Rigid designator

Rigid designator

In modal logic and the philosophy of language, a term is said to be a rigid designator when it designates (picks out, denotes, refers to) the same thing in "all possible worlds" in which that thing exists and does not designate anything else in those possible worlds in which that thing does "not" exist. A designator is "persistently rigid" if it designates the same thing in every possible world in which that thing exists and designates nothing in all other possible worlds. A designator is "obstinately rigid" if it designates the same thing in every possible world, period, whether or not that thing exists in that world. Rigid designators are contrasted with non-rigid or flaccid designators, which may designate different things in different possible worlds.

Proper Names and Definite Descriptions

The notion of rigid designation was first introduced by Saul Kripke in the lectures that became "Naming and Necessity", in the course of his argument against descriptivist theories of reference. At the time of Kripke's lectures, the dominant theories of reference in Analytic philosophy (associated with the theories of Gottlob Frege and Bertrand Russell) held that the meaning of sentences involving proper names could be given by substituting a contextually appropriate description for the name. Russell, for example, famously held [Russell, Bertrand, Knowledge by Acquaintance and Knowledge by Description, "The Problems of Philosophy", chapter 5 ( [http://www.ditext.com/russell/rus5.html online text] .)] that someone who had never met Otto von Bismarck might know of him as "the first Chancellor of the German Empire", and if so, his statement that (say) "Bismarck was a ruthless politician" should be understood to mean "The first Chancellor of the German Empire was a ruthless politician" (which could in turn be analysed into a series of more basic statements according to the method Russell introduced in his theory of definite descriptions). Kripke argued — against both the Russellian analysis and several attempted refinements of it — that such descriptions could not possibly "mean the same thing" as the name "Bismarck," on the grounds that proper names such as "Bismarck" always designate "rigidly", whereas descriptions such as "the first Chancellor of the German Empire" do not. Thus, for example, it "might have been the case" that Bismarck died in infancy. If so, he would not have ever satisfied the description "the first Chancellor of the German Empire," and (indeed) someone else probably would have. It does not follow that the first Chancellor of the German Empire may not have been the first Chancellor of the German Empire—that is (at least according to its surface-structure) a contradiction. Kripke argues that the way that proper names "work" is that when we make statements about what might or might not have been true of Bismarck, we are talking about what might or might not have been true of "that particular person" in various situations, whereas when we make statements about what might or might not have been true of, say, "the first Chancellor of the German Empire" we "could" be talking about what might or might not have been true of "whomever" would have happened to fill that office in those situations.

The "could" here is important to note: rigid designation is a property of the "way terms are used", not a property of "the terms themselves", and some philosophers, following Keith Donnellan, have argued that a phrase such as "the first Chancellor of the German Empire" "could" be used rigidly, in sentences such as "the first Chancellor of the German Empire could have decided never to go into politics." Kripke himself doubted that there was any need to recognize rigid uses of definite descriptions, and argued that Russell's notion of scope offered all that was needed to account for such sentences. But in either case, Kripke argued, nothing important in his account depends on the question (see: "Naming and Necessity" p. 6n8, p. 59n22). Whether definite descriptions can be used rigidly or not, they can at least "sometimes" be used non-rigidly, but a proper name "can only be used rigidly"; the asymmetry, Kripke argues, demonstrates that no definite description could "give the meaning" of a proper name—although it might be used to explain "who" a name refers to (that is, to "fix the referent" of the name).

Essentialism

In "Naming and Necessity", Kripke argues that proper names and certain natural kind terms—including biological taxa and types of natural substances (most famously, "water" and "H2O") designate rigidly. He argues for a form of scientific essentialism not unlike Aristotelian essentialism. Essential properties are common to an object in all possible worlds, and so they pick out the same objects in all possible worlds - they rigidly designate.

Causal-Historical Theory of Reference

Proper names rigidly designate for reasons that differ from natural kinds terms. The reason 'Johnny Depp' refers to one particular person in all possible worlds is because some person initially gave the name to him by saying something like "Let's call our baby 'Johnny Depp'". This is called the initial baptism. This usage of 'Johnny Depp' for referring to some particular baby got passed on from person-to-person in a giant causal and historical chain of events. That is why everybody calls Johnny Depp 'Johnny Depp'. Johnny's mother passed it onto her friends who passed it onto their friends who passed it onto their friends, and so on.

Necessary Identities

One interesting consequence of Kripke semantics is that identities involving rigid designators are necessary. If water is H2O, then water is "necessarily" H2O. Since the terms 'water' and 'H2O' pick out the same object in every possible world, there is no possible world in which 'water' picks out something different from 'H2O'. Therefore, water is necessarily H2O. It is possible, of course, that we are mistaken about the chemical composition of water, but that does not affect the necessity of identities. What is not being claimed is that water is necessarily H2O, but "conditionally", "if" water is H2O (though we may not know this, it does not change the fact if it is true), then water is necessarily H2O.

References

ee also

*Causal theory of reference
*class versus instance
*Counterpart theory
*Flaccid designator
*Scientific essentialism


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Нужна курсовая?

Look at other dictionaries:

  • rigid designator — A rigid designator is one that denotes the same thing in all possible worlds, or in all possible worlds in which that thing exists. The term was introduced by Kripke, to label the fact that if we specify a possibility using a singular term we… …   Philosophy dictionary

  • rigid designator — …   Useful english dictionary

  • Non-rigid designator — In the philosophy of language and modal logic, a non rigid designator (or flaccid designator) is a term that does not extensionally refer to the same object in all possible worlds. For example, consider the phrase The 43rd president of the United …   Wikipedia

  • designator — A term that designates. See definite description, rigid designator, singular term …   Philosophy dictionary

  • Starrer Designator — Ein starrer Designator (rigid designator) ist ein Bezeichnungsausdruck, der durch Saul Kripke in seiner Arbeit Name und Notwendigkeit im Felde der Theorie der Eigennamen formuliert wurde. Namen sind nach Kripke, im Gegensatz zu der klassischen… …   Deutsch Wikipedia

  • flaccid designator — Jocular contrast with rigid designator : a term such as a definite description that may be satisfied by different things in different possible worlds …   Philosophy dictionary

  • Functionalism (philosophy of mind) — Functionalism is a theory of the mind in contemporary philosophy, developed largely as an alternative to both the identity theory of mind and behaviourism. Its core idea is that mental states (beliefs, desires, being in pain, etc.) are… …   Wikipedia

  • Causal theory of reference — A causal theory of reference is any of a family of views about how terms acquire specific referents. Such theories have been used to describe reference in regard to all sorts of reference bearing terms, particularly logically proper names and… …   Wikipedia

  • Dynamic logic (modal logic) — For the subject in digital electronics also known as clocked logic, see dynamic logic (digital electronics). Dynamic logic is an extension of modal logic originally intended for reasoning about computer programs and later applied to more general… …   Wikipedia

  • Counterpart theory — In philosophy, specifically in the area of modal metaphysics, counterpart theory is an alternative to standard (Kripkean) possible worlds semantics for interpreting quantified modal logic. Counterpart theory still presupposes possible worlds, but …   Wikipedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”