Hallucinations in the sane

Hallucinations in the sane

A hallucination may occur in a person in a state of good mental and physical health, even in the apparent absence of a transient trigger factor such as fatigue, intoxication, or sensory deprivation.

It is not yet widely recognised that hallucinatory experiences are not merely the prerogative of the insane, or normal people in abnormal states, but that they occur spontaneously in a significant proportion of the normal population, when in good health and not undergoing particular stress or other abnormal circumstance.

The evidence for this statement has been accumulating for more than a century. Studies of hallucinatory experience in the sane go back to 1886 and the early work of the Society for Psychical Research, [Gurney, E., Myers, F.W.H. and Podmore, F. (1886). "Phantasms of the Living", Vols. I and II. London: Trubner and Co..] [Sidgwick, Eleanor; Johnson, Alice; and others (1894). Report on the Census of Hallucinations, London: "Proceedings of the Society for Psychical Research", Vol. X.] which suggested approximately 10% of the population had experienced at least one hallucinatory episode in the course of their life. More recent studies have validated these findings; the precise incidence found varies with the nature of the episode and the criteria of ‘hallucination’ adopted, but the basic finding is now well-supported. [See Slade, P.D. and Bentall, R.P. (1988). "Sensory Deception: a scientific analysis of hallucination". London: Croom Helm, for a review.]

Types

Of particular interest, for reasons to be discussed below, are those hallucinatory experiences of the sane which are characterised by extreme perceptual realism, sometimes to the extent that the subject does not at first achieve insight, indeed may only achieve insight after the experience has ended.

Apparitional experiences

An apparitional experience may be defined as one in which a subject seems to perceive some person or thing that is not really there. Self-selected samples tend to report a predominance of human figures, but apparitions of animals, [See, for example, Green, C., and McCreery, C. (1975). "Apparitions". London: Hamish Hamilton, pp. 192-196.] and even objects ["Ibid"., pp. 197-199.] are also reported. It is interesting to note that the majority of the human figures reported in such samples are not recognised by the subject, and of those who are, not all are of deceased persons, apparitions of living persons also being reported. ["Ibid.," pp. 178-183.]

Out-of-body experiences

Out-of-body experiences (OBEs) have become to some extent conflated in the public mind with the concept of the near-death experience. However, the evidence suggests that the majority of out-of-body experiences do not occur near death, but in conditions of either very high or very low arousal. [Irwin, H.J. (1985). "Flight of Mind: a psychological study of the out-of-body experience." Metuchen, New Jersey: The Scarecrow Press.] McCreery [McCreery, C. (2008). Dreams and psychosis: a new look at an old hypothesis. "Psychological Paper No. 2008-1". Oxford: Oxford Forum. [http://www.celiagreen.com/charlesmccreery/dreams-and-psychosis.pdf Online PDF] ] has suggested that this latter paradox may be explained by reference to the fact that sleep may be approached, not only by the conventional route of low arousal and deafferentation, but also by the less familiar route of extreme stress and hyper-arousal. [ Oswald, I. (1962). "Sleeping and Waking: Physiology and Psychology." Amsterdam: Elsevier.] On this model OBEs represent the intrusion of Stage 1 sleep processes into waking consciousness.

OBEs are to be regarded as hallucinatory on the grounds that they are perceptual or quasi-perceptual experiences in which by definition the ostensible viewpoint is not coincident with the physical body of the subject. Therefore the normal sensory input, if any, that the subject is receiving during the experience cannot correspond exactly to the perceptual representation of the world in the subject’s consciousness.

As with hallucinatory experiences in general, attempts to survey samples of the general population have suggested that such experiences are relatively common, incidence figures of between 15 and 25 percent being commonly reported. [See Irwin, "op.cit.," for a review.] The variation is presumably to be accounted for by the different types of populations sampled and the different criteria of ‘out-of-body experience’ used.

Dreams and lucid dreams

A dream has been defined by some (e.g. "Encyclopaedia Britannica") as a hallucinatory experience during sleep.

