Leonardo Polo

Leonardo Polo

Infobox_Philosopher
region = Western Philosophers
era = 20th-century philosophy
color = #B0C4DE



image_caption = Leonardo Polo

name = Leonardo Polo
birth = 1926 February 1 (Madrid, Spain)
school_tradition = Continental philosophy
main_interests = Metaphysics, Epistemology, Philosophical Anthropology
influences = Aristotle, Aquinas, Descartes, Hegel, Kant, Husserl, Heidegger
influenced = Ignacio Falgueras, Ricardo Yepes, Juan A. Garcia
notable_ideas = Mental limits to know reality can be overcome, The distinction between 'essence' and 'act of being' needs to be expanded

Leonardo Polo (born February 1, 1926 in Madrid, Spain) is a Professor of Philosophy at the University of Navarra (Spain) since 1954, he has also taught in the University of Granada (Spain), the University of the Holy Cross (Italy), the University of La Sabana (Colombia), the University of Piura (Peru) and Panamerican University (Mexico City), together with IESE Business School in Madrid and Barcelona. While his main philosophical interests are Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophical Anthropology, he has also written on Ethics, Sociology, Philosophy of Science and History of Philosophy. He is a catholic and a member of Opus Dei.

Life

Early life

Leonardo Polo was born in Madrid, February 1st, 1926. He attended elementary school at the French High School (Liceo francés) of Madrid. During the years previous to the Spanish Civil War, his father was vice-major of Madrid. For this reason, due to recommendations of the Spanish Republican Government, his family moves to Albacete (Spain). At the end of the war, they came back to Madrid, except for the father, who exiled himself first to Nicaragua, and after that to Chile, where he died in 1946.

During the high school he read the Fundamental Philosophy of the Spanish philosopher Jaime Balmes (read it at the gutenberg author| id=Jaime+Balmes | name=Jaume Balmes). From such readings he came to think that philosophy mainly consists in the knowledge of principles, which have to be known by principles too. At school he also read Ortega y Gasset, Aquinas, and Xavier Zubiri.

Although he was most inclined to study mathematics, the low relevance of such studies in professional circles in the aftermaths of the Spanish Civil War led him to do Law. Studying Law he could take over the family buffet, continuing so a familiar tradition.

Nonetheless, in 1949 he decided not to be a lawyer, but to follow his own inclination to theory. For this reason he began to write his doctoral dissertation in Law. During these years he remembered his conversations on Hegel with the Professor of Common Law, G. García-Valdecasas. Polo was very interested in a metaphysical interpretation of Natural Law. He read on Hegel’s philosophy of right, Heidegger’s "Being and Time", Kant’s "Critic of pure Reason", Spinoza’s "Ethics", and some books from Aristotle. Finally, he began to study Philosophy in Madrid.

The rise of a new philosophical method

It was spring of 1950 when Polo acknowledged the existence of what he calls the mental limit. He detected such limit as follows:

:“I realized it suddenly. I was just thinking about being and thought, and the relationship between each other; then I realized that we cannot arrive to being while we do not overcome the supposition of the objective knowledge, because supposition limits intellectual objects, and a limited knowledge cannot be a knowledge of being in a transcendental sense” (from an interview to Prof. Dr. Juan Cruz in “Anuario Filosófico” XXV/1 (1992), § 46. * http://dspace.unav.es/handle/1721.1/687] You can read here that interview).

In other words,

: “you can not separate being from being. You can not seize it objectively because as long as you do that being ceases to be real. But if being is not real, then it is nothing; the intentional study of being is a "quid pro quo"; being agrees with itself, but to be known "intentionaliter", as Scholasticism said, is an extrinsic denomination. When I know objectively, the idea I know has no effect on what I am knowing, because the idea I am knowing is on my mind as intelligible in act and in reality as intelligible in potency. The real distinction between essence and being tightens this matter, because if being and essence were the same, in knowing anything about the essence, one could know something about being” (from the same interview, § 47).

