Illocutionary act

Illocutionary act

Illocutionary act is a technical term introduced by John L. Austin in investigations concerning what he calls 'performative' and 'constative utterances'. According to Austin's original exposition in "How to Do Things With Words", an illocutionary act is an act (1) for the performance of which I must make it clear to some other person that the act is performed (Austin speaks of the 'securing of uptake'), and (2) the performance of which involves the production of what Austin calls 'conventional consequences' as, e.g., rights, commitments, or obligations. For example, in order to successfully perform a promise I must make clear to my audience that the promise occurs, and undertake an obligation to do the promised thing: hence promising is an illocutionary act in the present sense. However, for certain reasons, among them insufficient knowledge of Austin's original exposition, the term 'illocutionary act' is nowadays understood in a number of other ways.

Many define the term with reference to examples, saying such things as that any speech act "like stating, asking, commanding, promising, and so on" is an illocutionary act; they then often fail to give any sense of the expression "illocutionary act" capable of making clear what being an illocutionary act essentially consists in.

It is also often emphasised that Austin introduced the illocutionary act by means of a contrast with other kinds of acts: the illocutionary act, he says, is an act performed "in" saying something, as contrasted with a locutionary act, the act "of" saying something, and also contrasted with a perlocutionary act, an act performed "by" saying something.

Still another conception of an illocutionary act goes back to Schiffer's famous book 'Meaning' (1972, 103), in which the illocutionary act is represented as just the act of meaning something.

According to the conception Bach and Harnish adopt in 'Linguistic Communication and Speech Acts' (1979), an illocutionary act is an attempt to communicate, which they again analyse as the expressing of an attitude.

According to a widespread opinion, an adequate and useful account of "illocutionary acts" has been provided by John R. Searle (e.g., 1969, 1979). In recent years, however, it has repeatedly been doubted whether Searle's account is well-founded. A wide-ranging critique is in F C Doerge [http://w210.ub.uni-tuebingen.de/dbt/volltexte/2006/2273/ "Illocutionary Acts"] [Doerge (Friedrich Christoph), "Illocutionary Acts - Austin's Account and What Searle Made Out of It" Tuebingen University (2006) [http://w210.ub.uni-tuebingen.de/dbt/volltexte/2006/2273/] ] . Whole collections of articles examining Searle's account are: Burkhardt 1990 [Burkhardt, Armin (ed.), Speech Acts, Meaning and Intentions: Critical Approaches to the Philosophy of John R. Searle. Berlin / New York 1990.] and Lepore / van Gulick 1991 [Lepore, Ernest / van Gulick, Robert (eds): John Searle and his Critics. Oxford: Basil Blackwell 1991.] .

Illocutionary force

Several speech act theorists, including Austin himself, make use of the notion of an "illocutionary force". In Austin's original account, the notion remains rather unclear. Some followers of Austin, such as David Holdcroft, view illocutionary force as the property of an utterance to be made with the "intention" to perform a certain illocutionary act -- rather than as the successful performance of the act (which is supposed to further require the appropriateness of certain circumstances). According to this conception, the utterance of "I bet you five pounds that it will rain" may well have an illocutionary force even if the addressee doesn't hear it. However, Bach and Harnish assume illocutionary force just in case this or that illocutionary act is actually (successfully) performed. According to this conception, the addressee must have been heard and understood that the speaker intends to make a bet with them in order for the utterance to have 'illocutionary force'.

If we adopt the notion of illocutionary "force" as an aspect of meaning, then it appears that the (intended) 'force' of certain sentences, or utterances, is not quite obvious. If someone says, "It sure is cold in here", there are several different illocutionary acts that might be aimed at by the utterance. The utterer might intend to describe the room, in which case the illocutionary force would be that of 'describing'. But she might also intend to criticise someone who should have kept the room warm. Or it might be meant as a request to someone to close the window. These forces may be interrelated: it may be by way of stating that the temperature is too cold that one criticises someone else. Such a performance of an illocutionary act by means of the performance of another is referred to as an "indirect speech act".

Illocutionary force indicating devices (IFIDs)

Searle and Vanderveken (1985) often speak about what they call 'illocutionary force indicating devices' (IFIDs). These are supposed to be elements, or aspects of linguistic devices which indicate either (dependent on which conceptions of "illocutionary force" and "illocutionary act" are adopted) that the utterance is made with a certain illocutionary force, or else that it constitutes the performance of a certain illocutionary act. In English, for example, the interrogative mood is supposed to indicate that the utterance is (intended as) a question; the directive mood indicates that the utterance is (intended as) a directive illocutionary act (an order, a request, etc.); the words "I promise" are supposed to indicate that the utterance is (intended as) a promise. Possible IFIDs in English include: word order, stress, intonation contour, punctuation, the mood of the verb, and performative verbs.

