Boolean prime ideal theorem

Boolean prime ideal theorem

In mathematics, a prime ideal theorem guarantees the existence of certain types of subsets in a given abstract algebra. A common example is the Boolean prime ideal theorem, which states that ideals in a Boolean algebra can be extended to prime ideals. A variation of this statement for filters on sets is known as the ultrafilter lemma. Other theorems are obtained by considering different mathematical structures with appropriate notions of ideals, for example, rings and prime ideals (of ring theory), or distributive lattices and "maximal" ideals (of order theory). This article focuses on prime ideal theorems from order theory.

Although the various prime ideal theorems may appear simple and intuitive, they cannot be derived in general from the axioms of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (ZF). Instead, some of the statements turn out to be equivalent to the axiom of choice (AC), while others --- the Boolean prime ideal theorem, for instance --- represent a property that is strictly weaker than AC. It is due to this intermediate status between ZF and ZF+AC (ZFC) that the Boolean prime ideal theorem is often taken as an axiom of set theory. The abbreviations BPI or PIT (for Boolean algebras) are sometimes used to refer to this additional axiom.

Prime ideal theorems

Recall that an order ideal is a (non-empty) directed lower set. If the considered poset has binary suprema, as do the posets within this article, then this is equivalently characterized as a lower set "I" which is closed for binary suprema (i.e. "x", "y" in "I" imply "x"vee"y" in "I"). An ideal "I" is prime if, whenever an infimum "x"wedge"y" is in "I", one also has "x" in "I" or "y" in "I". Ideals are proper if they are not equal to the whole poset.

Historically, the first statement relating to later prime ideal theorems was in fact referring to filters -- subsets that are ideals with respect to the dual order. The ultrafilter lemma states that every filter on a set is contained within some maximal (proper) filter -- an "ultrafilter". Recall that filters on sets are proper filters of the Boolean algebra of its powerset. In this special case, maximal filters (i.e. filters that are not strict subsets of any proper filter) and prime filters (i.e. filters that with each union of subsets "X" and "Y" contain also "X" or "Y") coincide. The dual of this statement thus assures that every ideal of a powerset is contained in a prime ideal.

The above statement led to various generalized prime ideal theorems, each of which exists in a weak and in a strong form. "Weak prime ideal theorems" state that every "non-trivial" algebra of a certain class has at least one prime ideal. In contrast, "strong prime ideal theorems" require that every ideal that is disjoint from a given filter can be extended to a prime ideal which is still disjoint from that filter. In the case of algebras that are not posets, one uses different substructures instead of filters. Many forms of these theorems are actually known to be equivalent, so that the assertion that "PIT" holds is usually taken as the assertion that the corresponding statement for Boolean algebras (BPI) is valid.

Another variation of similar theorems is obtained by replacing each occurrence of "prime ideal" by "maximal ideal". The corresponding maximal ideal theorems (MIT) are often -- though not always -- stronger than their PIT equivalents.

Boolean prime ideal theorem

The Boolean prime ideal theorem is the strong prime ideal theorem for Boolean algebras. Thus the formal statement is:

: Let "B" be a Boolean algebra, let "I" be an ideal and let "F" be a filter of "B", such that "I" and "F" are disjoint. Then "I" is contained in some prime ideal of "B" that is disjoint from "F".

The weak prime ideal theorem for Boolean algebras simply states:

: Every Boolean algebra contains a prime ideal.

We refer to these statements as the weak and strong "BPI". The two are equivalent, as the strong BPI clearly implies the weak BPI, and the reverse implication can be achieved by using the weak BPI to find prime ideals in the appropriate quotient algebra.

The BPI can be expressed in various different ways. For this purpose, recall the following theorem:

For any ideal "I" of a Boolean algebra "B", the following are equivalent:
* "I" is a prime ideal.
* "I" is a maximal proper ideal, i.e. for any proper ideal "J", if "I" is contained in "J" then "I" = "J".
* For every element "a" of "B", "I" contains exactly one of {"a", ¬"a"}.This theorem is a well-known fact for Boolean algebras. Its dual establishes the equivalence of prime filters and ultrafilters. Note that the last property is in fact self-dual -- only the prior assumption that "I" is an ideal gives the full characterization. It is worth mentioning that all of the implications within this theorem can be proven in classical Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory.