Polo describes his discovering in this way: i) "A is A", supposes A", and ii) "Thought being does not think". According to the first proposition, there is no intellectual increase in the reality of A when we think it objectively . Mental objects are invariably supposed. Following the tradition that comes from Medieval Philosophy, "suppositio" is the fact that the significative reference is not indefinite. In this way, the reference of A stops, because what is in the realm of the mind is A as an object. "A" is "already" thought, "A" is already "given", "there is already" A, "what is immediately open to a mental act is an object". That is the supposition of A. One can think more, better, but according to a new mental act. You cannot increase the intellection of A with the same act you have already thought. That act stops in A. The act does not prosecutes to new objectivity, in other words, a mental act always refers to an object, in which it "stops". According to this fact, says Polo, the kantian constructivism of mental objects, and the hegelian dialectic method are misguided attempts.

The second sentece "Thought being does not think" explains a different meaning of the mental limitation. While mental activity and objectivity are different, they are inseparable. Without the first one, there is no possibility of the second one: there is no way of finding an idea that could think itself. The intentionality of mental acts always refers to objects where it is impossible to find the known existence. This formulation involves a criticism to the subject-object identity, and a rectification of Heidegger's existentialism.

First formulation of his Philosophical Proposal (1952-1966)

From 1952 to 1954 Leonardo Polo lives in Rome, where he writes two volumes entitled "The real distinction between being and essence", which are still unpublished. During his time in Rome, Polo worked in a Spanish Law Institute with the Spanish Professor of Roman Law Alvaro D'Ors. Polo tried to reinterpret Natural Law in the light of his own method. In doing so, he engages in dialogue with German idealism and Heidegger's philosophy of existence.

In 1961 he receives his doctorate in Philosophy from the Central University of Madrid with a dissertation on Descartes (later published as "Evidence and Reality in Descartes"), directed by Prof. Antonio Millán-Puelles. The book was published by the Spanish Higher Council of Scientific Investigation (CSIC) in 1963, and it was said have called the attention of Paul Ricoeur.

Polo then began to prepare for publication parts of the two volumes written in Rome. These books were later known and published as "El acceso al ser" (Access to being), of 1964, and "El ser I: La existencia extramental" (Being I: Extramental Existence), of 1966. The publication of these books helped him to obtain a university chair, which he finally got at the University of Granada. From 1966 he started teaching Fundamentals of Philosophy in that University.

Years of silence: 1966-1982

Unfortunately, these two books were widely misunderstood in the Spanish intellectual circles. Few were able to understand the complexity of the thematic and methodical dimensions of his proposal, along with its technical vocabulary. His assertion that freedom is a personal transcendental was also misunderstood. In doing so, some thought that Polo was a thinker on the Hegelian tradition.

Out of the four subjects which he thought are available when overcoming our mental limits, Polo only wrote about the first one ("Being I: Extramental Existence"). The original plan consisted of four parts: "Being II" would study the extramental essence (analysis of the persistence of extramental being in four predicamentales causes); "Being III" would study the being of human person, and "Being IV" would deal with the essence of man. Nevertheless he remained in silence during fifteen years. He did not publish anything other than a couple of papers. These are years of intense study and exchanges with other peers.

He taught two years at the University of Granada. After that he moved back to the University of Navarra, where in 1972 he extensively revised Being III and Being IV, writing a new version of his Philosophical Anthropology, which remained unpublished too.

From 1978 he started teaching in universities of South and Central America every year. Polo understood that for those countries education was a means of finding a way out of poverty, mainly because without division of labour, which is central to any modern society, education becomes impossible. Hence he promoted research and high standards in teaching in every university of South and Central America which he visited. It should be noted that many of this visits were to Opus Dei Universities, like Universidad Panamericana, Universidad de Piura, and Universidad de la Sabana

Years of maturity: from 1982 to the present

In 1982 Polo breaks his silence in a paper called "The intellectual and the intelligible". There he makes explicit the Aristotelian roots of his proposal, highlighting the continuity of his philosophy with the Aristotelian tradition. He saw it as a "continuation of the study of knowledge just at the stage in which Aristotle left it". To that aim he set out to write his "Theory of Knowledge" in 5 volumes, the last two of which correspond to Being II.

In 1999 and 2003 he published his third and definitive work on philosophical anthropology (the former Being III and IV from 1972, and the old "Real Distinction" from 1952 being the previous versions), which came to light under the title "Transcendental Anthropology" I (1999) and II (2003).

