsically good thing. Defenses of this notion are often formulated by reference to
biology , and observations that living things compete more with their own kind than with other kinds. Rather, what is of intrinsic good is the flourishing of all sentient life; extending to those animals which have some level of similar sentience, such asGreat Ape personhood . Others go farther, by declaring that life itself is of intrinsic value.By another approach, one achieves peace and agreement by focusing, not on one's peers (who may be rivals or competitors), but on the common environment. The reasoning goes that as living beings it is clearly and objectively good we are surrounded by an ecosystem that supports
life . Indeed, if we weren't, we couldn't even recognize that or discuss it. "Theanthropic principle in cosmology recognizes this view."Under
materialism or evenembodiment values, or in any system that recognizes the validity ofecology as a scientific study of limits and potentials, an ecosystem is a fundamental good. To all who investigate, it seems that goodness, or value, exists within an ecosystem,Earth . Creatures within that ecosystem and wholly dependent on it, evaluate good relative to what else could be achieved there. In other words, good issituated in a particular place and one does not dismiss everything that is not available there (such as very low gravity or absolutely abundant sugar candy) as "not good enough", one works within its constraints. Transcending them and learning to be satisfied with them, is thus another sort of value, perhaps calledsatisfaction , or inBuddhism enlightenment.Values and the people that hold them seem necessarily subordinate to the ecosystem. If this is so, then what kind of being could validly apply the word "good" to an ecosystem as a whole? Who would have the power to assess and judge an ecosystem as good or bad? By what criteria? And by what criteria would ecosystems be modified, especially larger ones such as the
atmosphere (climate change ) orocean s (extinction ) orforest s (deforestation )? "For discussion see debates onmonoculture andpermaculture .""Remaining on Earth" as the most basic value. While green ethicists have been most forthright about it, and have developed theories of
Gaia philosophy ,biophilia ,bioregionalism that reflect it, the questions are now universally recognized as central in determining value, e.g. the economic "value of Earth " to humans as a whole, or the "value of life " that is neither whole-Earth nor human. Many have come to the conclusion that without assuming ecosystem continuation as a universal good, with attendantvirtue s likebiodiversity andecological wisdom it is impossible to justify such operational requirements assustainability of human activity on Earth.One response is that humans are not necessarily confined to Earth, and could use it and move on. A counter-argument is that only a tiny fraction of humans could ever do this, and those would be self-selected by ability to do
technological escalation on others (for instance, the ability to create large missiles on which to flee the planet and simultaneously threaten others who sought to prevent them). Another counter-argument is thatextraterrestrial life would encounter the fleeing humans and be forced to destroy them as alocust species. A third is that if there are no other worlds fit to support life (and thus no extraterrestrials competing with humans to occupy them) it is both futile to flee, and foolish to imagine that it would take less energy and skill to protect the Earth as a habitat, than it would take to construct some new habitat.Accordingly remaining on Earth, as a living being surrounded by a working ecosystem, is a fair statement of the most basic values and goodness to any being we are able to communicate with. A moral system without this axiom seems simply not actionable.
However, most religious systems acknowledge an
afterlife and improving this is seen as an even more basic good. In many other moral systems, also, remaining on Earth in a state that lacks honor or power over self is less desirable - considerseppuku inbushido ,kamikaze s or the role ofsuicide attack s inJihadi rhetoric. In all these systems, remaining on Earth is perhaps no higher than a third-place value.Radical values environmentalism can be seen as either a very old or a very new view: that the only intrinsically good thing is a flourishing ecosystem; individuals and societies are merely instrumentally valuable, good only as means to having a flourishing ecosystem. The
Gaia philosophy is the most detailed expression of this overall thought but it strongly influencedDeep Ecology and the modernGreen Parties .It is often claimed that aboriginal peoples never lost this sort of view -
anthropological linguistics studies links between their languages and the ecosystems in which they lived and which gave rise to theirknowledge distinctions. Very often, environmental cognition andmoral cognition were not distinguished in these languages - offenses to nature were like those to other people, andAnimism reinforced this by giving nature "personality" via myth.Anthropological theories of value explore these questions.Most people in the world reject older
situated ethics and localized religious views. However small-community-based and ecology-centric views have gained some popularity in recent years. In part, this has been attributed to the desire for ethical certainties. Such a deeply-rooted definition of goodness would be valuable because it might allow one to construct a good life or society by reliable processes of deduction, elaboration or prioritisation. Ones that relied only on local referents one could verify for oneself, creating more certainty and therefore less investment in protection, hedging and insuring against consequences of loss of the value.History and novelty
An event is often seen as being of value simply because of its "novelty" in fashion and art. By contrast, cultural history and other antiques are sometimes seen as of value in and of themselves due to their "age". Philosopher-historians Will and Ariel Durant spoke as much with the quote, "As the sanity of the individual lies in the continuity of his memories, so the sanity of the group lies in the continuity of its traditions; in either case a break in the chain invites a neurotic reaction" (The Lessons of History, 72).
Assessment of the value of old or historical artifacts takes into consideration, especially but not exclusively: the value placed on having a detailed knowledge of the past, the desire to have tangible ties to ancestral history, and/or the increased market value scarce items traditionally hold.
Creativity andinnovation andinvention are sometimes upheld as fundamentally good especially in Western industrial society - all imply newness, and even opportunity to profit from novelty.Bertrand Russell was notably pessimistic about creativity and thought thatknowledge expanding faster thanwisdom necessarily was fatal.Anti-goodness theories
Choice of lesser goods theories
Sometimes more thorough attempts will also be made to describe the origin of
evil and how it might tend to come into existence as well, and sometimes those attempts will fall under the category of describing as false various forms of goodness. Among some schools of thought, the idea is put forth that all evil comes from the excessive pursuit of goods of lesser value, at the expense of goods of greater value. For instance,greed derives from the pursuit of gain for one's self, generally a good thing, at the expense of others, generally a bad thing. Overeating may result from the exchange of momentary pleasure derived from the eating of food, for the greater good of long term health. Inpsychology similar processes might occur in the formation of various types ofaddictions . No particular thing is thus considered to be intrinsically bad automatically, but rather evil will come from the pursuit of various goods in excess, to the expense of other more important ones, which are then neglected.ee also
*
Axiology
*Common good
*Descriptive ethics
*Evil
*Inductive reasoning
*Meta-ethics
*Supreme good
*Sin
*Value theory References
ources
*Aristotle. "Nicomachean Ethics". 1998. USA: Oxford University Press. (1177a15)
*Bentham, Jeremy. "The Principles of Morals and Legislation". 1988. Prometheus Books.
*Dewey, John. "Theory of Valuation". 1948. University of Chicago Press.
*Durant, Ariel and W. Durant. "The Lessons of History". 1997. MJF Books. (p72)
*Garcia, John David. "The Moral Society - A Rational Alternative to Death". 2005. Whitmore Publishing.
*Griffin, James. Well-Being: Its Meaning, Measurement and Moral Importance. 1986. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
*Hume, David. "A Treastise of Human Nature". 2000. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
*Hurka, Thomas. "Perfectionism". 1993. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
*Kant, Immanuel. "Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals". 1996. Cambridge University Press. Third section, [446] - [447] .
*Rawls, John. "A Theory of Justice". 1999. Belknap Press.External links
* [http://www.ourcivilisation.com/moral/moral8.htm Recognising Good And Evil] , by Philip Atkinson
Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.