Illocutionary negations

Another notion Searle and Vanderveken use is that of an 'illocutionary negation'. The difference of such an 'illocutionary negation' to a 'propositional negation' can be explained by reference to the difference between "I do not promise to come" and "I promise not to come". The first is an illocutionary negation - the 'not' negates the promise. The second is a propositional negation. In the view of Searle and Vanderveken, illocutionary negations change the type of illocutionary act.

ee also

* J. L. Austin
* linguistics
* performative utterance
* perlocutionary act
* pragmatics
* semantics
* Discussion of illocuationary acts in sec. 1 of Stanford Encycolopedia of Philosophy, "Assertion", http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/assertion/.

References

*Alston, William P.. "Illocutionary Acts and Sentence Meaning". Ithaka: Cornell University Press. 2000
*Austin, John L.. "How To Do Things with Words". Oxford: Oxford University Press. 1975 ISBN 0-19-281205-X
*Burkhardt, Armin (ed.). "Speech Acts, Meaning and Intentions: Critical Approaches to the Philosophy of John R. Searle". Berlin / New York 1990 ISBN 0-89925-357-1
*Doerge, Friedrich Christoph. "Illocutionary Acts - Austin's Account and What Searle Made Out of It". Tuebingen 2006. [http://w210.ub.uni-tuebingen.de/dbt/volltexte/2006/2273/]
*Lepore, Ernest / van Gulick, Robert (eds). "John Searle and his Critics". Oxford: Basil Blackwell 1991. ISBN 0-631-15636-4
*Searle, John R.. "Speech Acts". Cambridge University Press. 1969 ISBN 0-521-07184-4
*Searle, John R.. "Expression and Meaning". Cambridge University Press. 1979 ISBN 0-521-22901-4
*Searle, John R. and Daniel Vanderveken. "Foundations of Illocutionary Logic". Cambridge University Press. 1985. ISBN 0-521-26324-7


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Нужно решить контрольную?

Look at other dictionaries:

  • illocutionary act — (illocutionary force ) Term introduced by J. L. Austin, in his book How to Do Things with Words, for an act done in uttering what one does. Thus in saying ‘I promise’ in suitable circumstances I make a promise; in saying ‘Hooray!’ I cheer you on …   Philosophy dictionary

  • illocutionary acts — illocutionary act …   Philosophy dictionary

  • illocutionary — illocution, n. /il euh kyooh sheuh ner ee/, adj. Philos., Ling. pertaining to a linguistic act performed by a speaker in producing an utterance, as suggesting, warning, promising, or requesting. Cf. locutionary, perlocutionary. [1950 55; IL 1 +… …   Universalium

  • illocutionary — adj. pertaining to linguistic act carried out by a speaker in producing an expression …   English contemporary dictionary

  • Speech act — For the US Act, see SPEECH Act of 2010. Speech Act is a technical term in linguistics and the philosophy of language. The contemporary use of the term goes back to John L. Austin s doctrine of locutionary, illocutionary, and perlocutionary acts.… …   Wikipedia

  • Locutionary act — In Linguistics and the Philosophy of mind, a locutionary act is the performance of an utterance, and hence of a speech act. The term equally refers to the surface meaning of an utterance because, according to Austin s posthumous How To Do Things… …   Wikipedia

  • Perlocutionary act — A perlocutionary act (or perlocutionary effect) is a speech act, as viewed at the level of its psychological consequences , such as persuading, convincing, scaring, enlightening, inspiring, or otherwise getting someone to do or realize something …   Wikipedia

  • speech act — noun Any of illocutionary acts, locutionary acts and perlocutionary acts …   Wiktionary

  • John Searle — Infobox Philosopher region = Western Philosophy era = Contemporary philosophy color = #B0C4DE image caption = name = John Rogers Searle birth = July 31, 1932 (age 76) death = school tradition = Analytic notable ideas = Speech acts· Chinese room… …   Wikipedia

  • semantics — semanticist /si man teuh sist/, semantician /see man tish euhn/, n. /si man tiks/, n. (used with a sing. v.) 1. Ling. a. the study of meaning. b. the study of linguistic development by classifying and examining changes in meaning and form. 2.… …   Universalium

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”