These years of maturity have seen the publication of more than twenty books in a varied range of topics. Now Polo continues working in Pamplona (Spain). Different universities and institutions worldwide (like the "Institute of Philosophical Studies 'Leonardo Polo'" in Málaga (Spain) have organized meetings and symposia about his thought, and research is conducted and being spread to the present throughout books and articles which find their inspiration in his work.

Work

His most important works are: "Evidencia y realidad en Descartes" (Evidence and Reality in Descartes), published in 1963, "El acceso al ser," (Access to Being), in 1964, "El ser I: La existencia extramental" (Being I: Extramental Existence), in 1966, "Curso de Teoría del Conocimiento," (Course of Theory of Knowledge), published in four volumes between 1984 and 1996), "Hegel y el posthegelianismo" (Hegel and Posthegelianism), in 1985, "Antropología Trascendental I: La persona humana" (Transcendental Anthropology I: Human Person), in 1999 and "Antropología transcendental II: la esencia del hombre" (Transcendental Anthropology II: Human Essence) in 2003.

"El acceso al ser"

This book expounds Polo's metaphysical method. Aristotle considered metaphysics the highest possible science because it deals with being, which is the ultimate constituent of everything. Modern metaphysicians, such as Descartes and Kant, understood that many of the pitfalls of metaphysics were caused by the lack of a rigorous method. Polo is sympathetic with Descartes and Kant about the need for such a method, but reflects that in metaphysics the method has to take us to grasp the being or existence of entities as such. If instead of that, our method leaves unresolved the question 'what is being?', its achievements will lead to perplexity. For Polo, such is the situation of Modern metaphysicians. When perplexed, the metaphysician finds himself in an awkward position, for he becomes blind to his own cognitive limits, and consequently has to put up with the suspicion that something in his system is missing without knowing exactly what.

Polo's response to perplexity gravitates on the need to overcome such limits. His method consists in acknowledging such limits without denying them. To take thinking to its limit is the only way in which this can be detected and laid bare for scrutiny. Only in that way such limits will become apparent to the philosopher. The task of "El acceso al ser" is to illuminate the mind's cognitive limits for knowing in such a way that these can be effectively overcome. He calls this method 'the abandonment of mental limit'.

With this a new and unsuspected perspective opens up. Being does not appear as perplexical as it might have appeared to philosophers like Hegel. The abandonment of the limit exposes the being of the universe as it is. This can be seen, on the one hand, as a kind of "persistence"; on the other, as a principle of continuity which provides the basis for the principle of non-contradiction. But looking at the universe one does not know why things "are" in the first place or why it exists. The reason is that the universe depends on a different principle called "identity", and which is essentially God. Disconnect the world with that identity, and a large part of reality will lose its sense, for there is a third principle, the so-called "transcendental causality" which links up persistence and identity by placing the latter as creator of the former.

In this way, Polo thinks that "Access to Being" brings metaphysics back in its right historical track. Some medievals, and particularly Aquinas, conceived being as a transcendental, non-reducible notion. This method looks to do justice to their views.

"Curso de Teoría del Conocimiento"

This book is based on transcripts taken from the epistemology lectures which Polo delivered in the University of Navarra throughout the 80s, and that he corrected later on. The work contents are carefully distributed in four volumes, the last of which is divided in two parts. They are a much later and mature work in which Polo brings his discoveries in line with Aristotle's philosophy and sistematises his views for the first time.

Starting from perceptual knowledge, it discusses internal faculties such as imagination, the abstraction and the following steps to the highest cognitive level, which is rational knowledge. As part of his concern for the method, Polo formulates a number of axioms which specify what is a cognitive act. The first and most relevant of these is the 'axiom of the act', which establishes that knowledge is active, as a consequence of which knowledge is an intentional and perfect act. Knowledge secures that character over real and constitutive existing acts such as those constituting a planet or a tiny virus. Knowledge, following Aristotle, is "energeia" or perfect act which in itself does not consist in any kind of substance, nor fits into the categories of space and time, as all existing objects do (see Aristotle's theory of potentiality and actuality).

Polo devises an epistemic difference between operations and habits of the mind. Habits are powerful cognitive acts which bring particular insights into real objects, whereas operations analyse and exploit the cognitive achievement of habits in successive stages as much as they can. As operations come to an end, only further habits can bring new light to them. In this way, the distinction between them grows bigger and more articulated the further the we progress beyond perceptual knowledge.

