Dickinson S. Miller

Dickinson S. Miller

Dickinson S. Miller (October 7, 1868–November 13, 1963) worked with many world-renowned philosophers, including William James, George Santayana, John Dewey, Edmund Husserl, and Ludwig Wittgenstein.[1]

Contents

Biography

Miller received the A.B. degree in 1889 under George Fullerton at the University of Pennsylvania. He studied psychology under G. Stanley Hall at Clark University for a year, and then went to Harvard where he was a graduate student under William James, G. H. Palmer, Josiah Royce, and Santayana. He received the A.M. from Harvard in 1892.[2]

He then spent a year in Germany studying at Berlin and Halle under Max Dessoir, Hermann Ebbinghaus, and Friedrich Paulsen, earning his Ph.D. with a dissertation on Das Wesen der Erkenntnis und das Irrthums, which was published as "The Meaning of Truth and Error" in The Philosophical Review in 1893.[3]

This article led James to abandon Royce's solution of the knowledge problem in terms of an absolute mind. James recommended Miller to a post at Bryn Mawr College in 1893, where he was a close friend of Woodrow Wilson.[4]

In 1899, Miller became a strong critic of James's famous arguments in The Will to Believe that the beneficial effects of a belief somehow increased its "truth." His critical article was "The Will to Believe and the Duty to Doubt."[5]

Miller left Bryn Mawr that year to become an instructor of philosophy at Harvard, where he had a strong and productive collaboration with James.[6] James referred to Miller as "my most penetrating critic and intimate enemy." [7]

In 1904, Miller left Harvard to be a lecturer in philosophy at Columbia and professor in 1911. There he worked with Arthur O. Lovejoy and John Dewey.[8]

Miller retired from academic work after two years at Smith College (1926-26) and went into a "European retirement." [9] He visited Rome at first and then alternated between Florence and Vienna, where he made contact with the "Vienna Circle" of philosophers, including Moritz Schlick, Otto Neurath, Rudolf Carnap, Herbert Feigl, and others.

Miller challenged a basic principle of the Circle that "no sentence can be admitted to philosophical thought as having a meaning unless it is verifiable in experience." Such a principle, he argued "cuts the ground from under its own feet" because a sentence has to already have meaning before you can apply the test.[10]

In Vienna he met with Ludwig Wittgenstein who was then loosely associated with the Vienna Circle.

Free will as involving determination

In 1934, as Miller left to return for America, he published a landmark article in Mind under the pseudonym R. E. Hobart,[11] one that has led to a great deal of confusion in the relationship between free will and determinism.

He analyzed the relationship between "could" and "can" in the sense of choosing to do otherwise in the same circumstances and he claimed that the controversy of free will versus determinism was a waste of energy over a false antithesis. At least some determinism is not a problem for free will but a feature.[12]

The article was titled "Free Will as Involving Determination and Inconceivable Without It," but it is widely misquoted as "Involving Determinism." His biographer, Loyd Easton, mistakenly describes it as "an acute example of 'soft determinism' or 'reconciliationism'."[13]

The problem of "determinism" versus free will that William James was concerned about was the strict causal determines that is better called predeterminism where every event is determined in a causal chain back to the beginning of time, and there is "but one possible future," as James put it.[14]

Far from "reconciling" free will with this kind of determinism, as David Hume said that he had done in his "reconciling project,",[15] James proposed the first two-stage model of free will that denies predeterminism and accepts absolute chance as necessary for the generation of alternative possibilities, which are the source of "ambiguous futures" selected by the determination, but not predetermination, of the will.

A careful reading of Miller/Hobart shows that he is much closer to James's new idea about free will than to Hume's reconciling compatibilism.[16]

The Mind article

Writing about six years after the discovery of quantum indeterminacy, Hobart explicitly does not endorse strict logical or physical determinism, and he explicitly does endorse the existence of alternative possibilities, which can depend on absolute chance. He concludes that we can do otherwise in the same circumstances.

He says:

I am not maintaining that determinism is true...it is not here affirmed that there are no small exceptions, no slight undetermined swervings, no ingredient of absolute chance.[17]

"We say," I can will this or I can will that, whichever I choose ". Two courses of action present themselves to my mind. I think of their consequences, I look on this picture and on that, one of them commends itself more than the other, and I will an act that brings it about. I knew that I could choose either. That means that I had the power to choose either.[18]

Here Hobart seems to agree with William James that there are ambiguous futures. One could parse the previous paragraph as supporting the two-stage model of free will - first "free" courses of action present themselves, then an adequately determined "will" chooses between them, in a temporal sequence.

Note that Hobart sees clearly that courses of action present themselves - our thoughts "come to us" - and the will brings the act about - our actions "come from us."

Hobart refers to G. E. Moore's idea that one could have done otherwise - "if" one had chosen otherwise. But Hobart seems convinced that we have that real power.

Thus it is true, after the act of will, that I could have willed otherwise. It is most natural to add, "if I had wanted to"; but the addition is not required. The point is the meaning of "could". I could have willed whichever way I pleased. I had the power to will otherwise, there was nothing to prevent my doing so, and I should have done so if I had wanted.[19]

Hobart finds fault with the indeterminist's position, but he gives the typical overstatement by a determinist critic, that any chance will be the direct cause of our actions, which of course would clearly be a loss of freedom and responsibility

Indeterminism maintains that we need not be impelled to action by our wishes, that our active will need not be determined by them. Motives "incline without necessitating". We choose amongst the ideas of action before us, but need not choose solely according to the attraction of desire, in however wide a sense that word is used. Our inmost self may rise up in its autonomy and moral dignity, independently of motives, and register its sovereign decree.

