Rhetorical reason

Rhetorical reason

"Rhetorical reason" may be defined as the faculty of discovering the crux of the matter, endemic to rhetorical invention, that precedes argumentation.

Aristotle's definition

Aristotle's definition of rhetoric, “The faculty of observing, in any given case, the available means of persuasion”, presupposes a distinction between an art ("techne") of speech–making and a cognitively prior faculty of discovery. That is so because, before one argues a case, one must discover what is at issue. How, for example, does one discover available means of persuasion? One does not simply frolic through fertile fields of "topoi", randomly gathering materials with which to build lines of argument. There is a method endemic to rhetoric which guides the search for those lines of argument that speak most directly to the issue at stake.

George A. Kennedy explains the distinction when he writes that the work of rhetoric, in Aristotle’s view, "is "to discover ["theoresai"] the available means of persuasion" (1.1.1355b25-6). It is thus a theoretical activity and discovers knowledge. This knowledge, which includes words, arguments, and topics, is then used by the orator as the material cause of a speech. There is thus a theoretical art of rhetoric standing behind or above the productive art of speech-making" (1980, p. 63).

Rhetorical invention then, involves more than a "techne"; it is also a faculty of discovery ("dunamis to theoresai")--rhetorical reason.

The Aristotelian approach to invention further assumes that reasoning employed in decision-making is a kind of probable reasoning.

“It assumes that, although the contingencies of nature and of individuals prevent our obtaining certainty about future political and social affairs, we still can use our reason to discover the best course to pursue. Such reasoning applied to human affairs to make decisions about what should be done is rhetorical reasoning issuing in praxis" (Moss 1986, pp. 2, 3).

Moral inquiry

Judgments about what should be done in the future are generally matters of shared inquiry and are always contingent (based on probability). Shared inquiry, following Wayne C. Booth, can be understood as “the art of reasoning together about shared concerns” (1988, p. 108). That is, shared because the judgment is discursively negotiated with reference to both the crux of the matter and in light of what is in the best interest of oneself or some other. Accounting for both Moss and Booth, rhetorical reason may then be conceptualized as a method of "shared moral inquiry," but one must be precise regarding the meaning of the word “moral.” "Moral inquiry," within the present context, means inquiry into practical matters (as opposed to mere speculation or scientific inquiry). Hans-Georg Gadamer uses “moral” in this very sense in "Truth and Method" (p. 314); Albert R. Jonsen and Stephen Toulmin write that “moral knowledge is essentially particular” (1988, p. 330). Shared moral inquiry is moral, not because it involves questions of morality, but because it attempts to determine what is the right thing to do in contingent cases; where such judgments are not made deterministically. Moral inquiry is conducted in the contingent realm, and is concerned with the particular case. There are moral implications for all such decisions, but that is another matter.

Understood with precision then, rhetorical reason guides and "phronesis" drives moral inquiry. The aim of moral inquiry is sound moral judgment, but judgment in hard cases is frustrated because the crux of the matter is hedged in by a potentially limitless parade of particulars.

Rhetorical reason manages particulars by systematically determining the relevance of issues and identifying the "stasis" (which is the most relevant of the relevant issues). Now ascribing relevance, per se, is an act of "phronesis" (Tallmon, 2001 & 1995a,b). Hence, rhetorical reason is a modality of "phronesis" and also, as Aristotle famously notes, a counterpart of dialectic. That is, it depends upon practical wisdom for its proper work, and, in that work, it operates much like dialectical inference, only its proper domain is the particular case as opposed to the general question.

Hence, viewed as a guide to resolving tough cases, rhetorical reason is constituted by:
*topical logic (which guides inquiry by managing particulars)
*"stasis" (which guides inquiry toward the crux of the matter)
*sensitivity to maxims (which signal when the inquiry has taken a turn away from the instant case)
*dialectical inference (which helps clarify the issue at stake,) and the entire enterprise is driven by
*"phronesis"

Individuals exercise rhetorical reason, but its excellence is realized in the public arena (i.e., in shared inquiry, by referencing pooled wisdom).

