König's lemma

König's lemma

König's lemma or König's infinity lemma is a theorem in graph theory due to Dénes Kőnig (1936). It gives a sufficient condition for an infinite graph to have an infinitely long path. The computability aspects of this theorem have been thoroughly investigated by researchers in mathematical logic, especially in computability theory. This theorem also has important roles in constructive mathematics and proof theory. Note that, although Kőnig's name is properly spelled with a double acute accent, the lemma named after him is customarily spelled with an umlaut.

Statement of the lemma

If "G" is a connected graph with infinitely many vertices such that every vertex has finite degree (that is, each vertex is adjacent to only finitely many other vertices) then every vertex of "G" is part of an infinitely long simple path, that is, a path with no repeated vertices.

A common special case of this is that every tree that contains infinitely many vertices, each having finite degree, has at least one infinite simple path.

Note that the vertex degrees must be finite, but need not be bounded: it is possible to have one vertex of degree 10, another of degree 100, a third of degree 1000, and so on.

Proof

For the proof, assume that the graph consists of infinitely many vertices v_i and is connected.

Start with any vertex "v"1. Every one of the infinitely many vertices of "G" can be reached from "v"1 with a simple path, and each such path must start with one of the finitely many vertices adjacent to "v"1. There must be one of those adjacent vertices through which infinitely many vertices can be reached without going through "v"1. If there were not, then the entire graph would be the union of finitely many finite sets, and thus finite, contradicting the assumption that the graph is infinite. We may thus pick one of these vertices and call it "v"2.

Now infinitely many vertices of "G" can be reached from "v"2 with a simple path which doesn't use the vertex "v"1. Each such path must start with one of the finitely many vertices adjacent to "v"2. So an argument similar to the one above shows that there must be one of those adjacent vertices through which infinitely many vertices can be reached; pick one and call it "v"3.

Continuing in this fashion, an infinite simple path can be constructed by mathematical induction. At each step, the induction hypothesis states that there are infinitely many nodes reachable by a simple path from a particular node v_i that does not go through one of a finite set of vertices. The induction argument is that one of the vertices adjacent to v_i satisfies the induction hypothesis, even when v_i is added to the finite set.

The proof just given may not be considered constructive, because at each step it uses a proof by contradiction to establish that there exists an adjacent vertex from which infinitely many other vertices can be reached. Facts about the computational aspects of the lemma suggest that no proof can be given that would be considered constructive by the main schools of constructive mathematics.

Computability aspects

The computability aspects of König's lemma have been thoroughly investigated. The form of König's lemma most convenient for this purpose is the one which states that any infinite finitely branching subtree of omega^{ has an infinite path. Here omega denotes the set of natural numbers and omega^{ the canonical tree of all finite sequences of natural numbers, ordered by extension. Each finite sequence can be identified with a partial function from omega to itself, and each infinite path can be identified with a total function. This allows for an analysis using the techniques of computability theory.

A subtree of omega^{ in which each sequence has only finitely many immediate extensions (that is, the tree has finite degree when viewed as a graph) is called finitely branching. Not every infinite subtree of omega^{ has an infinite path, but König's lemma shows that any finitely branching subtree must have a path.

For any subtree "T" of omega^{ the notation Ext("T") denotes the set of nodes of "T" through which there is an infinite path. Even when "T" is computable the set Ext("T") may not be computable. Every subtree "T" of omega^{ that has a path has a path computable from Ext("T").

It is known that there are finitely branching computable subtrees of omega^{ that have no arithmetical path, and indeed no hyperarithmetical path. Every computable subtree of omega^{ with a path must have a path computable from Kleene's O, the canonical Pi^1_1 complete set. This is because the set Ext("T") is always Sigma^1_1 (see analytical hierarchy) when "T" is computable.

A finer analysis has been conducted for computably bounded trees. A subtree of omega^{ is called computably bounded or recursively bounded if there is a computable function "f" from omega to omega such that for all "n" there is no sequence in the tree whose "n"th element is larger than "f(n)". Thus "f" gives a bound for how “wide” the tree is. The following basis theorems apply to infinite, computably bounded, computable subtrees of omega^{< omega},.
* Any such tree has a path computable from 0', the canonical Turing complete set that can decide the halting problem.
* Any such tree has a path that is low. This is known as the low basis theorem.
* Any such tree has a path that is "hyperimmune free". This means that any function computable from the path is dominated by a computable function.
* For any noncomputable subset "X" of omega the tree has a path that does not compute "X".

A weak form of König's lemma which states that every infinite binary tree has an infinite branch is used to define the subsystem WKL0 of second-order arithmetic. This subsystem has an important role in reverse mathematics. Here a binary tree is one in which every term of every sequence in the tree is 0 or 1, which is to say the tree is computably bounded via the constant function 2. The full form of König's lemma is not provable in WKL0, but is equivalent to the stronger subsystem ACA0.

Relationship to constructive mathematics and compactness

The fan theorem of Brouwer is, from a classical point of view, the contrapositive of a form of König's lemma. A subset "S" of {0,1}^{ is called a "bar" if any function from omega to the set {0,1} has some initial segment in "S". A bar is "detachable" if every sequence is either in the bar or not in the bar (this assumption is required because the theorem is ordinarily considered in situations where the law of the excluded middle is not assumed). A bar is "uniform" if there is some number "N" so that any function from omega to {0,1} has an initial segment in the bar of length no more than N. Brouwer's fan theorem says that any detachable bar is uniform.

