- Eudaimonia
"Eudaimonia" (Greek: polytonic|εὐδαιμονία) is a classical Greek word commonly translated as '
happiness '. Etymologically, it consists of the word "eu" ("good" or "well being") and "daimōn" ("spirit" or "minor deity", used by extension to mean one's lot or fortune). Although popular usage of the termhappiness refers to a state ofmind , related tojoy orpleasure , "eudaimonia" rarely has such connotations, and the less subjective "human flourishing" is often preferred as a translation. [See Aristotle's Psychology, By Prof. Daniel N. Robinson. (1999). Published by Daniel N. Robinson. ISBN-10: 096720660X ISBN-13: 978-0967206608]Greek philosophy
Socrates 'philosophy , as it is represented inPlato 's early dialogues, contains two related claims about "eudaimonia". The first is the strong inter-dependence of eudaimonia,virtue ("aretē"), andknowledge ("epistemē"):virtue is a sort of knowledge, perhaps 'knowledge of good andevil ', and it is this knowledge that is required to reach the ultimate good, with "eudaimonia" being the prime candidate for this ultimate good. The second, sometimes called "psychologicaleudaimonism " or "Socratic intellectualism", is the claim that the ultimate good, "eudaimonia", is what all human desires and actions aim to achieve.Plato's middle dialogues present a somewhat different position. In the "Republic", we find a
moral psychology more complex than psychological eudaimonism: we do not only desire our ultimate good; rather the soul, or mind, has three motivating parts - a rational, spirited (approximately, emotional), and appetitive part - and each of these parts has its own desired ends. "Eudaimonia", then, is not simply acquired through knowledge, it requires the correct psychic ordering of this tripartite soul: the rational part must govern the spirited and appetitive part, thereby correctly leading all desires and actions to "eudaimonia" and the principal constituent of "eudaimonia", virtue.Aristotle claims that "every art and every scientific inquiry, and similarly every action and purpose, may be said to aim at some good. Hence 'the good' has been well defined as that at which all things aim." According to Aristotle, the hierarchy of human purposes aim at "eudaimonia" as the highest, most inclusive end. This is the end that everyone in fact aims at, and it is the only end towards which it is worth undertaking means. "Eudaimonia" is constituted, according to Aristotle, not by honor, or wealth, or power, but by rational activity in accordance withvirtue over a complete life. Such activity manifests thevirtue s of character, including,honesty ,pride , friendliness, and wittiness; the intellectual virtues, such asrationality injudgment ; and non-sacrificial (i.e. mutually beneficial) friendships and scientificknowledge (knowledge of things that are fundamental and/or unchanging is the best).Epicurus agrees with Aristotle that happiness ("eudaimonia") is the highest good. However, unlike Aristotle, he identifies happiness with pleasure. Epicurus presents two main arguments. The first defends the claim that pleasure is the only thing that people do, as a matter of fact, value for its own sake. The second, which fits in well with Epicurus'empiricism , supposedly lies in one's introspective experience: one immediately perceives that pleasure is good and that pain is bad, in the same way that one immediately perceives that fire is hot. Thus, as something immediately apparent, no further argument is needed to show the goodness of pleasure or the badness of pain. Although all pleasures are good and all pains evil, Epicurus does not believe that all pleasures are "choiceworthy" or all pains unchoiceworthy. Instead, one should calculate what is in one's long-term self-interest, and forgo what will bring pleasure in the short-term if doing so will ultimately lead to pain in the long-term.The
Stoics believe that virtue is necessary and sufficient for eudaimonia. Virtue consists of living according to Nature, so eudaimonia is achieved by living according to Nature's will. However, no one (except the fictional "sage") can ever achieve perfect virtue, and everyone is always equally and completely vicious. The best a non-sage can do is to act "befittingly," or in the same way that a perfectly virtuous sage would in the same situation. No one will ever achieve perfect virtue, and therefore eudaimonia, but one can approach it. [Brennan, "The Stoic Life""']ee also
*
Eudaimonism
*Nicomachean Ethics
*Virtue ethics
*Fellowship of Reason
*Humanism
Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.