Habits are a direct exercise of the abandonment of the limit. While we all use some of them in ordinary life, i.e. so to be able to speak, not every one makes use of the highest available habits, which according to Polo illuminate unprecedented problems of philosophy such as the nature of first principles as examined in "El acceso al ser".

Yet habits are sustained by a good many operations. The distinction between operations and habits runs across all cognitive faculties and helps to bring concepts, linguistic and numerical abilities and judgements into a new light, out of which we know, i.e. that after the first abstracted object the path of reasoning faces a junction: it can either 'generalise', to organise abstract objects into families, as we do in any classification of items into categories and subcategories, or it can follow a 'rational' path, exploring thus the promising connection between concepts and reality in order to make a judgement upon the universal or particular nature of a thing.

Polo not only gives evidence of his views by discussing rival theories; he contrasts his views with that of Kant, Hegel and Heidegger. Kant's epistemology, while succeeding in systematising knowledge, presents perceptual knowledge as passive and so fails to comply with the requirements of axiom A, which asserts that knowledge is active. For Kant:

:"perceptual knowledge is passive and yet the intellect is active. But if the intellect is active and perception is passive, the relation between both, if active, must be transitive. A transitive movement has suddenly crept into knowledge (...) as a kind of "actio in passo", something which for Aristotle is paradigmatic of a physical action" (2nd ed. 1987, 70-1).

Similarly, the second volume of Polo's epistemology discusses a good deal of the concept of abstract objects for Heidegger, whereas the last volume explores the philosophical basis of 20th century physics.

Transcendental Anthropology

Polo had expressed in private conversations that his voluminous "Theory of Knowledge" had shed much light into his method, but that his work would be incomplete if he were not to canvass the habits which yield knowledge of the human essence and its singular act of being.

That is precisely the core of his Transcendental Anthropology "(Antropología Trascendental)", a science he believes is a transcendental philosophy of man – not taking 'transcendental' as synonym with "a priori" and opposed to 'empirical', as Kant would have taken it, but signifying the primacy of persons' being -.

Polo believes that throughout the centuries philosophical anthropology has been trumped by metaphysics. Say that metaphysics concerns the study of the universe and that philosophical anthropology focus on man. If we take man to be a bare metaphysical being in the sense in which Aristotle, Aquinas and some other medieval philosophers considered and defined it as a 'rational substance', we will find extremely hard to explain free will. For the notion of substance is intrinsically tied up to metaphysical necessity, so that its substance can be characterised as being "per se" or needing not the input of any other to subsist. Of course that does not imply that the being of that substance is absolutely necessary, because no creature can cause itself to be.

Human freedom, however, is incompatible with necessity. Modern philosophers understood it only too well when they asserted that man's essence consisted in spontaneity. This is certainly a feature of free will. In any choice, I may be bound by a limited number of alternatives on offer, but at the crucial point I am totally free to choose any of the alternatives regardless of my own inclinations. Freedom awaits us in any act of choice manifesting the radical openness of the will. For Polo, 'various distinctions must be settled in the first transcendental, that is, in the act of being "(esse)"' (I, p. 69). It is a mistake to call man 'free' once it has being called a 'substance', be it rational or not, for man is not a free-willed substance but a free-willed being. Thus, the distinction between the universe and man needs to be scaled up so as to work on a transcendental order. Human beings are different from comets, plants and animals not in external or accidental features, but at the level of what Aquinas would call "actus essendi" (act of being).

For Polo, the difference between the universe and man is this: Man is a co-being which co-exists with other co-existences. Man is the being existentially open to other acts of being: it co-exists with the being of the universe, with other human persons and, most importantly, with God. In its openness to others lies the dual character of its being, which makes the existence of a lonely person a metaphysical absurdity.

The ontological limits of a person do not have the sharper edges of other creatures’ beings. We conceive degrees of perfection in instruments such as a boiler depending on a variety of reasons, i.e. on how it fulfils or achieves some desirable purpose for which the instrument was crafted. A similar thing can be said of animals, in what they add up to sustaining biological life. The human being is equally open to perfection, but that increase, which is equally ruled by some purpose, is inherent to its act of being. Inasmuch as human beings co-exist with other co-beings, and especially with God, free will can grow.

