- Effective results in number theory
For historical reasons and in order to have application to the solution of
Diophantine equation s, results innumber theory have been scrutinised more than in other branches ofmathematics to see if their content iseffectively computable . Where it is asserted that some list of integers is finite, the question is whether in principle the list could be printed out after a machine computation.Littlewood's result
An early example of an ineffective result was
J. E. Littlewood 's theorem of 1914, that in theprime number theorem the differences of both ψ("x") and π("x") with their asymptotic estimates change sign infinitely often. [ [http://math.stanford.edu/~feferman/papers/unwind.pdf] , p.9.] Until the result on theSkewes number of 1933, these results were believed by some experts to be intrinsically ineffective.In more detail, writing for a numerical sequence "f"("n"), an "effective" result about its changing sign infinitely often would be a theorem including, for every value of "N", a value "M" > "N" such that "f"("N") and "f"("M") have different signs, and such that "M" could be computed with specified resources. In practical terms, "M" would be computed by taking values of "n" from "N" onwards, and the question is 'how far must you go?' A special case is to find the first sign change. The interest of the question was that the numerical evidence known showed no change of sign: Littlewood's result guaranteed that this evidence was just a small number effect, but 'small' here included values of "n" up to a billion.
The requirement of computability reflects on and contrasts with the approach used in
analytic number theory to prove the results. It for example brings into question any use ofLandau notation and its implied constants: are assertions pureexistence theorem s for such constants, or can one recover a version in which 1000 (say) takes the place of the implied constant? In other words if it were known that there was "M" > "N" with a change of sign and such that:"M" = O("G"("N"))
for some explicit function "G", say built up from powers, logarithms and exponentials, that means only
:"M" < "A"."G"("N")
for some absolute constant "A". The value of "A", the so-called "implied constant", may also need to be made explicit, for computational purposes. One reason Landau notation was a popular introduction is that it hides exactly what "A" is. In some indirect forms of proof it may not be at all obvious that the implied constant can be made explicit.
The 'Siegel period'
Many of the principal results of analytic number theory that were proved in the period 1900-1950 were in fact ineffective. The main examples were:
*The
Thue-Siegel-Roth theorem
*Siegel's theorem on integral points , from 1929
*The 1934 theorem ofHans Heilbronn andEdward Linfoot on theclass number 1 problem [H. Heilbronn, E. Linfoot, On the imaginary quadratic corpora of class-number one. Quart. J. Math. Oxford Ser. 5 (1934), pp. 293-301.]
*The 1935 result on theSiegel zero [The EoM article [http://eom.springer.de/D/d032890.htm] comments on the ineffectiveness of the bound.]
* TheSiegel-Walfisz theorem based on the Siegel zero.The concrete information that was left theoretically incomplete included lower bounds for class numbers (
ideal class group s for some families of number fields grow); and bounds for the best rational approximations toalgebraic number s in terms ofdenominator s. These latter could be read quite directly as results on Diophantine equations, after the work ofAxel Thue . The result used forLiouville number s in the proof is effective in the way it applies themean value theorem : but improvements (to what is now the Thue-Siegel-Roth theorem) were not.Later work
Later results, particularly of
Alan Baker , changed the position. Weaker theorems, qualitatively speaking, but with explicit constants, can actually be applied, in conjunction with machine computation, to prove that lists of solutions (suspected to be complete) are actually the entire solution set.Theoretical issues
The difficulties here were met by radically different proof techniques, taking much more care about proofs by contradiction. The logic involved is closer to
proof theory than to that ofcomputability theory andcomputable function s. It is rather loosely conjectured that the difficulties may lie in the realm ofcomputational complexity theory . Ineffective results are still being proved in the shape A "or" B, where we have no way of telling which.Notes
External links
*springer|first=V.G.|last= Sprindzhuk
id=d/d032590|title=Diophantine approximation
Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.