- Kochen-Specker theorem
In
quantum mechanics , the Kochen-Specker (KS) theorem [S.Kochen and E.P. Specker, "The problem of hidden variables inquantum mechanics", "Journal of Mathematics and Mechanics"17, 59-87 (1967).] is a "no go" theorem provedbySimon Kochen andErnst Specker in1967 . It placescertain constraints on the permissible types of hiddenvariable theories which try to explain the apparent randomnessofquantum mechanics as a deterministic theory featuringhidden states. The theorem is a complement toBell's theorem .The theorem proves that there is a contradiction between two basicassumptions of hidden variable theories intended to reproduce the resultsof quantum mechanics: that all hidden variables corresponding to quantum mechanical observables havedefinite values at any given time, and that the values of thosevariables are intrinsic and independent of the device used tomeasure them. The contradiction is generated by the fact thatquantum mechanical observables need not be
commutative, making it impossible to embed the
algebra of these observables in acommutative algebra, by assumption representing the classicalstructure of the hidden variables theory.The Kochen-Specker proof demonstrates the impossibility ofEinstein's assumption, made in the famous Einstein-Podolsky-Rosenpaper [A. Einstein, B. Podolsky and N. Rosen,"Can quantum-mechanical description of physical reality be consideredcomplete?" "Phys. Rev." 47, 777-780 (1935).] , that quantum mechanicalobservables represent `elements of physical reality'. Moregenerally does the theorem exclude hidden variable theories requiringelements of physical reality to be "non"contextual (i.e. independent of the measurementarrangement).
History
The KS theorem is an important step in the debate on the (in)completenessof quantum mechanics, boosted in 1935 by the criticism inthe EPR paper of the
Copenhagen assumption of completeness,creating the so-calledEPR paradox . This paradox is derived from theassumption that a quantum mechanical measurement result is generated in adeterministic way as a consequence of the existence of an element of physical realityassumed before the measurement to be present as a property of the microscopic object.In the EPR paper it was assumed that the measured value of a quantum mechanical observablecan play the role of such an element of physical reality.As a consequence of this metaphysical presupposition the EPR criticism was not takenvery seriously by the majority of the physics community. Moreover, in his answer [N. Bohr,"Can quantum-mechanical description of physical reality be consideredcomplete?" "Phys. Rev." 48, 696-702 (1935).] to the EPR paper Bohr had pointed to an ambiguity in the EPR paper,to the effect that it is assumed there that the value of a quantum mechanical observableis non-contextual (i.e. independent of the measurement arrangement).Taking into account the contextuality stemming from the measurement arrangement would, according to Bohr,make obsolete the EPR reasoning. It was subsequently observed by Einstein [A. Einstein,"Quanten-Mechanik und Wirklichkeit", "Dialectica" 2, 320 (1948).] thatBohr's reliance on contextuality implies nonlocality, and that,as a consequence, one would have to accept incompletenessif one wanted to avoid nonlocality (spooky action at a distance).In the 1950's and 60's two lines of development were open for thosenot being averse of metaphysics, both lines improving on a "no go" theorempresented by von Neumann [J. von Neumann, "Mathematische Grundlagen derQuantenmechanik", Springer, Berlin, 1932; English translation: "Mathematicalfoundations of quantum mechanics", Princeton Univ. Press, 1955, Chapter IV.1,2.] , purporting toprove the impossibility of hidden variable theories yieldingthe same results as does quantum mechanics. First, Bohmdeveloped an interpretation of quantum mechanics, generally accepted asa hidden variable theory underpinning quantum mechanics.The nonlocality of Bohm's theory induced Bell to assume thatquantum reality is "non"local, and that probably only "local" hidden variable theoriesare in disagreement with quantum mechanics. More importantly did Bell manage to lift theproblem from the metaphysical level to the physical one by deriving an inequality, the
Bell inequality, that is liable to be experimentally tested.A second line is the Kochen-Specker one. The essentialdifference with Bell's approach is that the possibility ofan underpinning of quantum mechanics by a hidden variabletheory is dealt with independently of any reference tononlocality. Although contextuality plays an important partalso here, there is no implication of nonlocality because theproof refers to observables belonging to one single object, tobe measured in one and the same region of space. Contextualityis related here with "in"compatibility of quantum mechanical observables,incompatibility being associated with mutual exclusiveness ofmeasurement arrangements.
Considerably simpler proofs than the Kochen-Specker one were givenlater, amongst others, by Mermin [N.D. Mermin, "What's wrongwith these elements of reality?" "Physics Today", 43,Issue 6, 9-11 (1990); N.D. Mermin, "Simple unified form for themajor no-hidden-variables theorems", "Phys. Rev. Lett."65, 3373 (1990).] and by Peres [A.Peres, "Two simple proofs of the Kochen-Specker theorem", "J.Phys. A: Math. Gen." 24, L175-L178 (1991).] .
The KS theorem
The KS theorem explores whether it is possible to embed the set of quantummechanical observables into a set of "classical" quantities,notwithstanding that all classical quantities are mutually compatible.The first observation made in the Kochen-Specker paper, is that this is possiblein a trivial way, viz. by ignoring the algebraic structure of the set of quantum mechanical observables. Indeed, let pA(ak) be the probability that observable A has value ak, then the product ApA(ak), taken over all possible observables A, is a valid joint probability distribution, yielding all probabilities of quantum mechanical observables by taking marginals. Kochen and Specker note that this joint probability distribution is not acceptable, however, since it ignores all correlations between the observables. Thus, in quantum mechanics A2 has value ak2 if A has value ak, implying that the values of A and A2 are highly correlated.
