- Axiom of pairing
In
axiomatic set theory and the branches oflogic ,mathematics , andcomputer science that use it, the axiom of pairing is one of theaxiom s ofZermelo-Fraenkel set theory .Formal statement
In the
formal language of the Zermelo-Frankel axioms, the axiom reads::or in words::Given any set "A" and any set "B", there is a set "C" such that, given any set "D", "D" is a member of "C"if and only if "D" is equal to "A" or "D" is equal to "B".or in simpler words::Given two sets, there is a set whose members are exactly the two given sets.
Interpretation
What the axiom is really saying is that, given two sets "A" and "B", we can find a set "C" whose members are precisely "A" and "B".We can use the
axiom of extensionality to show that this set "C" is unique.We call the set "C" the "pair" of "A" and "B", and denote it {"A","B"}.Thus the essence of the axiom is::Any two sets have a pair.{"A","A"} is abbreviated {"A"}, called the "singleton" containing "A".Note that a singleton is a special case of a pair.The axiom of pairing also allows for the definition of
ordered pairs . For any sets and , theordered pair is defined by the following::
Note that this definition satisfies the condition
:
Ordered "n"-tuples can be defined recursively as follows:
:
Non-independence
The axiom of pairing is generally considered uncontroversial, and it or an equivalent appears in just about any alternative
axiomatization of set theory. Nevertheless, in the standard formulation of theZermelo–Fraenkel set theory , the axiom of pairing follows theaxiom schema of replacement applied to any given set with two or more elements, and thus it is sometimes omitted. The existence of such a set with two elements, such as { {}, { {} } }, can be deduced either from theaxiom of empty set and theaxiom of power set or from theaxiom of infinity .Generalisation
Together with the
axiom of empty set , the axiom of pairing can be generalised to the following schema::that is::Given any finite number of sets "A"1 through "A""n", there is a set "C" whose members are precisely "A"1 through "A""n".This set "C" is again unique by the axiom of extension, and is denoted {"A"1,...,"A""n"}.Of course, we can't refer to a "finite" number of sets rigorously without already having in our hands a (finite) set to which the sets in question belong.Thus, this is not a single statement but instead a schema, with a separate statement for each
natural number "n".
*The case "n" = 1 is the axiom of pairing with "A" = "A"1 and "B" = "A"1.
*The case "n" = 2 is the axiom of pairing with "A" = "A"1 and "B" = "A"2.
*The cases "n" > 2 can be proved using the axiom of pairing and theaxiom of union multiple times.For example, to prove the case "n" = 3, use the axiom of pairing three times, to produce the pair {"A"1,"A"2}, the singleton {"A"3}, and then the pair "A"1,"A"2},{"A"3.The axiom of union then produces the desired result, {"A"1,"A"2,"A"3}. We can extend this schema to include "n"=0 if we interpret that case as theaxiom of empty set .Thus, one may use this as an
axiom schema in the place of the axioms of empty set and pairing. Normally, however, one uses the axioms of empty set and pairing separately, and then proves this as atheorem schema. Note that adopting this as an axiom schema will not replace theaxiom of union , which is still needed for other situations.Another alternative
Another axiom which implies the axiom of pairing in the presence of the
axiom of empty set is :.Using {} for "A" and "x" for B, we get {"x"} for C. Then use {"x"} for "A" and "y" for "B", getting {"x,y"} for C. One may continue in this fashion to build up any finite set. And this could be used to generate allhereditarily finite set s without using theaxiom of union .References
*Paul Halmos, "Naive set theory". Princeton, NJ: D. Van Nostrand Company, 1960. Reprinted by Springer-Verlag, New York, 1974. ISBN 0-387-90092-6 (Springer-Verlag edition).
*Jech, Thomas, 2003. "Set Theory: The Third Millennium Edition, Revised and Expanded". Springer. ISBN 3-540-44085-2.
*Kunen, Kenneth, 1980. "Set Theory: An Introduction to Independence Proofs". Elsevier. ISBN 0-444-86839-9.
Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.