Virtue jurisprudence

Virtue jurisprudence

In the philosophy of law, "virtue jurisprudence" is the name given to theories of law related to virtue ethics. By making the aretaic turn in legal theory, virtue jurisprudence focuses on the importance of character and human excellence or virtue to questions about the nature of law, the content of the law, and judging.

The topics encompassed by virtue jurisprudence

Among the topics encompassed by virtue jurisprudence are the following:
# Virtue ethics has implications for an account of the proper ends of legislation. If the aim of law is to make citizens virtuous (as opposed to maximizing utility or realizing a set of moral rights), what are the implications for the content of the laws?
# Virtue ethics has implications for legal ethics. Current approaches to legal ethics emphasize deontological moral theory, i.e. duties to clients and respect for client autonomy, and these deontological approaches are reflected in the various codes of professional conduct that have been devised for lawyers, judges, and legislators.
# Accounts of the virtue of justice (in particular, Aristotle and Aquinas’s theories of natural justice) have implications for debates between natural lawyers and legal positivists over the nature of law.
# A virtue-centered theory of judging, which describes the particular excellences required by judges.

Aretaic theories of judging

The judicial virtues

The most developed aspect of virtue jurisprudence is its distinctive theory of judging. A virtue-centered theory of judging offers an account of the characteristics or excellences that make for a good judge. These include: (1) judicial temperance, (2) judicial courage, (3) judicial temperament, (4) judicial intelligence, (5) judicial wisdom, and (6) justice. Although every theory of judging can incorporate some account of judicial virtue, a virtue-centered theory of judging makes the distinctive claim that the judicial virtues are central, "i.e." that they have basic explanatory and normative significance.

Criticism of a virtue-centered theory of judging

Many of the criticisms of virtue jurisprudence are parallel to those offered in the context of debates over virtue ethics. Some of these include:
* The charge that virtue jurisprudence does not provide sufficient guidance for the making of legal decisions. "Do as a virtuous judge would do!" This formula provides little instruction to an ordinary decision maker.
* The argument that virtue jurisprudence requires inordinate trust in the capacities of judges. In a democratic society, the rightness or wrongness of legal decisions should be decided by criteria that are public and accessible to all citizens.

Virtue as the proper end of law

Aristotle argued that the inculcation of promotion of virtue was the proper end of law. Aquinas argued that true laws (which are rational) can teach virtue by being internalized by those who already possess sufficient virtue to grasp the purpose of the law. Even those who have not yet achieved this level of virtue can be coerced into obedience to the law, and this may enable them to become more virtuous.

A contemporary restatement of this view is found in the writings of Robert George. In his book, "Making Men Moral", George argues for the promotion of virtue as the end of law and against the contrary view that the purpose of law is the protection of rights.

Law and virtue outside the Western tradition

The phrase "virtue jurisprudence" is usually applied in the context of contemporary Western philosophical thinking about law. There are, however, important ideas about the relationship between law and virtue in other intellectual traditions. One example is provided by Confucian ideas about virtue. In the Analects, Confucius argues that a society in which people are virtuous would have no need of judges, rules, or jurisprudence because people would be able to resolve social conflicts by themselves. Thus, it is argued that the idea of virtue is opposed to the idea of law.

It can be argued that that even virtuous citizens might disagree about the application of the law, especially where their own interests or ideological commitments are at stake. However, this argument is rather foreign to both traditional and modern Chinese political thought. Chinese political theory tends to assume that the truly virtuous are selfless to the point of martyrdom and would not consider their own personal interests and that the virtuous are able to transcend ideology. At the same time, traditional Chinese political thought regards those with absolute virtue to be historically extremely rare, and that most people, including the Emperor and his officials, are prone to both corruption and error. Consequently, there is a belief that law and indeed government is an unfortunate necessity in dealing with an imperfect world and with imperfect people.

The view that the inculcation of virtue is the proper end of legislation contrasts markedly with traditional Chinese thinking on the subject, which argues that laws exist because men are lacking in virtue. Confucianism places very little faith on the ability of law or external pressure to make men moral but rather believes that virtue must come from introspection and education.