Thus Polo conceives freedom not as sheer spontaneity, autonomous independence or lack of physical and psychological constraints, but in a new an unexpected sense: as being radically open to other beings. We may be tempted to think that a person’s relation with God is strictly causal, but that is only the case of the universe which in "Access to Being" was characterised as "persistence". A person’s unique dependence on God is the root of her freedom and hence, of an inward openness built on self-knowledge and self-giving. The person’s call to openness is at the same time a call to be ontologically ever-more, that is, to be more human in accord with the moral, ethical, and practical implications of what is a 'good' person by nature, and which can only be found in an Aristotelian, non-utilitarian frame of objective values.

Polo proposes that 'openness', 'freedom', 'intellection' and 'love' are "human transcendentals." This means that there can only be a human being when these four properties are in place, although the number of these human transcendentals is not restricted to these four. What is important is that human transcendentals allow an anonymous being to co-exist and to be recognised among other co-existences like her. In this way, Polo overturns the classic doctrine of transcendentals, for which properties such as 'being', 'one', 'truth', 'good' and 'beauty' are universal and all-embracing, including human beings. But he argues that since persons are able to actively acquire those intrinsically static qualities and be intimately transformed by their achievement, human transcendentals substantially differ from the classic set of transcendentals.

References

This list of works on the philosophy of Leonardo Polo is based on the bibliographical work of Prof. Juan A. García * [http://www.leonardopolo.net/plus/jagarcia.htm] (Málaga University) who has research on this matter for the Institute of Philosophical Studies "Leonardo Polo" [http://www.leonardopolo.net/index.html]

Books

1. Balibrea, Miguel Angel: El argumento ontológico de Descartes. La crítica de Leonardo Polo a la prueba cartesiana. Cuadernos del Anuario filosófico, serie universitaria, nº 106. Pamplona: Universidad de Navarra 2000; 102 pp.

2. Balibrea, Miguel Angel: La realidad del máximo pensable. La crítica de Leonardo Polo al argumento de San Anselmo. Cuadernos del Anuario filosófico, serie universitaria, nº 98. Pamplona: Universidad de Navarra 2000; 117 pp.

3. Collado, Santiago: Noción de hábito en la teoría del conocimiento de Polo. Publicaciones de la facultad de filosofía y letras de la universidad de Navarra, colección filosófica nº 159. Pamplona: Eunsa, 2000; 370 pp.

4. Esquer Gallardo, Héctor: El límite del pensamiento. La propuesta metódica de Leonardo Polo. Publicaciones de la facultad de filosofía y letras de la universidad de Navarra, colección filosófica nº 161. Pamplona: Eunsa 2000; 233 pp. (Puede adquirirlo por internet)

5. García González, Juan A.: Principio sin continuación. Escritos sobre la metafísica de Leonardo Polo. Colección Estudios y ensayos, nº 25. Málaga: Universidad de Málaga, 1998; 228 pp. Según se indica en la p. 10, incluye once estudios sobre Polo, de los cuales nueve previamente editados (Puede adquirirlo por internet)

6. García Valdecasas, Miguel: Límite e identidad. La culminación de la filosofía en Hegel y Polo. Cuadernos del Anuario filosófico, serie de filosofía española, nº 6. Pamplona: Universidad de Navarra, 1998; 106 pp.

7. González Ginocchio, David: El acto de conocer. Antecedentes aristotélicos de Leonardo Polo. Cuadernos del Anuario filosófico, serie universitaria, nº 183. Pamplona: Universidad de Navarra, 2005; 128 pp.

8. González Umeres, Luz: Imaginación, memoria y tiempo. Contrastes entre Bergson y Polo. Cuadernos del Anuario filosófico, serie universitaria, nº 185. Pamplona: Universidad de Navarra, 2006; 114 pp.

9. González Umeres, Luz: La experiencia del tiempo humano. De Bergson a Polo. Cuadernos del Anuario filosófico, serie universitaria, nº 134. Pamplona: Universidad de Navarra, 2001; 104 pp.

10. Padial, Juan José: La antropología del tener según Leonardo Polo. Cuadernos del Anuario filosófico, serie universitaria, nº 100. Pamplona: Universidad de Navarra, 2000; 146 pp.