This can be proven in a classical setting by considering the bar as an open covering of the compact topological space {0,1}^omega. Each sequence in the bar represents a basic open set of this space, and these basic open sets cover the space by assumption. By compactness, this cover has a finite subcover. The "N" of the fan theorem can be taken to be the length of the longest sequence whose basic open set is in the finite subcover. This topological proof can be used in classical mathematics to show that the following form of König's lemma holds: for any natural number "k", any infinite subtree of the tree {0,ldots,k}^{ has an infinite path.

Relationship with the axiom of choice

König's lemma may be considered to be a choice principle; the first proof above illustrates the relationship between the lemma and the axiom of dependent choice. At each step of the induction, a vertex with a particular property must be selected. Although it is proved that at least one appropriate vertex exists, if there is more than one suitable vertex there may be no canonical choice. This issue cannot arise if the graph is assumed to be countable.

König's lemma is essentially the restriction of the axiom of dependent choice to entire relations "R" such that for each "x" there are only finitely many "z" such that "xRz". The form of König's lemma that says "Every infinite finitely branching tree has an infinite path" is equivalent to the principle that every sequence of finite sets has a choice function (compare Levy [1979, Exercise IX.2.18] ). Thus there are models of ZF set theory, without choice, in which this form of König's lemma fails.

References

*cite conference
author = Cenzer, D.
title = Pi^0_1 classes in recursion theory
booktitle = Handbook of Computability Theory
publisher = Elsevier
date = 1999
pages = 37–85
id = ISBN 0444898824

*cite book
author = Kőnig, D.
authorlink = Dénes Kőnig
title = Theorie der Endlichen und Unendlichen Graphen: Kombinatorische Topologie der Streckenkomplexe
location = Leipzig
publisher = Akad. Verlag
year = 1936

*cite book
author = Levy, A.
title = Basic Set Theory
year = 1979
publisher = Springer
Reprint Dover 2002, ISBN 0486420795.

*cite book
author = Simpson, S.
title = Subsystems of Second Order Arithmetic
publisher = Springer
year = 1999

*cite book
author = Soare, R.
title = Recursively Enumerable Sets and Degrees
publisher = Springer
year = 1987

External links

* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/mathematics-constructive/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Constructive Mathematics]
*
* The Mizar project has completely formalized and automatically checked the proof of a version of König's lemma in the file [http://mizar.org/JFM/Vol3/trees_2.html TREES_2] .


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Нужно решить контрольную?

Look at other dictionaries:

  • König — is the German language word for King . Family names derived from König are also spelled without the umlaut ö as Koenig or without correct transliteration of the umlaut just as Konig. People named König or Konig *Arthur König (1856 1901), German… …   Wikipedia

  • König (Begriffsklärung) — König bezeichnet einen Monarchen, siehe König, auch König (Spanien) einen Familiennamen, siehe König (Familienname) eine Schachfigur, siehe König (Schach) eine Spielkarte, siehe König (Spielkarte) ein Kartenspiel, siehe König (Kartenspiel) den… …   Deutsch Wikipedia

  • Kőnig — Dénes Kőnig (* 21. September 1884 in Budapest; † 19. Oktober 1944 ebenda) war ein ungarischer Mathematiker, der im Bereich der Graphentheorie arbeitete. Er war Sohn des Mathematikers Gyula Kőnig. Inhaltsverzeichnis 1 Leben 2 Dénes Kőnig Preis …   Deutsch Wikipedia

  • König's theorem — There are several theorems with the name König s theorem:* König s theorem (set theory), named after the Hungarian mathematician Julius König * König s theorem (graph theory), named after his son Dénes Kőnig * König s theorem (kinetics), named… …   Wikipedia

  • Lemma von König — Das Lemma von König oder Königslemma ist ein Theorem der Graphentheorie von Dénes Kőnig (1936). Die Berechenbarkeit des Lemmas wurde gründlich in der Mathematischen Logik erforscht. Dénes Kőnig wird korrekterweise mit Doppelakut geschrieben. Das… …   Deutsch Wikipedia

  • König von Norwegen — Die Liste der norwegischen Könige beginnt traditionell mit Harald Hårfagre, obgleich er nur über einen Teil Westnorwegens eine gewisse Oberherrschaft ausübte und sich sein Königtum wesentlich vom Königtum des Mittelalters unterschied. Was die… …   Deutsch Wikipedia

  • Denes König — Dénes Kőnig (* 21. September 1884 in Budapest; † 19. Oktober 1944 ebenda) war ein ungarischer Mathematiker, der im Bereich der Graphentheorie arbeitete. Er war Sohn des Mathematikers Gyula Kőnig. Inhaltsverzeichnis 1 Leben 2 Dénes Kőnig Preis …   Deutsch Wikipedia

  • Dénes König — Dénes Kőnig (* 21. September 1884 in Budapest; † 19. Oktober 1944 ebenda) war ein ungarischer Mathematiker, der im Bereich der Graphentheorie arbeitete. Er war Sohn des Mathematikers Gyula Kőnig. Inhaltsverzeichnis 1 Leben 2 Dénes Kőnig Preis …   Deutsch Wikipedia

  • Dénes Kőnig — Born September 21, 1884(1884 09 21) Budapest …   Wikipedia

  • Dénes Kőnig — (* 21. September 1884 in Budapest; † 19. Oktober 1944 ebenda) war ein ungarischer Mathematiker, der im Bereich der Graphentheorie arbeitete. Er war Sohn des Mathematikers Gyula Kőnig. Inhaltsverzeichnis 1 Leben 2 Dénes Kőnig Preis …   Deutsch Wikipedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”