A lucid dream may be defined as one in which the dreamer is aware that he or she is asleep and dreaming. The term ‘lucid dream’ was first used by the Dutch physician Frederik van Eeden, [van Eeden, F. (1913). A study of dreams. "Proceedings of the Society for Psychical Research", 26, Part 47, pp. 431-461.] who studied his own dreams of this type. The word ‘lucid’ refers to the fact that the subject has achieved insight into his or her condition, rather than the perceptual quality of the experience. Nevertheless, it is one of the features of lucid dreams that they can have an extremely high quality of perceptual realism, to the extent that the dreamer may spend time examining and admiring the perceptual environment and the way it appears to imitate that of waking life. [See Green, C. (1968). "Lucid Dreams." London: Hamish Hamilton, for examples.]

Lucid dreams by definition occur during sleep, but they may be regarded as hallucinatory experiences in the same way as non-lucid dreams of a vivid perceptual nature may be regarded as hallucinatory, that is they are examples of 'an experience having the character of sense perception, but without relevant or adequate sensory stimulation […] ' [Drever, (1952). "A Dictionary of Psychology". London: Penguin.]

False awakenings

A false awakening is one in which the subject seems to wake up, whether from a lucid or a non-lucid dream, but is in fact still asleep. [Cf. Green C. and McCreery C. (1994). "Lucid Dreaming: the Paradox of Consciousness During Sleep". London: Routledge. Chapter 7.] Sometimes the experience is so realistic perceptually (the sleeper seeming to wake in his or her own bedroom, for example) that insight is not achieved at once, or even until the dreamer really wakes up and realises that what has occurred was hallucinatory. Such experiences seem particularly liable to occur to those who deliberately cultivate lucid dreams. However, they may also occur spontaneously and be associated with the experience of sleep paralysis.

ubtypes

Auditory hallucinations

Auditory hallucinations, and in particular the hearing of a voice, are thought of as particularly characteristic of people suffering from schizophrenia. However, normal subjects also report auditory hallucinations to a surprising extent. For example, Bentall and Slade [ Bentall R.P. and Slade P.D. (1985). Reliability of a scale measuring disposition towards hallucination: a brief report. "Personality and Individual Differences", 6, 527 529.] found that as many as 15.4% of a population of 150 male students were prepared to endorse the statement ‘In the past I have had the experience of hearing a person’s voice and then found that no one was there’. They add: ‘ […] no less that 17.5% of the [subjects] were prepared to score the item “I often hear a voice speaking my thoughts aloud” as “Certainly Applies”. This latter item is usually regarded as a first-rank symptom of schizophrenia […] ’

Green and McCreery [Green and McCreery, "Apparitions", "op.cit. " p.85.] found that 14% of their 1800 self-selected subjects reported a purely auditory hallucination, and of these nearly half involved the hearing of articulate or inarticulate human speech sounds. An example of the former would be the case of an engineer facing a difficult professional decision, who, while sitting in a cinema, heard a voice saying, ‘loudly and distinctly’: ‘You can’t do it you know’. He adds: 'It was so clear and resonant that I turned and looked at my companion who was gazing placidly at the screen […] I was amazed and somewhat relieved when it became apparent that I was the only person who had heard anything.' [Ibid., pp. 85-86.]

This case would be an example of what Posey and Losch [ Posey, T.B. and Losch, M.E. (1983). Auditory hallucinations of hearing voices in 375 normal subjects. "Imagination, Cognition and Personality", 3, 99-113.] call ‘hearing a comforting or advising voice that is not perceived as being one’s own thoughts’. They estimated that approximately 10% of their population of 375 American college students had had this type of experience.

The ‘Sense of Presence’

This is a paradoxical experience in which the person has a strong feeling of the presence of another person, sometimes recognised, sometimes unrecognised, but without any apparently justifying sensory stimulus.

