- König's theorem (set theory)
:"For other uses, see
König's theorem ."In
set theory , König's theorem (named after the Hungarian mathematicianGyula König ) colloquially states that if the axiom of choice holds, "I" is a set, "mi" and "ni" arecardinal number s for every "i" in "I", and m_i < n_i ! for every "i" in "I" then :sum_{iin I}m_iThe "sum" here is the cardinality of the
disjoint union of the sets "mi" and the product is the cardinality of thecartesian product . However, this formulation cannot even be stated without the use of some form of theAxiom of Choice .Details
The precise statement of the result: if "I" is a set , "Ai" and "Bi" are sets for every "i" in "I", and A_i
for every "i" in "I" then :sum_{iin I}A_i < means "strictly less than inwhere cardinality ," i.e. there is aninjective function from "Ai" to "Bi," but not one going the other way. The union involved need not be disjoint (a non-disjoint union can't be any bigger than the disjoint version, also assuming theaxiom of choice ). In this formulation, König's theorem is equivalent to theAxiom of Choice . cite book|last=Rubin|first=H.|coauthors=Rubin, J.E.|title=Equivalents of the Axiom of Choice, II|publisher=North Holland|Place=New York, NY|year=1985|pages=185|id=ISBN 0-444-87708-8](Of course this is trivial if the cardinal numbers "mi" and "ni" are finite and the index set "I" is finite. If "I" is empty, then the left sum is the empty sum and therefore 0, while the right hand product is the
empty product and therefore 1).König's theorem is remarkable because of the strict inequality in the conclusion. There are many easy rules for the arithmetic of infinite sums and products of cardinals in which one can only conclude a weak inequality ≤, for example: IF m_i < n_i ! for all "i" in "I", THEN we can only conclude :sum_{iin I} m_i le sum_{iin I} n_i since, for example, setting m_i = 1 & n_i = 2 where the index set "I" is the natural numbers, yields the sum aleph_0 for boths sides and we have a strict equality.
Corollaries of König's theorem
*If kappa, is a cardinal then kappa < 2^{kappa}.!If we take "mi" = 1, and "ni" = 2 for each "i" in κ, then the left hand side of the above inequality is just κ, while the right hand side is 2κ, the cardinality of functions from κ to {0,1}, that is, the cardinality of the power set of κ. Thus, König's theorem gives us an alternate proof of
Cantor's theorem . (Historically of course Cantor's theorem was proved much earlier.)Axiom of choice
One way of stating the axiom of choice is "An arbitrary Cartesian product of non-empty sets is non-empty.". Let "Bi" be a non-empty set for each "i" in "I". Let "Ai" = {} for each "i" in "I". Thus by König's theorem, we have:
*If forall iin I({}, then That is, the Cartesian product of the given non-empty sets, "B i", has a larger cardinality than the sum of empty sets. Thus it is non-empty which is just what the axiom of choice states. Since the axiom of choice follows from König's theorem, we will use it freely and implicitly when discussing consequences of the theorem.König's theorem and cofinality
König's theorem has also important consequences for
cofinality of cardinal numbers.*If kappagealeph_0, then kappa
.Choose a strictly increasing cf(κ)-sequence of cardinals approaching κ. Each of them is less than κ, so their sum which is κ is less than the product of cf(κ) copies of κ. According to
Easton's theorem , the next consequence of König's theorem is the only nontrivial constraint on the continuum function forregular cardinal s.*If kappageqaleph_0 and lambdageq 2, then kappa
.Let mu = lambda^kappa !. Suppose that, contrary to this corollary, kappa ge cf(mu). Then using the previous corollary, mu , a contradiction. Thus the supposition must be false and this corollary must be true. A proof of König's theorem
Assuming
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory , including especially theaxiom of choice , we can prove the theorem. Remember that we are given forall iin Iquad A_i, and we want to show sum_{iin I}A_i . First, we show that there is an injection from the sum to the product. Using the axiom of choice, for each "i" we choose an injection "fi" from "Ai" to "Bi". Notice that "fi" cannot be a surjection because then its inverse would be an injection from "Bi" to "Ai". So, for each "i", there must be an element of "Bi" not in the range of "fi". Using the axiom of choice again, we choose such an "xi" for each "i". Define "g" on the sum by "g"("i,a") ("j") = "fi"("a") when "j" = "i" and "a" is an element of "Ai" and "g"("i,a") ("j") = "xj" when "j" ≠ "i" and "a" is an element of "Ai". Since "fi"("a") ≠ "xi" for each "i", "g" is an injection from the sum to the product.
Second, we show that there is no injection "h" from the product to the sum. Suppose, to the contrary, that such an "h" existed. In a similar manner to
Cantor's diagonal argument , we will construct an element "e" of the product, which cannot have a value under "h". For each "i" in "I", construct a partial function "fi" from "Ai" to "Bi" by "fi"("a") = "d"("i") if there is a "d" in the product such that "h"("d") = ("i","a"). (This is a partial function because "h" is an injection, so the "d" is unique.) If "fi" were a surjection, then, using the axiom of choice, we could construct an injection "g" from "Bi" into "Ai" ("g" would be a right inverse of "f""i"), contradicting the hypothesis. Hence, for each "i" in "I", there are elements of "Bi" not in the image of "fi". So using the axiom of choice again, we choose "e"("i") in "Bi" but not in the image of "fi". Consider, now, the value of "h"("e") = ("i","c") with "c" in "Ai". But then "fi"("c") = "e"("i"), contradicting the construction of "e". Hence no such injection can exist, and the product is strictly larger in cardinality than the sum.External links
* [http://planetmath.org/encyclopedia/KonigsTheorem.html König's theorem] article on PlanetMath, includes a proof
References
*cite book | author=M. Holz, K. Steffens and E. Weitz | title=Introduction to Cardinal Arithmetic | publisher=Birkhäuser | year=1999 | id=ISBN 3764361247
Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.