11. Piá Tarazona, Salvador: El hombre como ser dual. Estudio de las dualidades radicales según la "Antropología Trascendental" de Leonardo Polo. Publicaciones de la facultad de filosofía y letras de la universidad de Navarra, colección filosófica nº 166. Pamplona: Eunsa, 2001; 478 pp. (Puede adquirirlo por internet)

12. Piá Tarazona, Salvador: Los primeros principios en Leonardo Polo. Cuadernos del Anuario filosófico, serie de filosofía española, nº 2. Pamplona: Universidad de Navarra, 1997; 108 pp.

13. Posada, Jorge Mario: La física de causas en Leonardo Polo. Publicaciones de la facultad de filosofía y letras de la universidad de Navarra, colección filosófica nº 102. Pamplona: Eunsa, 1996; 487 pp. (Puede adquirirlo por internet)

14. Posada, Jorge Mario: Voluntad de poder y poder de la voluntad. Una glosa a la propuesta antropológica de Leonardo Polo a la vista de la averiguación nietzscheana. Cuadernos del Anuario filosófico, serie universitaria, nº 173. Pamplona: Universidad de Navarra, 2004; 80 pp.

15. Sellés, Juan Fernando: El conocer personal. Estudio del entendimiento agente según Polo. Cuadernos del Anuario filosófico, serie universitaria, nº 163. Pamplona: Universidad de Navarra, 2003; 169 pp.

Papers

Journals

1. Journal STUDIA POLIANA * [http://www.latindex.unam.mx/larga.php?opcion=1&folio=12563] , Pamplona: Universidad de Navarra. Periodicity annual

2. On line Journal MISCELÁNEA POLIANA * [http://www.leonardopolo.net/revista/revista.html] , edited by the Institute of Philosophical Studies "Leonardo Polo" * [http://www.leonardopolo.net/index.html]

3. VV. AA.: Actas del Congreso internacional sobre el pensamiento de Leonardo Polo (Pamplona 25-7.XI.1996). Anuario Filosófico, Pamplona 29-2 (1996) 291-1120. with 52 studies * [http://www.unav.es/publicaciones/anuario_filosofico/25-1.html] (see the number and the abstract).

4. VV. AA.: special number of Anuario Filosófico, Pamplona 25-1 (1992): 9-251; with 11 studies * [http://dspace.unav.es/handle/1721.1/683] (see the number and the abstract).

Chapters of books

1. Falgueras-García González-Padial (coords.): Futurizar el presente. Estudios sobre la filosofía de Leonardo Polo. Málaga: Universidad de Málaga 2003; 350 pp. with 19 studies):- Prólogo: futurizar el presente (I. Falgueras),- ¿Advertencia o concepto de existencia? (R. Corazón),- El carácter futurizante del entendimiento agente según Polo (J. F. Sellés)- El crecimiento de la vida humana. La temporalidad y el futuro en la antropología poliana (G. Castillo),- El problema de la moción divina (E. Forment),- El problema del fundamento en Apel y Polo... (C. Ortiz de Landázuri),- Entre filosofía y genética. Aportaciones de Polo al diálogo interdisciplinar en torno al alma humana (C. Martínez Priego)- Intencionalidad del conocer versus intencionalidad del querer (U. Ferrer),- La doctrina del acto de ser en Polo... (S. Piá),- La experiencia de la libertad: Bergson-Polo (L. González Umeres)- La fenomenología desde la perspectiva del abandono del límite (F. Haya),- La índole intelectual de la voluntad y lo voluntario... (J.M. Posada e I. García),- Nociones básicas de la filosofía en Polo (J. García),- Realismo trascendental (I. Falgueras),- Sindéresis y voluntad. ¿Quién mueve a la voluntad? (F. Molina),- Sobre la constancia de la presencia mental y la congruencia de la reflexión cognoscitiva (J. Padial)]

2. Falgueras-García González-Yepes: El pensamiento de Leonardo Polo. Simposio sobre el pensamiento de Leonardo Polo (Pamplona 5-6.XI.1993). Cuadernos del Anuario filosófico, nº 11. Pamplona: Universidad de Navarra 1994; 84 pp.:- El abandono del límite y el conocimiento (J. García),- La atropología trascendental de Leonardo Polo (R. Yepes),- Leonardo Polo ante la filosofía clásica y moderna (I. Falgueras)]

3. Falgueras-González-González Enciso-Yepes: Academic Act in honour of Professor Leonardo Polo. Pamplona: Facultad de Filosofía y Letras of the University of Navarre, 27.XI.1996; 57 pp.Published in Miscelánea poliana, nº 1 (2005), y Studia poliana, Pamplona 8 (2006) 13-42.