Thus the following (strong) maximal ideal theorem (MIT) for Boolean algebras is equivalent to BPI:

:Let "B" be a Boolean algebra, let "I" be an ideal and let "F" be a filter of "B", such that "I" and "F" are disjoint. Then "I" is contained in some maximal ideal of "B" that is disjoint from "F".

Note that one requires "global" maximality, not just maximality with respect to being disjoint from "F". Yet, this variation yields another equivalent characterization of BPI:

:Let "B" be a Boolean algebra, let "I" be an ideal and let "F" be a filter of "B", such that "I" and "F" are disjoint. Then "I" is contained in some ideal of "B" that is maximal among all ideals disjoint from "F".

The fact that this statement is equivalent to BPI is easily established by noting the following theorem: For any distributive lattice "L", if an ideal "I" is maximal among all ideals of "L" that are disjoint to a given filter "F", then "I" is a prime ideal. The proof for this statement (which can again be carried out in ZF set theory) is included in the article on ideals. Since any Boolean algebra is a distributive lattice, this shows the desired implication.

All of the above statements are now easily seen to be equivalent. Going even further, one can exploit the fact the dual orders of Boolean algebras are exactly the Boolean algebras themselves. Hence, when taking the equivalent duals of all former statements, one ends up with a number of theorems that equally apply to Boolean algebras, but where every occurrence of "ideal" is replaced by "filter". It is worth noting that for the special case where the Boolean algebra under consideration is a powerset with the subset ordering, the "maximal filter theorem" is called the ultrafilter lemma.

Summing up, for Boolean algebras, the weak and strong MIT, the weak and strong PIT, and the equivalent statements with filters in place of ideals are all equivalent. It is known that all of these statements are consequences of the axiom of choice (the easy proof makes use of Zorn's lemma), but cannot be proven in classical Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory. Yet, the BPI is strictly weaker than the axiom of choice, though the proof of this statement, due to J. D. Halpern and Azriel Levy is rather non-trivial.

Further prime ideal theorems

The prototypical properties that were discussed for Boolean algebras in the above section can easily be modified to include more general lattices, such as distributive lattices or Heyting algebras. However, in these cases maximal ideals are different from prime ideals, and the relation between PITs and MITs is not obvious.

Indeed, it turns out that the MITs for distributive lattices and even for Heyting algebras are equivalent to the axiom of choice. On the other hand, it is known that the strong PIT for distributive lattices is equivalent to BPI (i.e. to the MIT and PIT for Boolean algebras). Hence this statement is strictly weaker than the axiom of choice. Furthermore, observe that Heyting algebras are not self dual, and thus using filters in place of ideals yields different theorems in this setting. Maybe surprisingly, the MIT for the duals of Heyting algebras is not stronger than BPI, which is in sharp contrast to the abovementioned MIT for Heyting algebras.

Finally, prime ideal theorems do also exist for other (not order-theoretical) abstract algebras. For example, the MIT for rings implies the axiom of choice. This situation requires to replace the order-theoretic term "filter" by other concepts -- for rings a "multiplicatively closed subset" is appropriate.

The ultrafilter lemma

A filter on a set "X" is a collection of nonempty subsets of "X" that is closed under finite intersection and under superset. An ultrafilter is a maximal filter. The ultrafilter lemma states that every filter on a set "X" is a subset of some ultrafilter on "X" (a maximal filter of nonempty subsets of "X".) This lemma is most often used in the study of topology.

The ultrafilter lemma is equivalent to the Boolean prime ideal theorem, with the equivalence provable in ZF set theory without the axiom of choice. The idea behind the proof is that the subsets of any set form a Boolean algebra partially ordered by inclusion, and any Boolean algebra is representable as an algebra of sets by Stone's representation theorem.

Applications

Intuitively, the Boolean prime ideal theorem states that there are "enough" prime ideals in a Boolean algebra in the sense that we can extend "every" ideal to a maximal one. This is of practical importance for proving Stone's representation theorem for Boolean algebras, a special case of Stone duality, in which one equips the set of all prime ideals with a certain topology and can indeed regain the original Boolean algebra (up to isomorphism) from this data. Furthermore, it turns out that in applications one can freely choose either to work with prime ideals or with prime filters, because every ideal uniquely determines a filter: the set of all Boolean complements of its elements. Both approaches are found in the literature.