References

*R.A. Duff, " [http://www.blackwell-synergy.com/links/doi/10.1111/1467-9973.00269/abs/ The Limits of Virtue Jurisprudence] ", Metaphilosophy, Volume 34 Issue 1-2 Page 214 - January 2003.
*Robert P. George, "Making Men Moral" (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1993) ISBN 0-19-825424-5.
*Kyron Huigens, " [http://www.cardozo.yu.edu/cardlrev/v24n2/Huigens%20Final%20Version.pdf Nietzsche and Aretaic Legal Theory] " (2003)
*Suzanna Sherry, " [http://www.law.wfu.edu/prebuilt/LR_v38n2_Sherry.pdf Judges of Character] ", 38 Wake Forest L. Rev. 793 (2003).
*Lawrence Solum, " [http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=959646 Natural Justice] ", American Journal of Jurisprudence, Vol. 51, pp. 65-105 (2006).
*Lawrence B. Solum, " [http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=369940 Virtue Jurisprudence: A Virtue-Centered Theory of Judging] ", Metaphilosophy, Volume 34 Issue 1-2 Page 178 - January 2003.

ee also

*Aquinas
*Aristotle
*Judicial activism
*Jurisprudence
*Natural law
*Philosophy of law
*Virtue ethics
*Virtue

External links

* [http://www.aquinasonline.com/Magee/virtlaw.html Law and Virtue in Aquinas by Joseph M. Magee]
* [http://legaltheorylexicon.blogspot.com/2004_04_01_legaltheorylexicon_archive.html#108170346624977963 Legal theory lexicon: virtue jurisprudence] by Larry Solum.


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Нужно сделать НИР?

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Virtue ethics — Virtue theory is a branch of moral philosophy that emphasizes character, rather than rules or consequences, as the key element of ethical thinking. In the West virtue ethics was the prevailing approach to ethical thinking in the ancient and… …   Wikipedia

  • Jurisprudence — For the jurisprudence of courts, see Case law. Philosophers of law ask what is law? and what should it be? Jurisprudence is the theory and philosophy of law. Scholars of jurisprudence, or legal theorists (including legal philosophers and social… …   Wikipedia

  • Civic virtue — Civility redirects here. For the Wikipedia policy on civility, see Wikipedia:Civility. Jacques Louis David s 1784 painting The Oath of the Horatii, illustrating a dramatic moment from Livy s history of Rome, embodies eighteenth century ideas… …   Wikipedia

  • Guardianship, in Civil Jurisprudence — • A person intrusted by law with the interests of another whose youth, inexperience, mental weakness or feebleness of will, disqualifies him from acting for himself in the ordinary affairs of life, and who is known as the ward Catholic… …   Catholic encyclopedia

  • Islamic economic jurisprudence — Part of a series on Islamic jurisprudence (Fiqh) …   Wikipedia

  • Natural law — For other uses, see Natural law (disambiguation). Natural law, or the law of nature (Latin: lex naturalis), is any system of law which is purportedly determined by nature, and thus universal.[1] Classically, natural law refers to the use of… …   Wikipedia

  • Ronald Dworkin — Infobox Philosopher region = Western Philosophy era = 20th century philosophy 21st century philosophy color = #B0C4DE |image caption = Ronald Dworkin at the 2008 Brooklyn Book Festival. name = Ronald Dworkin birth = birth date and age|1931|12|11… …   Wikipedia

  • Aretaic turn — The aretaic turn is a movement in contemporary moral philosophy and ethics to emphasize character and human excellence or virtue, as opposed to moral rules or consequences. This movement has been extended to other philosophical disciplines,… …   Wikipedia

  • Utilitarianism — This article discusses utilitarian ethical theory. For a discussion of John Stuart Mill s book Utilitarianism, see Utilitarianism (book). For the architectural theory, see Utilitarianism (architecture) Part of a series on …   Wikipedia

  • Jeremy Bentham — Full name Jeremy Bentham Born 15 February 1748(1748 02 15) London, England Died 6 June 1832 …   Wikipedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”