Grelling–Nelson paradox

Grelling–Nelson paradox

The Grelling–Nelson paradox is a semantic self-referential paradox formulated in 1908 by Kurt Grelling and Leonard Nelson and sometimes mistakenly attributed to the German philosopher and mathematician Hermann Weyl. It is thus occasionally called Weyl's paradox as well as Grelling's paradox. It is closely analogous to several other well-known paradoxes, in particular the Barber paradox and Russell's paradox.

The paradox

Suppose one interprets the adjectives "autological" and "heterological" as follows:
# An adjective is ' (sometimes ') if and only if it describes itself. For example "short" is autological, since the word "short" is short. "English," "unhyphenated" and "pentasyllabic" are also autological.
# An adjective is "" if and only if it does not describe itself. Hence "long" is a heterological word, as are "abbreviated" and "monosyllabic."

All adjectives, it would seem, must be either autological or heterological, for each adjective either describes itself, or it doesn't. The Grelling–Nelson paradox arises when we consider the adjective "heterological".To test if the (imaginary) word "'foo" is autological one can ask: Is "foo" a foo word? If the answer is 'yes', "foo" is autological. If the answer is 'no', "foo" is heterological.

By comparison, one can ask: Is "heterological" a heterological word? If the answer is 'yes', "heterological" is autological (leading to a contradiction). If the answer is 'no', "heterological" is heterological (again leading to a contradiction).

But, then, we cannot say what is logical is not logical, and so on.

The paradox can be eliminated, without changing the meaning of "heterological" where it was previously well-defined, by modifying the definition of "heterological" slightly to hold of all nonautological words except "heterological." But "nonautological" is subject to the same paradox, for which this evasion is not applicable because the rules of English uniquely determine its meaning from that of "autological." A similar slight modification to the definition of "autological" (such as declaring it false of "nonautological" and its synonyms) might seem to fix that, but the paradox still obtains for synonyms of "autological" and "heterological" such as "selfdescriptive" and "nonselfdescriptive," whose meanings also would need adjusting, and the consequences of those adjustments would then need to be pursued, and so on. Freeing English of the Grelling–Nelson paradox entails considerably more modification to the language than mere refinements of the definitions of "autological" and "heterological," which need not even be in the language for the paradox to arise. The scope of these obstacles for English is comparable to that of Russell's paradox for mathematics founded on sets, argued as follows.

Is "Autological" autological?

One may also ask if "autological" is autological.It can be chosen consistently to be either:
* if we say that "autological" is autological, and then ask if it applies to itself, then yes, it does, and thus is autological;
* if we say that "autological" is not autological, and then ask if it applies to itself, then no, it does not, and thus is not autological.

This is the opposite of the situation for heterological: while "heterological" logically cannot be autological or heterological, "autological" can be either. (It cannot be both, as the category of autological and heterological cannot overlap.)

In logical terms, the situation for "autological" is::"autological" is autological if and only if "autological" is autological:A if and only if A, a tautologywhile the situation for "heterological" is::"heterological" is autological if and only if "heterological" is heterological:A if and only if not A, a contradiction.

imilarities with Russell's paradox

The Grelling–Nelson paradox can be translated into Bertrand Russell's famous paradox in the following way. First one must identify each adjective with the set of objects to which that adjective applies. So, for example, the adjective "red" is equated with the set of all red objects. In this way, the adjective "pronounceable" is equated with the set of all pronounceable things, one of which is the word "pronounceable" itself. Thus, an autological word is understood as a set, "one of whose elements is the set itself". The question of whether the word "heterological" is heterological becomes the question of whether the set of all sets not containing themselves contains itself as an element.

See also

* List of autological words
* Metamagical Themas

External links

* [http://www.segerman.org/autological.html Autological words]


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Нужна курсовая?

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Paradox — For other uses, see Paradox (disambiguation). Further information: List of paradoxes A paradox is a seemingly true statement or group of statements that lead to a contradiction or a situation which seems to defy logic or intuition. Typically,… …   Wikipedia

  • Paradox — Ein Paradoxon oder Paradox (altgriechisch παράδοξον, von παρα , para – gegen und δόξα, dóxa – Meinung, Ansicht), auch Paradoxie (παραδοξία) und in der Mehrzahl Paradoxa g …   Deutsch Wikipedia

  • Kurt Grelling — Infobox Philosopher region = Western Philosophy era = 20th century philosophy color = #B0C4DE name = Otto Neurath birth = birth date|1886|03|02 death = death date|1942|09| school tradition = Analytic main interests = Philosophy of science, Logic… …   Wikipedia

  • Russell's paradox — Part of the foundations of mathematics, Russell s paradox (also known as Russell s antinomy), discovered by Bertrand Russell in 1901, showed that the naive set theory of Frege leads to a contradiction.It might be assumed that, for any formal… …   Wikipedia

  • Leonard Nelson — (July 11, 1882, Berlin October 29, 1927, Göttingen) was a German mathematician and philosopher. He was part of the Neo Friesian School and a friend of the mathematician David Hilbert, and devised the logical paradox which bears his name with Kurt …   Wikipedia

  • Interesting number paradox — The interesting number paradox is a semi humorous paradox that arises from attempting to classify numbers as interesting or dull . The paradox states that all numbers are interesting. The proof is by contradiction: if there were uninteresting… …   Wikipedia

  • Richard's paradox — is a fallacious paradox of mathematical mapping first described by the French mathematician Jules Richard in 1905. Today, it is ordinarily used in order to show the importance of carefully distinguishing between mathematics and metamathematics.… …   Wikipedia

  • Russell Paradox — Die Russellsche Antinomie ist ein von Bertrand Russell und Ernst Zermelo entdecktes Paradoxon der Naiven Mengenlehre, das Russell 1903 publizierte und daher seinen Namen trägt. Inhaltsverzeichnis 1 Begriff und Problematik 2 Geschichte und… …   Deutsch Wikipedia

  • Russells Paradox — Die Russellsche Antinomie ist ein von Bertrand Russell und Ernst Zermelo entdecktes Paradoxon der Naiven Mengenlehre, das Russell 1903 publizierte und daher seinen Namen trägt. Inhaltsverzeichnis 1 Begriff und Problematik 2 Geschichte und… …   Deutsch Wikipedia

  • Russellsches Paradox — Die Russellsche Antinomie ist ein von Bertrand Russell und Ernst Zermelo entdecktes Paradoxon der Naiven Mengenlehre, das Russell 1903 publizierte und daher seinen Namen trägt. Inhaltsverzeichnis 1 Begriff und Problematik 2 Geschichte und… …   Deutsch Wikipedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”