Now, in so far as this "interposition of the self" is undetermined, the act is not its act, it does not issue from any concrete continuing self; it is born at the moment, of nothing, hence it expresses no quality; it bursts into being from no source. (p.6)

In proportion as an act of volition starts of itself without cause it is exactly, so far as the freedom of the individual is concerned, as if it had been thrown into his mind from without — "suggested" to him — by a freakish demon. It is exactly like it in this respect, that in neither case does the volition arise from what the man is, cares for or feels allegiance to; it does not come out of him. In proportion as it is undetermined, it is just as if his legs should suddenly spring up and carry him off where he did not prefer to go. Far from constituting freedom, that would mean, in the exact measure in which it took place, the loss of freedom.[20]

It is very likely that Hobart has William James in mind as "the indeterminist." If so, despite knowing James very well, he is mistaken about James's position. James would not have denied that our will is an act of determination, consistent with, and in some sense "caused by" our character and values, our habits, and our current feelings and desires. He simply wanted chance to provide alternative possibilities for actions and a break in the causal chain of strict determinism.

Since Hobart accepts alternative possibilities, It is arguable that his analysis is actually consistent with Jamesian free will, properly understood. His title includes "determination," not determinism. And he sincerely believes we make free, determining choices:

In daily life we are all determinists, just as we are all libertarians. We are constantly attributing behaviour to the character, the temperament, the peculiarities of the person and expecting him to behave in certain fashions. The very words of our daily converse, as we have so amply observed, are full of determinism. And we see nothing inconsistent in being aware at the same time that he is free in choosing his course, as we know ourselves to be.[21]

References

  1. ^ Loyd Easton, Dickinson Miller: Philosophical Analysis and Human Welfare", Reidel, 1975
  2. ^ Loyd Easton, Dickinson Miller: Philosophical Analysis and Human Welfare", p.1
  3. ^ Easton, p.2
  4. ^ Easton, p.2
  5. ^ Ralph Barton Perry, The Thought and Character of William James, vol. 2, p.240
  6. ^ Easton, p.5
  7. ^ "R. E. Hobart" on Information Philosopher
  8. ^ Easton, p.8
  9. ^ Easton, p.21
  10. ^ Easton, p.22
  11. ^ R. E. Hobart, Free Will as Involving Determination and Inconceivable Without It" Mind, Vol XLIII, No. 169, p.2
  12. ^ Easton, p.23
  13. ^ Easton, p.23
  14. ^ James, William. 1884. The Dilemma of Determinisn, Unitarian Review, vol.XXII, p.193. Reprinted in The Will to Believe, Dover Publications, 1956, p.145
  15. ^ David Hume, An Enquiry concerning Human Uderstanding, VIII, 1, §72
  16. ^ Bob Doyle, "Jamesian Free Will: The Two-Stage Model of William James," William James Studies, April 2010
  17. ^ Mind, Vol XLIII, No. 169, January, 1934, p.2
  18. ^ Mind, p.8
  19. ^ Mind,p.9
  20. ^ Mind, p.7
  21. ^ Mind, p.21

External links


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Поможем написать реферат

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Dickinson Dees — Headquarters Newcastle upon Tyne No. of offices 5 in UK and 1 affiliated office in Brussels …   Wikipedia

  • Miller Barber — Personal information Nickname Mr. X Born March 31, 1931 (1931 03 31) (age 80) Shreveport, Louisiana …   Wikipedia

  • Dickinson Memorial Library and Park — U.S. National Register of Historic Places …   Wikipedia

  • Dickinson v. United States — Supreme Court of the United States Argued October 21, 1953 Decided Novembe …   Wikipedia

  • Dickinson —   [ dɪkɪnsn], Emily Elizabeth, amerikanische Lyrikerin, * Amherst (Massachusetts) 10. 12. 1830, ✝ ebenda 15. 5. 1886; schrieb, zurückgezogen in Amherst lebend, insgesamt 1 775 Gedichte, die ihr Anerkennung als eine der bedeutendsten… …   Universal-Lexikon

  • Dickinson, Emily — ▪ American poet Introduction in full  Emily Elizabeth Dickinson  born Dec. 10, 1830, Amherst, Mass., U.S. died May 15, 1886, Amherst       American lyric poet who lived in seclusion and commanded a singular brilliance of style and integrity of… …   Universalium

  • Dickinson College — Université Dickinson Devise Pietate et doctrina tuta libertas (Religion et étude, le rempart de la liberté) Nom original Dickinson College Inform …   Wikipédia en Français

  • Dickinson Electronic Archives — The Dickinson Electronic Archives (DEA) is a website devoted to the study of Emily Dickinson, her writing practices, writings directly influencing her work, and critical and creative writings generated by her work. The DEA is produced by the… …   Wikipedia

  • Dickinson State University — Established 1918[1][2] Type Public Endowment $8.9 million …   Wikipedia

  • Miller Gallery at Carnegie Mellon University — Coordinates: 40°26′38″N 79°56′36″W / 40.4439°N 79.9432°W / 40.4439; 79.9432 …   Wikipedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”