Epistemic possibility

Epistemic possibility

In philosophy and modal logic, epistemic possibility relates a statement under consideration to the current state of our knowledge about the actual world: a statement is said to be "epistemically possible" if it "may be true, for all we know", "epistemically necessary" if it is "certain" (or "must be the case, given what we know"), and "epistemically impossible" if it "cannot be true, given what we know". Epistemic possibility is often contrasted with subjunctive possibility (or alethic possibility), and it is important to note that although epistemic and subjunctive possibilities are often expressed using the same modal terms (such as "possibly", "could be", "must be") or similar modal terms that are sometimes confused (such as "may be" and "might be"), statements that are qualified in terms of epistemic possibility and statements that are qualified in terms of subjunctive possibility have importantly different meanings.

The contrast is best explained by example. Consider the two statements:

# Hitler "might have been" victorious in World War II
# Hitler "may have been" victorious in World War II

Although these two statements are often confused with one another, they mean two different things: the first says something "true" about the vagaries of war (if determinism is false, anyway); the second says something that is certainly "false". The difference comes from the fact that the first statement—a statement of "subjunctive" possibility—says something about how things "might have been" under counterfactual conditions, whereas the second—a statement of "epistemic" possibility—says something about the relation between a particular outcome (a victory by Hitler) and "our knowledge about the actual world" (since, as it happens, we know perfectly well that that particular outcome did "not" actually obtain, we know that what it says is false).

The parallel distinction arises between types of conditionals (if-then statements). Consider the difference between the epistemic connection expressed by an indicative conditional and the causal or metaphysical relation expressed by a subjunctive conditional:

# If Oswald didn't shoot Kennedy, someone else did
# If Oswald hadn't shot Kennedy, someone else would have

The first statement says something that is certainly true, and will be accepted as such by anyone who is convinced that somebody shot Kennedy. It's clearly true because it expresses this epistemic relation between its antecedent (the "if"-clause) and its consequent (the "then"-clause): The antecedent, if we came to know it was true, would provide us with excellent evidence that the consequent is true. The second statement, on the other hand, expresses a causal or metaphysical relation: It says that the world was set up so that the consequent would have been made true if the antecedent were true. One will accept that second statement to the extent that one thinks the world was set up in that way. (Conspiracy theorists who think there was a back-up shooter, for instance, may accept the second statement.)

Because of these differences, epistemic possibility bears on the actual world in ways that subjunctive possibility does not. Suppose, for example, that I want to know whether or not to take an umbrella before I leave. If you tell me "It's "possible that" it is raining outside"—in the sense of epistemic possibility—then that would weigh on whether or not I take the umbrella. But if you just tell me that "It's "possible for" it to rain outside"—in the sense of "metaphysical possibility"—then I am no better off for this bit of modal enlightenment.

Further reading

* Alan R. White, "Modal Thinking" (ISBN 0-631-16560-6), chapter 1. White discusses subjunctive possibility as "the actuality of a possibility" and epistemic possibility as "the possibility of an actuality"
* Keith DeRose, "Epistemic Possibilities," "The Philosophical Review" 100 (1991): pp. 581–605.
* David Chalmers, [http://consc.net/papers/content.html The Components of Content] and [http://consc.net/papers/tyranny.html The Tyranny of the Subjunctive]


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Поможем решить контрольную работу

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Epistemic modality — is a sub type of linguistic modality that deals with a speaker s evaluation/judgment of, degree of confidence in, or belief of the knowledge upon which a proposition is based. In other words, epistemic modality refers to the way speakers… …   Wikipedia

  • Epistemic modal logic — is a subfield of modal logic that is concerned with reasoning about knowledge. While epistemology has a long philosophical tradition dating back to Ancient Greece, epistemic logic is a much more recent development with applications in many fields …   Wikipedia

  • Epistemic logic — is a subfield of modal logic that is concerned with reasoning about knowledge. While epistemology has a long philosophical tradition dating back to Ancient Greece, epistemic logic is a much more recent development with applications in many fields …   Wikipedia

  • Subjunctive possibility — (also called alethic possibility or metaphysical possibility) is the form of modality most frequently studied in modal logic. Subjunctive possibilities are the sorts of possibilities we consider when we conceive of counterfactual situations;… …   Wikipedia

  • justification, epistemic —    One is epistemically justified in holding a belief if one cannot be blamed for holding it, even if it turns out to be false. Common suggestions for what epistemic justification entails include possessing adequate evidence and being able to… …   Christian Philosophy

  • Modal logic — is a type of formal logic that extends classical propositional and predicate logic to include operators expressing modality. Modals words that express modalities qualify a statement. For example, the statement John is happy might be qualified by… …   Wikipedia

  • Modal verb — A modal verb (also modal, modal auxiliary verb, modal auxiliary) is a type of auxiliary verb that is used to indicate modality that is, likelihood, ability, permission, and obligation.[1]:p.33 The use of auxiliary verbs to express modality is… …   Wikipedia

  • List of philosophy topics (D-H) — DDaDai Zhen Pierre d Ailly Jean Le Rond d Alembert John Damascene Damascius John of Damascus Peter Damian Danish philosophy Dante Alighieri Arthur Danto Arthur C. Danto Arthur Coleman Danto dao Daodejing Daoism Daoist philosophy Charles Darwin… …   Wikipedia

  • Counterpart theory — In philosophy, specifically in the area of modal metaphysics, counterpart theory is an alternative to standard (Kripkean) possible worlds semantics for interpreting quantified modal logic. Counterpart theory still presupposes possible worlds, but …   Wikipedia

  • Keith DeRose — (born April 24, 1962) is an American philosopher currently teaching at Yale University in New Haven, Connecticut. His primary interests include epistemology, philosophy of language and history of modern philosophy. He is best known for his work… …   Wikipedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”