More generally it is required by Kochen and Specker that for an arbitrary function f the value of observable satisfies
::
If A1 and A2 are "compatible" (commeasurable) observables, then, by the same token, we should have the following two equalities
:: and real, and
::
The first of the latter two equalities is a considerable weakening compared to von Neumann's assumption that this equality should hold independently of whether A1 and A2 are compatible or incompatible. Kochen and Specker were capable of proving that a value assignment is not possible even on the basis of these weaker assumptions. In order to do so they restricted the observables to a special class, viz. so-called yes-no observables, having only values 0 and 1, corresponding to "projection" operators on the eigenvectors of certain orthogonal bases of a Hilbert space.
Restricting themselves to a three-dimensional Hilbert space, they were able to find a set of 117 such projection operators, "not" allowing to attribute to each of them in an unambiguous way either value 0 or 1. Instead of the rather involved proof by Kochen and Specker it is more illuminating to reproduce here one of the much simpler proofs given much later, which employs a lower number of projection operators by considering a four-dimensional Hilbert space. It turns out that it is possible to obtain a similar result on the basis of a set of only 18 projection operators. The method also works in an eight dimensional Hilbert Space. [M. Kernaghan and A. Peres, Phys. Lett. A 198 (1995) 1–5.]
In order to do so it is sufficient to realize that, if u1, u2, u3 and u4 are the four orthogonal vectors of an orthogonal basis in the four-dimensional Hilbert space, then the projection operators P1, P2, P3, P4 on these vectors are all mutually commuting (and, hence, correspond to compatible observables, allowing a simultaneous attribution of values 0 or 1). Since
::it follows that
:: But, since
:: it follows from 0 or 1, i = 1...4,that out of the four values , one must be 1 while the other three must be 0.
Cabello [A. Cabello, "A proof with 18 vectors of the Bell-Kochen-Specker theorem", in: M. Ferrero and A. van der Merwe (eds.), New Developments on Fundamental Problems in Quantum Physics, Kluwer Academic, Dordrecht, Holland, 1997, 59-62; Adan Cabello, Jose M. Estebaranz, Guillermo Garcia Alcaine, "Bell-Kochen-Specker theorem: A proof with 18 vectors", quant-ph/9706009v1, http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/9706009v1] , extending an argument developed by Kernaghan [M. Kernaghan, J. Phys. A 27 (1994) L829.] considered 9 orthogonal bases, each basis corresponding to a column of the following table, in whichthe basis vectors are explicitly displayed. The bases are chosen in such a way that each has a vector in common with one other basis (indicated in the table by equal colours), thus establishing certain correlations between the 36 corresponding yes-no observables.
Now the "no go" theorem easily follows by making sure that it is impossible todistribute the four numbers 1,0,0,0 over the four rows of each column, such thatequally coloured compartments contain equal numbers. Another way to see the theorem, using the approach by Kernaghan, is to recognize that a contradiction is implied between the odd number of bases and the even number of occurrences of the observables.
Remarks on the KS theorem
1. "Contextuality"
In the Kochen-Specker paper the possibility is discussed that the value attribution may be context-dependent, i.e. observables corresponding to equal vectors in different columns of the table need not have equal values because different columns correspond to "different" measurement arrangements. Since subquantum reality (as described by the hidden variable theory) may be dependent on the measurement context, it is possible that relations between quantum mechanical observables and hidden variables are just homomorphic rather than isomorphic. This would make obsolete the requirement of a context-independent value attribution. Hence, the KS theorem does only exclude noncontextual hidden variable theories. The possibility of contextuality has given rise to the so-called modal interpretations of quantum mechanics.
2. "Different levels of description"
By the KS theorem the impossibility is proven of Einstein's assumption that an element of physical reality is represented by a value of a quantum mechanical observable. The question may be asked whether this is a very shocking result. The value of a quantum mechanical observable refers in the first place to the final position of the pointer of a measuring instrument, which comes into being only during the measurement, and which, for this reason, cannot play the role of an element of physical reality. Elements of physical reality, if existing, would seem to need a subquantum (hidden variable) theory for their descriptionrather than quantum mechanics. In later publications [e.g. J.F. Clauser and M.A. Horne, "Experimental consequences of objective local theories", "Physical Review D" 10, 526-535 (1974).] the Bell inequalities are discussed on the basis of hidden variable theories in which the hidden variable is supposed to refer to a "subquantum" property of the microscopic object different from the value of a quantum mechanical observable. This opens up the possibility of distinguishing different levels of reality described by different theories, which, incidentally, had already been practised by
Louis de Broglie . For such more general theories the KS theorem is applicable only if the measurement is assumed to be a faithful one, in the sense that there is a "deterministic" relation between a subquantum element of physical reality and the value of the observable found on measurement. The existence or nonexistence of such "subquantum" elements of physical reality is not touched by the KS theorem.References
External links
*Carsten Held, "The Kochen-Specker Theorem", Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy * [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kochen-specker/]
* [http://xstructure.inr.ac.ru/x-bin/theme2.py?arxiv=quant-ph&level=1&index1=3004 Kochen-Specker theorem on arxiv.org]
*S. Kochen and E. P. Specker, The problem of hidden variables in quantum mechanics, Full text [http://www.iumj.indiana.edu/IUMJ/dfulltext.php?year=1968&volume=17&artid=17004]
Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.