- Aristotelianism
Aristotelianism is a tradition of
philosophy that takes its defining inspiration from the work ofAristotle . Sometimes contrasted by critics with therationalism and idealism ofPlato , Aristotelianism is understood by its proponents as critically developing Plato’s theories. [For contrasting examples of this, see Hans-Georg Gadamer, "The Idea of the Good in Platonic-Aristotelian Philosophy" (trans. P. Christopher Smith), Yale University Press, 1986, and Lloyd P. Gerson, "Aristotle and Other Platonists", Cornell University Press, 2005.] Most particularly, Aristotelianism brings Plato’s ideals down to Earth as goals andgoods internal to natural species that are realized in activity. This is the characteristically Aristotelian idea ofteleology , and the practicality of the approach is embodied inNichomachean Ethics as the Aristotelian virtue ofphronesis .Fact|date=January 2008History
Preserved by Aristotle's followers in the
Peripatetic school , and elaborated by other ancient commentators, Aristotelianism began its modern history with its reception by Islamic, Jewish and Christian philosophers. The most famous of these philosophers areAverroes ,Maimonides andThomas Aquinas .Averroism was particularly influential in reconciling Aristotelianism with the Islamic and Christian faiths, while Aquinas argued that the truth in Aristotle’s philosophy is complemented and completed by the truth revealed in the Christian tradition. TheRoman Catholic Church has reasserted a Thomistic Aristotelianism since the 1870s.After retreating under criticism from modern natural philosophers, the distinctively Aristotelian idea of teleology was transmitted through Wolff and Kant to Hegel, who applied it to history as a totality. Although this project was criticized by Trendelenburg and Brentano as un-Aristotelian, Hegel’s influence is now often said to be responsible for an important Aristotelian influence upon Marx. [For example, George E. McCarthy (ed.), "Marx and Aristotle: Nineteenth-Century German Social Theory and Classical Antiquity", Rowman & Littlefield, 1992.] Postmodernists, in contrast, reject Aristotelianism’s claim to reveal important theoretical truths. [For example, Ted Sadler, "Heidegger and Aristotle: The Question of Being", Athlone, 1996.] In this, they follow Heidegger’s critique of Aristotle as the greatest source of the entire tradition of Western philosophy. Recent Aristotelian ethical and ‘practical’ philosophy, such as that of Gadamer and McDowell, is often premised upon a rejection of Aristotelianism’s traditional metaphysical or theoretical philosophy. From this viewpoint, the early modern tradition of political
republicanism , which views the "res publica", public sphere or state as constituted by its citizens’ virtuous activity, can appear thoroughly Aristotelian.Contemporary Aristotelianism
The most famous contemporary Aristotelian philosopher is
Alasdair MacIntyre . Especially famous for helping to revivevirtue ethics in his book "After Virtue ", MacIntyre revises Aristotelianism with the argument that the highest temporal goods, which are internal to human beings, are actualized through participation in social practices. He opposes Aristotelianism to the managerial institutions of capitalism and its state, and to rival traditions—including the philosophies of Hume andNietzsche —that reject its idea of essentially human goods and virtues and instead legitimatecapitalism . Therefore, on MacIntyre’s account, Aristotelianism is not identical with Western philosophy as a whole; rather, it is "the best theory so far, [including] the best theory so far about what makes a particular theory the best one." [Alasdair MacIntyre, 'An Interview with Giovanna Borradori', in Kelvin Knight (ed.), "The MacIntyre Reader", Polity Press / University of Notre Dame Press, 1998, p. 264.] Politically and socially, it has been characterized as a newly 'revolutionary Aristotelianism'. This may be contrasted with the more conventional, apolitical and effectively conservative uses of Aristotle by, for example, Gadamer and McDowell. [Kelvin Knight, "Aristotelian Philosophy: Ethics and Politics from Aristotle to MacIntyre", Polity Press, 2007.]ee also
*
Aristotelian ethics
*Hylomorphism Notes
Further reading
*Chappell, Timothy (ed.), "Values and Virtues: Aristotelianism in Contemporary Ethics", Oxford University Press, 2006.
*Ferrarin, Alfredo, "Hegel and Aristotle", Cambridge University Press, 2001.
*Kenny, Anthony, "Essays on the Aristotelian Tradition", Oxford University Press, 2001.
*Knight, Kelvin, "Aristotelian Philosophy: Ethics and Politics from Aristotle to MacIntyre", Polity Press, 2007.
*Knight, Kelvin & Paul Blackledge (eds.), "Revolutionary Aristotelianism: Ethics, Resistance and Utopia", Lucius & Lucius (Stuttgart, Germany), 2008.
*Lobkowicz, Nicholas, "Theory and Practice: History of a Concept from Aristotle to Marx", University of Notre Dame Press, 1967.
*MacIntyre, Alasdair, "After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory", University of Notre Dame Press, 1984 / Duckworth, 1985 (2nd edn.).
*MacIntyre, Alasdair, "Whose Justice? Which Rationality?", University of Notre Dame Press / Duckworth, 1988.
*MacIntyre, Alasdair, "Three Rival Versions of Moral Enquiry: Encyclopaedia, Genealogy, and Tradition", University of Notre Dame Press / Duckworth, 1990.
*MacIntyre, Alasdair, ‘The Theses on Feuerbach: A Road Not Taken’, in Kelvin Knight (ed.), "The MacIntyre Reader", University of Notre Dame Press / Polity Press, 1998.
*MacIntyre, Alasdair, "Dependent Rational Animals: Why Human Beings Need the Virtues", Open Court / Duckworth, 1999.
*MacIntyre, Alasdair, ‘Natural Law as Subversive: The Case of Aquinas’ and ‘Rival Aristotles: 1. Aristotle Against Some Renaissance Aristotelians; 2. Aristotle Against Some Modern Aristotelians’, in MacIntyre, "Ethics and Politics: Selected Essays" volume 2, Cambridge University Press, 2006.
*Riedel, Manfred (ed.), "Rehabilitierung der praktischen Philosophie", Rombach, volume 1, 1972; volume 2, 1974.
*Ritter, Joachim, "Metaphysik und Politik: Studien zu Aristoteles und Hegel", Suhrkamp, 1977.
*Schrenk, Lawrence P. (ed.), "Aristotle in Late Antiquity", Catholic University of America Press, 1994.
*Sharples, R. W. (ed.), "Whose Aristotle? Whose Aristotelianism?", Ashgate, 2001.
*Shute, Richard, "On the History of the Process by Which the Aristotelian Writings Arrived at Their Present Form", Arno Press, 1976 (originally 1888).
*Sorabji, Richard (ed.), "Aristotle Transformed: The Ancient Commentators and Their Influence", Duckworth, 1990.
*Stocks, John Leofric, "Aristotelianism", Harrap, 1925.
*Veatch, Henry B., "Rational Man: A Modern Interpretation of Aristotelian Ethics", Indiana University Press, 1962.External links
* Clayton, Edward. (2005) [http://www.iep.utm.edu/p/p-macint.htm Political Philosophy of Alasdair MacIntyre] ,
Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
* [http://macintyreanphilosophy.googlepages.com/home International Society for MacIntyrean Philosophy]
Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.