4. Falgueras-García González-Padial-Sellés: Preparatory Materials for the Internet Congress in order to comment "El acceso al ser" from Leonardo Polo. Digitally edited. IEFLP, Málaga 2005.

External links

* [http://www.leonardopolo.net/index.html Institute of Philosophical Studies "Leonardo Polo"]

* [http://www.iterhominis.com/03_Polo/Obras_LP.htm Works of Leonardo Polo in interhominis (Brasil)]

* [http://www.ensayistas.org/filosofos/spain/Polo/ Web focussed on the philosophy of Leonardo Polo in the Anthology of Hispanic Essay of the University of Georgia (USA)] .

* [http://www.mercaba.org/Filosofia/Polo/cartel_leonardo_polo.htm Another internet site devoted to Leonardo Polo, make by Mercabá] .

* [http://www.fundacionleonardopolo.net/ Project of the Leonardo Polo Foundation]

* [http://www.philosophybooks.info/ Books reviews on several books of Leonardo Polo] .


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Нужен реферат?

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Leonardo Polo — Barrena (1 de febrero de 1926, Madrid, España) es un filósofo español. Contenido 1 Biografía 2 Pensamiento 3 Bibliografía 3.1 …   Wikipedia Español

  • Polo (disambiguation) — Polo is a team sport played on horseback in which the objective is to score goals against an opposing team. It may also refer to:ports* Elephant polo * Water polo * Canoe poloClothing* Polo shirt, also known as a tennis shirt or golf shirt * Polo …   Wikipedia

  • Leonardo (desambiguación) — Leonardo es el nombre propio de varios personajes: Leonardo Argüello Barreto, presidente de Nicaragua; Leonardo Boff, sacerdote brasileño y líder de la Teología de la Liberación; Leonardo Bruni, humanista italiano; Leonardo Caprile, animador de… …   Wikipedia Español

  • Polo — Saltar a navegación, búsqueda El término Polo puede referirse a: En alimentación y bebidas: Polo de helado; Polar, cerveza de Venezuela En automoción: Polo, automóvil del fabricante Volkswagen; En deportes: Polo, deporte que se practica montado a …   Wikipedia Español

  • Leonardo da Vinci-Fiumicino Airport — Aeroporto Leonardo da Vinci di Fiumicino Roma/Fiumicino Airport IATA: FCO …   Wikipedia

  • Leonardo Mina Polo — Leonardo Mina Nombre Leonardo Mina Polo Nacimiento 5 de enero de 1977 (34 años) Buenaventura, Colombia Nacionalidad …   Wikipedia Español

  • Leonardo Olschki — (* 15. Juli 1885 in Verona; † 7. Dezember 1961 in Berkeley) war ein italienischer Romanist, Italianist, Orientalist und Literaturwissenschaftler deutsch jüdischer Abstammung mit US amerikanischer Staatsbürgerschaft. Inhaltsverzeichnis 1 Leben und …   Deutsch Wikipedia

  • Leonardo — may refer to:* Leonardo da Vinci, Italian Renaissance architect, musician, anatomist, inventor, engineer, sculptor, geometer and painter * Leonardo DiCaprio, an American actor * Leonardo Fibonacci (Leonardo of Pisa), Italian mathematician *… …   Wikipedia

  • Leonardo Benevolo — (Orta San Giulio, 25 de septiembre de 1923), arquitecto e historiador italiano. Biografía Estudia arquitectura en la Universidad de Roma, donde se gradúa en 1946. Enseña historia de la arquitectura en el Ateneo, y después en las universidades de… …   Wikipedia Español

  • Leonardo Sottani — (born November 1, 1973 in Figline Valdarno) is a retired water polo player from Italy, who represented his native country at the 1996 Summer Olympics in Atlanta, Georgia. There the attacking forward (1m97) was a member of the the men s national… …   Wikipedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”