The nineteenth-century American psychologist and philosopher William James described the experience thus: 'From the way in which this experience is spoken of by those who have had it, it would appear to be an extremely definite and positive state of mind, coupled with a belief in the reality of its object quite as strong as any direct sensation ever gives. And yet no sensation seems to be connected with it at all... The phenomenon would seem to be due to a pure conception becoming saturated with the sort of stinging urgency which ordinarily only sensations bring.' [James, W. (1890; 1950). "Principles of Psychology", Volume II. New York, Dover Publications, pp. 322-3. ]

The following is an example of this type of experience: 'My husband died in June 1945, and 26 years afterwards when I was at Church, I felt him standing beside me during the singing of a hymn. I felt I would see him if I turned my head. The feeling was so strong I was reduced to tears. I had not been thinking of him before I felt his presence. I had not had this feeling before that day, neither has it happened since then.' [Green and McCreery, "Apparitions", "op.cit"., p.118.]

Experiences of this kind appear to meet all but one of the normal criteria of hallucination. For example, Slade and Bentall proposed the following working definition of a hallucination: 'Any percept-like experience which (a) occurs in the absence of an appropriate stimulus, (b) has the full force or impact of the corresponding actual (real) perception, and (c) is not amenable to direct and voluntary control by the experiencer.' [Slade and Bentall, op.cit., p.23.] The experience quoted above certainly meets the second and third of these three criteria. One might add that the 'presence' in such a case is experienced as located in a definite position in external physical space. In this respect it may be said to be more hallucinatory than, for example, some hypnagogic imagery, which may be experienced as external to the subject but located in a mental ‘space’ of its own. [ Leaning, F.E. (1925). An introductory study of hypnagogic phenomena. "Proceedings of the Society for Psychical Research", 35, 289-409. ] [Mavromatis, A. (1987). "Hypnagogia: the Unique State of Consciousness Between Wakefulness and Sleep". London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. ]

Hallucinations in bereavement

Rees [Rees, W.D. (1971). The hallucinations of widowhood. "British Medical Journal", 4, 37-41. ] conducted a study of 293 widowed people living in a particular area of mid-Wales. He found that 14% of those interviewed reported having had a visual hallucination of their deceased spouse, 13.3% an auditory one and 2.7% a tactile one. These categories overlapped to some extent as some people reported a hallucinatory experience in more than one modality. Of interest in light of the previous heading was the fact that 46.7% of the sample reported experiencing the presence of the deceased spouse.

Theoretical implications

Psychological

The main importance of hallucinations in the sane to theoretical psychology lies in their relevance to the debate between the disease model versus the dimensional model of psychosis. According to the disease model, psychotic states such as those associated with schizophrenia and manic-depression, represent symptoms of an underlying disease process, which is dichotomous in nature; i.e. a given subject either does or does not have the disease, just as a person either does or does not have a physical disease such as tuberculosis. According to the dimensional model, by contrast, the population at large is ranged along a normally distributed continuum or dimension, which has been variously labelled as psychoticism (H.J.Eysenck), schizotypy (Gordon Claridge) or psychosis-proneness. [For a discussion of the concept of schizotypy and its variants, cf. McCreery, C. and Claridge, G. (2002). Healthy schizotypy: the case of out-of-the-body experiences. "Personality and Individual Differences", 32, 141-154.]

The occurrence of spontaneous hallucinatory experiences in sane persons who are enjoying good physical health at the time, and who are not drugged or in other unusual physical states of a transient nature such as extreme fatigue, would appear to provide support for the dimensional model. The alternative to this view requires one to posit some hidden or latent disease process, of which such experiences are a symptom or precursor, an explanation which would appear to beg the question.

Philosophical

The "argument from hallucination" has traditionally been one of those used by proponents of the philosophical theory of representationalism as against the theory of direct realism. Representationalism holds that when perceiving the world we are not in direct contact with it, as common sense suggests, but only in direct contact with a representation of the world in consciousness. That representation may be a more or less accurate one depending on our circumstances, the state of our health, and so on. Direct realism, on the other hand, holds that the common sense or unthinking view of perception is correct, and that when perceiving the world we should be regarded as in direct contact with it, unmediated by any representation in consciousness.