Bibliography

* Aristotle. "Nicomachean Ethics". (1985) Terence Irwin. trans. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.
* Aristotle. On Rhetoric (1991) George Kennedy. trans. Oxford: Oxford UP.
* Aristotle. Rhetoric. (1954) W. Rhys Roberts. trans. Aristotle: Rhetoric and Poetics. Friedrich Solmsen. ed. New York: Modern Library.
* Booth, Wayne C. (1988) The Vocation of a Teacher. Chicago: U Chicago Press.
* Gadamer, Hans-Georg (1986) trans. Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall, Truth and Method 2nd ed. New York: Crossroad.
* Jonsen, Albert R. and Stephen Toulmin. (1988) The Abuse of Casuistry. Berkeley: U California Press.
* Kennedy, George. (1980) Classical Rhetoric and Its Christian and Secular Tradition From Ancient to Modern Times, Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press.
* Moss, Jean Deitz. ed. (1986) Rhetoric and Praxis: The Contribution of Classical Rhetoric to Practical Reasoning. Washington, D.C.: The Catholic U of America Press.
* Tallmon, James M. "Casuistry." (2001) Ed. Thomas O. Sloane. New York: Oxford University Press Encyclopedia of Rhetoric, 83-88.
* Tallmon, James M. (1995a) “Casuistry and the Role of Rhetorical Reason in Ethical Inquiry,” Philosophy and Rhetoric, 377-87.
* Tallmon, James M. (1995b) “Newman’s Contribution to Conceptualizing Rhetorical Reason,” Rhetoric Society Quarterly, 197-213.

See also

*Rhetoric
*Casuistry
*Dialectic
*Practical reason
*Phronesis
*Rogerian argument
*Stasis
*Maxims
*Techne
*Chaim Perelman


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Поможем написать курсовую

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Practical reason — In philosophy, practical reason is the use of reason to decide how to act. This contrasts with theoretical reason (often called speculative reason), which is the use of reason to decide what to believe. For example: agents use practical reason to …   Wikipedia

  • Glossary of rhetorical terms — Rhetorical Theory is a subject rife with jargon and special terminology. This page explains commonly used rhetorical terms in alphabetical order. The brief definitions here are intended to serve as a quick reference rather than an in depth… …   Wikipedia

  • The Age of Reason — The Age of Reason: Being an Investigation of True and Fabulous Theology , a deistic treatise written by eighteenth century British radical and American revolutionary Thomas Paine, critiques institutionalized religion and challenges the inerrancy… …   Wikipedia

  • On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason — On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason[1] was originally published as a doctoral dissertation in 1813. The German philosopher Arthur Schopenhauer revised this important work and re published it in 1847. Throughout all… …   Wikipedia

  • Rhetoric — This article is about the art of rhetoric in general. For the work by Aristotle, see Rhetoric (Aristotle). Painting depicting a lecture in a knight academy, painted by Pieter Isaacsz or Reinhold Timm for Rosenborg Castle as part of a series of… …   Wikipedia

  • Chaim Perelman — Chaïm Perelman (May 20, 1912 ndash;January 22, 1984) was a Polish born philosopher of law, who studied, taught, and lived most of his life in Brussels. He was among the most important argumentation theorists of the twentieth century. His chief… …   Wikipedia

  • Inventio — is the system or method used for the discovery of arguments in Western rhetoric and comes from the Latin word, meaning invention or discovery . Inventio is the central, indispensable canon of rhetoric, and traditionally means a systematic search… …   Wikipedia

  • Casuistry — (pronEng|ˈkæʒuːɨstri) is an applied ethics term referring to case based reasoning. Casuistry is used in juridical and ethical discussions of law and ethics, and often is a critique of principle based reasoning. [… …   Wikipedia

  • Phronesis — (Greek: φρόνησις) in Aristotle s Nicomachean Ethics is the virtue of moral thought, usually translated practical wisdom , sometimes as prudence .Aristotle distinguishes between two intellectual virtues: sophia and phronesis . Sophia (usually… …   Wikipedia

  • stranger — stranger, foreigner, alien, outlander, outsider, immigrant, émigré can all designate a person who comes into a community from the outside and is not recognized as a member of that community. This is the primary denotation of some of the words,… …   New Dictionary of Synonyms

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”