[cite book|last=Rubin|first=H.|coauthors=Rubin, J.E.|title=Equivalents of the Axiom of Choice, II|publisher=North Holland|Place=New York, NY|year=1985|pages=185|id=ISBN 0-444-87708-8] ](Of course this is trivial if the cardinal numbers "mi" and "ni" are finite and the index set "I" is finite. If "I" is empty, then the left sum is the empty sum and therefore 0, while the right hand product is the empty product and therefore 1).
König's theorem is remarkable because of the strict inequality in the conclusion. There are many easy rules for the arithmetic of infinite sums and products of cardinals in which one can only conclude a weak inequality ≤, for example: IF for all "i" in "I", THEN we can only conclude : since, for example, setting & where the index set "I" is the natural numbers, yields the sum for boths sides and we have a strict equality.
Corollaries of König's theorem
*If is a cardinal then If we take "mi" = 1, and "ni" = 2 for each "i" in κ, then the left hand side of the above inequality is just κ, while the right hand side is 2κ, the cardinality of functions from κ to {0,1}, that is, the cardinality of the power set of κ. Thus, König's theorem gives us an alternate proof of Cantor's theorem. (Historically of course Cantor's theorem was proved much earlier.)
Axiom of choice
One way of stating the axiom of choice is "An arbitrary Cartesian product of non-empty sets is non-empty.". Let "Bi" be a non-empty set for each "i" in "I". Let "Ai" = {} for each "i" in "I". Thus by König's theorem, we have:
*If