Clearly, during an apparitional experience, for example, the correspondence between how the subject is perceiving the world and how the world really is at that moment is distinctly imperfect. At the same time the experience may present itself to the subject as indistinguishable from normal perception. McCreery [McCreery, C. (2006). "Perception and Hallucination: the Case for Continuity." "Philosophical Paper No. 2006-1". Oxford: Oxford Forum. [http://www.celiagreen.com/charlesmccreery/perception.pdf Online PDF] ] has argued that such empirical phenomena strengthen the case for representationalism as against direct realism.

References

Further reading

* Birchwood, Max J., Chadwick, Paul, and Trower, Peter (1996). "Cognitive Therapy for Delusions, Voices and Paranoia." New York: John Wiley & Sons Inc.
* Johnson, Fred H., (1978). "The Anatomy of Hallucinations". Chicago: Nelson-Hall.
* Pearson, R.S. (2005) "The Experience of Hallucinations in Religious Practice". Seattle: Telical Books.

See also

*Lucid dream
*False awakening
*Out-of-body experience
*Apparitional experience
*Schizotypy
*Perception
*Philosophy of perception
*Representationalism
*Trance


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Поможем решить контрольную работу

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Hallucinations in those who are not mentally ill — A hallucination may occur in a person in a state of good mental and physical health, even in the apparent absence of a transient trigger factor such as fatigue, intoxication or sensory deprivation.It is not yet widely recognised that… …   Wikipedia

  • The Science of Sleep — Infobox Film name = The Science of Sleep caption = The Science of Sleep Theatrical Poster director = Michel Gondry writer = Michel Gondry starring = Gael García Bernal Charlotte Gainsbourg Alain Chabat Miou Miou Dan Fleury Emma de Caunes Aurélia… …   Wikipedia

  • The Hitchhiker's Guide to the Galaxy Tertiary to Quintessential Phases — The Tertiary Phase , Quandary Phase and Quintessential Phase are radio adaptations of the books Life, the Universe and Everything , So Long, and Thanks For All the Fish and Mostly Harmless recorded in 2003 and 2004 by Above the Title Productions… …   Wikipedia

  • The Signal-Man — is a short story by Charles Dickens, first published as part of the Mugby Junction collection in the 1866 Christmas edition of All the Year Round .The signal man of the title tells the narrator of a ghost that has been haunting him. Each spectral …   Wikipedia

  • The Labours of Hercules — Infobox Book | name = The Labours of Hercules title orig = translator = image caption = Dust jacket illustration of the US (true first) edition. See Publication history (below) for UK first edition jacket image. author = Agatha Christie… …   Wikipedia

  • The Black Corridor — Infobox Book | name = The Black Corridor title orig = translator = image caption = Cover of the first edition author = Michael Moorcock illustrator = cover artist = Leo and Diane Dillon country = United States language = English series = subject …   Wikipedia

  • So Long, and Thanks for All the Fish — Infobox Book name = So Long, and Thanks for All the Fish title orig = translator = image caption = Ballantine Books, Paperback, 1999. author = Douglas Adams illustrator = cover artist = Peter Cross, U.S. hardcover country = United Kingdom and… …   Wikipedia

  • Oggy and the Cockroaches — Title Format Animated Comedy Created by Jean Yves Raimbaud Terry Klassen Country of orig …   Wikipedia

  • List of The Batman villains — The following is a list of the villains who have appeared in the Batman animated series, The Batman , their background in the show and their likely inspirations. NOTOC =Bane= * Voice Actor: Joaquim de Almeida (in Traction ); Ron Perlman (in Team… …   Wikipedia

  • Political abuse of psychiatry in the Soviet Union — Soviet Union …   Wikipedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”