Many other theorems of general topology that are often said to rely on the axiom of choice are in fact equivalent to BPI. For example, the theorem that a product of compact Hausdorff spaces is compact is equivalent to it. If we leave out "Hausdorff" we get a theorem equivalent to the full axiom of choice.

A not too well known application of the Boolean prime ideal theorem is the existence of a non-measurable set [Wacław Sierpiński, Fonctions additives non complètement additives et fonctions non mesurables. Fund.Math. 30, 96-99 (1938)] (the example usually given is the Vitali set, which requires the Axiom of Choice). From this and the fact that the BPI is strictly weaker than the Axiom of Choice, it follows that the existence of non measurable sets is strictly weaker than the axiom of choice.

ee also

* list of Boolean algebra topics

Notes

References

* B. A. Davey and H. A. Priestley, "Introduction to Lattices and Order", 2nd edition, Cambridge University Press, 2002.: "An easy to read introduction, showing the equivalence of PIT for Boolean algebras and distributive lattices."

* P. T. Johnstone, "Stone Spaces", Cambridge studies in advanced mathematics 3, Cambridge University Press, 1982.: "The theory in this book often requires choice principles. The notes on various chapters discuss the general relation of the theorems to PIT and MIT for various structures (though mostly lattices) and give pointers to further literature."

* B. Banaschewski, "The Power of the Ultrafilter Theorem", Journal of the London Mathematical Society (2) 27, 193--202, 1983.: "Discusses the status of the ultrafilter lemma."

* M. Erné, "Prime Ideal Theory for General Algebras", Applied Categorical Structures 8, 115--144, 2000.: "Gives many equivalent statements for the BPI, including prime ideal theorems for other algebraic structures. PITs are considered as special instances of separation lemmas."


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Нужна курсовая?

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Prime ideal theorem — In mathematics, the prime ideal theorem may be * the Boolean prime ideal theorem * the Landau prime ideal theorem on number fields …   Wikipedia

  • Landau prime ideal theorem — In mathematics, the prime ideal theorem of algebraic number theory is the number field generalization of the prime number theorem. It provides an asymptotic formula for counting the number of prime ideals of a number field K , with norm at most X …   Wikipedia

  • Ideal (order theory) — In mathematical order theory, an ideal is a special subset of a partially ordered set (poset). Although this term historically was derived from the notion of a ring ideal of abstract algebra, it has subsequently been generalized to a different… …   Wikipedia

  • Boolean algebra — This article discusses the subject referred to as Boolean algebra. For the mathematical objects, see Boolean algebra (structure). Boolean algebra, as developed in 1854 by George Boole in his book An Investigation of the Laws of Thought,[1] is a… …   Wikipedia

  • Ideal (ring theory) — In ring theory, a branch of abstract algebra, an ideal is a special subset of a ring. The ideal concept allows the generalization in an appropriate way of some important properties of integers like even number or multiple of 3 . For instance, in… …   Wikipedia

  • Stone's representation theorem for Boolean algebras — In mathematics, Stone s representation theorem for Boolean algebras states that every Boolean algebra is isomorphic to a field of sets. The theorem is fundamental to the deeper understanding of Boolean algebra that emerged in the first half of… …   Wikipedia

  • List of Boolean algebra topics — This is a list of topics around Boolean algebra and propositional logic. Contents 1 Articles with a wide scope and introductions 2 Boolean functions and connectives 3 Examples of Boolean algebras …   Wikipedia

  • Tychonoff's theorem — For other theorems named after Tychonoff, see Tychonoff s theorem (disambiguation). In mathematics, Tychonoff s theorem states that the product of any collection of compact topological spaces is compact. The theorem is named after Andrey… …   Wikipedia

  • Compactness theorem — In mathematical logic, the compactness theorem states that a set of first order sentences has a model if and only if every finite subset of it has a model. This theorem is an important tool in model theory, as it provides a useful method for… …   Wikipedia

  • Original proof of Gödel's completeness theorem — The proof of Gödel s completeness theorem given by Kurt Gödel in his doctoral dissertation of 1929 (and a rewritten version of the dissertation, published as an article in 1930) is not easy to read today; it uses concepts and formalism that are… …   Wikipedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”